Evolutionary Theory of the Origin
of Religion. Facts misunderstood suggest ghosts,
which develop into gods. This process lies behind
history and experience. Difficulties of the Theory.
The Theory of Lucretius. Objections Mr. Tyler’s
Theory. The question of abnormal facts not discussed
by Mr. Tylor. Possibility that such ‘psychical’
facts are real, and are elements in development of
savage religion. The evidence for psychical phenomena
compared with that which, in other matters, satisfies
anthropologists. Examples. Conclusion.
Among the many hypotheses as to the
origin of religion, that which we may call the evolutionary,
or anthropological, is most congenial to modern habits
of thought. The old belief in a sudden, miraculous
revelation is commonly rejected, though, in one sense,
religion was none the less ‘revealed,’
even if man was obliged to work his way to the conception
of deity by degrees. To attain that conception
was the necessary result of man’s reflection
on the sum of his relations to the universe.
The attainment, however, of the monotheistic idea
is not now generally regarded as immediate and instinctive.
A slow advance, a prolonged evolution was required,
whether we accept Mr. Max Muller’s theory of
‘the sense of the Infinite,’ or whether
we prefer the anthropological hypothesis. The
latter scheme, with various modifications, is the
scheme of Epicurus, Lucretius, Hume, Mr. Tylor, and
Mr. Herbert Spencer. Man half consciously transferred
his implicit sense that he was a living and rational
being to nature in general, and recognised that earth,
sky, wind, clouds, trees, the lower animals, and so
on, were persons like himself, persons perhaps more
powerful and awful than himself. This transference
of personality can scarcely be called the result of
a conscious process of reasoning. Man might
recognise personality everywhere, without much more
thought or argument than a kitten exerts when it takes
a cork or a ball for a living playmate. But
consciousness must have reached a more explicit stage,
when man began to ask himself what a person
is, what life is, and when he arrived at the conclusion
that life is a spirit. To advance from that
conclusion; to explain all life as the manifestation
of indwelling spirits; then to withdraw the conception
of life and personality from inanimate things, to
select from among spirits One more powerful than the
rest, to recognise that One as disembodied, as superior,
then as supreme, then as unique, and so to attain the
monotheistic conception, has been, according to the
evolutionary hypothesis, the tendency of human thought.
Unluckily we cannot study the process
in its course of action. Perhaps there is no
savage race so lowly endowed, that it does not possess,
in addition to a world of ‘spirits,’ something
that answers to the conception of God. Whether
that is so, or not, is a question of evidence.
We have often been told that this or the other people
‘has no religious ideas at all’.
But later we hear that they do possess a belief in
spirits, and very often better information proves
that, in one stage or other of advance or degradation,
the theistic conception of a Maker and Judge of the
world is also present. Meanwhile even civilised
and monotheistic peoples also admit the existence
of a world of spirits of the dead, of ‘demons’
(as in Platonism), of saints (as in Catholicism), of
devils, of angels, or of subordinate deities.
Thus the elements of religion are universally distributed
in all degrees of culture, though one element is more
conspicuous in one place or mood, another more conspicuous
in another. In one mood the savage, or the civilised
man, may be called monotheistic, in another mood atheistic,
in a third, practically polytheistic. Only a
few men anywhere, and they only when consciously engaged
in speculation, assume a really definite and exclusive
mental attitude on the subject. The orthodox
monotheistic Mussulman has his afreets, and djinns;
the Jew, or the Christian, has his angels, the Catholic
has his saints; the Platonist has his demons; Superstition
has its ghosts. The question is whether all
these spiritual beings are only ghosts raised to higher
powers: or (in the case of deity), to the highest
conceivable power, while, even when this last process
has been accomplished, we ask whether other ghosts,
on lower grades, continue to be recognised.
Meanwhile the whole anthropological hypothesis, whether
valid or invalid, lies behind history, behind the experience
of even the most backward races at present extant.
If it be urged, as by Hume, that the conception of
a supreme deity is only a reflection of kingship in
human society, we must observe that some monarchical
races, like the Aztecs, seem to have possessed no
recognised monarchical Zeus; while something very like
the monotheistic conception is found among races so
remote from the monarchical state of society as to
have no obvious distinctions of rank, like the Australian
blacks. Moreover the evidence, on such difficult
points, is obscure, and fluctuating, and capable of
various interpretation. Even among the most backward
peoples, the traceable shadow of a monotheistic idea
often seems to bear marks of degradation and disuse,
rather than of nascent development. There is
a God, but He is neglected, and tribal spirits receive
prayer and sacrifice. Just as in art there is
a point where we find it difficult to decide whether
an object is decadent, or archaic, so it is in the
study of religious conceptions.
These are a few among the inevitable
difficulties and obscurities which haunt the anthropological
or evolutionary theory of the origin of religion.
Other difficulties meet us at the very beginning.
The theory regards gods as merely ghosts or spirits,
raised to a higher, or to the highest power.
Mankind, according to the system, was inevitably
led, by the action of reason upon apparent facts, to
endow all things, from humanity itself to earth, sky,
rain, sea, fire, with conscious personality, life,
spirit; and these attributes were as gradually withdrawn
again, under stress of better knowledge, till only
man was left with a soul, and only the universe was
left with a God. The last scientific step, then,
it may be inferred, is to deprive the universe of
a God, and mankind of souls.
This step may be naturally taken by
those who conceive that the whole process of ghost
and god-making is based on a mere set of natural and
inevitable fallacies, and who decline to recognise
that these progressive fallacies (if fallacies they
are) may be steps on a divinely appointed road towards
truth; that He led us by a way that we knew not, and
a path we did not understand. Yet, of course,
it is plain that a conclusion may be correct, although
it was reached by erroneous processes. All scientific
verities have been attained in this manner, by a gradual
modification and improvement of inadequate working
hypotheses, by the slow substitution of correctness
for error. Thus monotheism and the doctrine of
the soul may be in no worse case than the Copernican
theory, or the theory of the circulation of the blood,
or the Darwinian theory; itself the successor of innumerable
savage guesses, conjectures of Empedocles, ideas of
Cuvier, of the elder Darwin, of Lamarck, and of Chambers.
At present, of course, the theistic
hypothesis, and the hypothesis of a soul, do not admit
of scientific verification. The difficulty is
to demonstrate that ‘mind’ may exist, and
work, apart from ‘matter’. But it
may conceivably become verifiable that the relations
of ‘mind’ and ‘matter’ are,
at all events, less obviously and immediately interdependent,
that will and judgment are less closely and exclusively
attached to physical organisms than modern science
has believed. Now, according to the anthropological
theory of the origin of religion, it was precisely
from the opposite of the scientific belief, it
was from the belief that consciousness and will may
be exerted apart from, at a distance from, the physical
organism, that the savage fallacies began,
which ended, ex hypothesi, in monotheism, and in the
doctrine of the soul. The savage, it is said,
started from normal facts, which he misinterpreted.
But suppose he started, not from normal facts alone,
but also from abnormal facts, from facts
which science does not yet recognise at all, then
it is possible that the conclusions of the savage,
though far too sweeping, and in parts undeniably erroneous,
are yet, to a certain extent, not mistaken. He
may have had ‘a sane spot in his mind,’
and a sane impulse may have led him into the right
direction. Man may have faculties which savages
recognise, and which physical science does not recognise.
Man may be surrounded by agencies which savages exaggerate,
and which science disregards altogether, and these
faculties and agencies may point to an element of
truth which is often cast aside as a survival of superstition,
as the ‘after-image’ of an illusion.
The lowest known stage, and, according
to the evolutionary hypothesis, the earliest stage
in religion, is the belief in the ghosts of the dead,
and in no other spiritual entities. Whether
this belief anywhere exists alone, and untempered by
higher creeds, is another question. These ghosts
are fed, propitiated, receive worship, and, to put
it briefly, the fittest ghosts survive, and become
gods. Meanwhile the conception of ghosts of the
dead is more or less consciously extended, so that
spirits who never were incarnate as men become credible
beings. They may inform inanimate objects, trees,
rivers, fire, clouds, earth, sky, the great natural
departments, and thence polytheism results. There
are political processes, the consolidation of a state,
for example, which help to blend these gods of various
different origins into a divine consistory.
One of these gods, it may be of sky, or air becomes
king, and reflection may gradually come to recognise
him not only as supreme, but as, theoretically, unique,
and thus Zeus, from a very limited monarchy, may rise
to solitary all-fatherhood. Yet Zeus may, originally,
have been only the ghost of a dead medicine-man who
was called ‘Sky,’ or he may have been the
departmental spirit who presided over the sky, or
he may have been sky conceived of as a personality,
or these different elements may have been mingled in
Zeus. But the whole conception of spirit, in
any case, was derived, it is argued, from the conception
of ghosts, and that conception may be traced to erroneous
savage interpretations of natural and normal facts.
If all this be valid, the idea of
God is derived from a savage fallacy, though, of course,
it does not follow that an idea is erroneous, because
it was attained by mistaken processes and from false
premises. That, however, is the inference which
many minds are inclined to draw from the evolutionary
hypothesis. But if the facts on which the savage
reasoned are, some of them, rare, abnormal, and not
scientifically accepted; if, in short, they are facts
demonstrative of unrecognised human faculties, if these
faculties raise a presumption that will, mind, and
organism are less closely interdependent than science
supposes, then the savage reasoning may contain an
important element of rejected truth. It may
even seem, at least, conceivable that certain factors
in the conception of ‘spirit’ were not
necessarily evolved as the anthropological hypothesis
conceives them to have been.
Science had scarcely begun her secular
conflict with religion when she discovered that the
battle must be fought on haunted ground on the field
of the ghosts of the dead. ’There are no
gods or only dei otiosi careless indolent
deities. There is nothing conscious that survives
death no soul that can exist apart from the fleshly
body.’ Such were the doctrines of Epicurus
and Lucretius but to these human nature opposed ‘facts’;
we see people said men long dead in our dreams
or even when awake: the Homeric Achilles beholding
Patroclus in a dream instantly infers that there verily
is a shadow an eidolon a shadowy consciousness
shadowy presence which outlasts the death of the
body. To this Epicurus and Lucretius reply
that the belief is caused by fallacious inferences
from facts these facts appearances beheld in sleep
or vision these spectral faces of the long dead
are caused by ’films peeled off from the surface
of objects which fly to and fro through the air
and do likewise frighten our minds when they present
themselves to us awake as well as in sleep
what time we behold strange shapes and “idols”
of the light-bereaved’ Lucretius expressly
advances this doctrine of ‘films’ (an application
of the Democritean theory of perception) ’that
we may not believe that souls break loose from Acheron
or that shades fly about among the living or that
any part of us is left behind after death’.
Believers in ghosts must have replied that they do
not see in sleep or awake ‘films’
representing a mouldering corpse as they ought to
do on the Lucretian hypothesis but the image or idolon
of a living face. Plutarch says that if philosophers
may laugh these long enduring ‘films’
from a body perhaps many ages deep in dust are laughable. However Lucretius is so wedded to his ‘films’
that he explains a purely fanciful being like a centaur
by a fortuitous combination of the film of a man with
the film of a horse. A ‘ghost’ then
is to the mind of Lucretius merely a casual persistent
film of a dead man composed of atoms very light which
can fly at inconceivable speed and are not arrested
by material obstacles. By parity of reasoning
no doubt if Pythagoras is seen at the same moment
in Thurii and Metapontum only a film of him is beheld
at one of these two places. The Democritean theory
of ordinary perception thus becomes the Lucretian
theory of dreams and ghosts. Not that Lucretius
denies the existence of a rational soul in living
men a portion of it may even leave the body
during sleep and only a spark may be left in the
embers of the physical organism. If even that
spark withdraws death follows and the soul no longer
warmly housed in the body ceases to exist. For
the ‘film’ (ghost) is not the soul and
the soul is not the film whereas savage philosophy
identifies the soul with the ghost. Even Lucretius
retains the savage conception of the soul as a thing
of rarer matter a thing partly separable from the
body but that thing is resolved for ever into its
elements on the death of the body. His imaginary
‘film’ on the other hand may apparently
endure for ages.
The Lucretian theory had, for Lucretius,
the advantages of being physical, and of dealing a
blow at the hated doctrine of a future life.
For the public it had the disadvantages of being incapable
of proof, of not explaining the facts, as conceived
to exist, and of being highly ridiculous, as Plutarch
observed. Much later philosophers explained
all apparitions as impressions of sense, recorded
on the brain, and so actively revived that they seemed
to have an objective existence. One or two stock
cases (Nicolai’s, and Mrs. A.’s), in which
people in a morbid condition, saw hallucinations
which they knew to be hallucinations, did, and do,
a great deal of duty. Mr. Sully has them, as
Hibbert and Brewster have them, engaged as protagonists.
Collective hallucinations, and the hallucinations
of the sane which coincide with the death, or other
crisis in the experience of the person who seemed to
be seen, were set down to imagination, ‘expectant
attention,’ imposture, mistaken identity, and
so forth.
Without dwelling on the causes, physical
or psychological, which have been said by Frazer of
Tiree (1707), Ferrier, Hibbert, Scott, and others,
to account for the hallucinations of the sane, for
‘ghosts,’ Mr. Tylor has ably erected his
theory of animism, or the belief in spirits.
Thinking savages, he says, ’were deeply impressed
by two groups of biological phenomena,’ by the
facts of living, dying, sleep, trance, waking and
disease. They asked: ‘What is the
difference between a living body and a dead one?’
They wanted to know the causes of sleep, trance and
death. They were also concerned to explain the
appearances of dead or absent human beings in dreams
and waking visions. Now it was plain that ‘life’
could go away, as it does in death, or seems to do
in dreamless sleep. Again, a phantasm of a living
man can go away and appear to waking or sleeping people
at a distance. The conclusion was reached by
savages that the phantasm which thus appears is identical
with the life which ‘goes away’ in sleep
or trance. Sometimes it returns, when the man
wakes, or escapes from his trance. Sometimes
it stays away, he dies, his body corrupts, but the
phantasm endures, and is occasionally seen in sleeping
or waking vision. The general result of savage
thought is that man’s life must be conceived
as a personal and rational entity, called his ‘soul,’
while it remains in his body, his ‘wraith,’
when it is beheld at a distance during his life, his
‘ghost,’ when it is observed after his
death. Many circumstances confirmed or illustrated
this savage hypothesis Breath remains with the body
during life, deserts it at death. Hence the
words spiritus, ‘spirit,’ [Greek], anima,
and, when the separable nature of the shadow is noticed,
hence come ‘shade,’ ‘umbra,’
[Greek], with analogues in many languages. The
hypothesis was also strengthened, by the great difficulty
which savages feel in discriminating between what
occurs in dreams, and what occurs to men awake.
Many civilised persons feel the same difficulty with
regard to hallucinations beheld by them when in bed,
asleep or awake they know not, on the dim border of
existence. Reflection on all these experiences
ended in the belief in spirits, in souls of the living,
in wraiths of the living, in ghosts of the dead, and,
finally, in God.
This theory is most cogently presented
by Mr. Tylor, and is confirmed by examples chosen
from his wide range of reading. But, among these
normal and natural facts, as of sleep, dream, breath,
life, dying, Mr. Tylor includes (not as facts, but
as examples of applied animistic theory) cases of
‘clairvoyance,’ apparitions of the dying
seen by the living at a distance, second sight, ghostly
disturbances of knocking and rapping, movements of
objects, and so forth. It is not a question
for Mr. Tylor whether clairvoyance ever occurs:
whether ‘death-bed wraiths’ have been
seen to an extent not explicable by the laws of chance,
whether disturbances and movements of objects not
to be accounted for by human agency are matters of
universal and often well-attested report. Into
the question of fact, Mr. Tylor explicitly declines
to enter; these things only concern him because they
have been commonly explained by the ‘animistic
hypothesis,’ that is, by the fancied action of
spirits. The animistic hypothesis, again, is
the result, naturally fallacious, of savage man’s
reasonings on life, death, sleep, dreams, trance,
breath, shadow and the other kindred biological phenomena.
Thus clairvoyance (on the animistic hypothesis) is
the flight of the conscious ‘spirit’ of
a living man across space or time; the ‘deathbed
wraith’ is the visible apparition of the newly-emancipated
‘spirit,’ and ‘spirits’ cause
the unexplained disturbances and movements of objects.
In fact it is certain that the animistic hypothesis
(though a mere fallacy) does colligate a great number
of facts very neatly, and has persisted from times
of low savagery to the present age of reason.
So here is a case of the savage origin and persistent
‘survival’ of a hypothesis, the
most potent hypothesis in the history of humanity.
From Mr. Tylor’s point of view,
his concern with the subject ceases here, it is not
his business to ascertain whether the abnormal facts
are facts or fancies. Yet, to other students,
this question is very important. First, if clairvoyance,
wraiths, and the other alleged phenomena, really do
occur, or have occurred, then savage man had much
better grounds for the animistic hypothesis than if
no such phenomena ever existed. For instance,
if a medicine-man not only went into trances, but
brought back from these expeditions knowledge otherwise
inaccessible, then there were better grounds for believing
in a consciousness exerted apart from the body than
if there were no evidence but that of non-veridical
dreams. If merely the dream-coincidences which
the laws of chance permit were observed, the belief
in the soul’s dream-flight would win less favourable
and general acceptance than it would if clairvoyance,
’the sleep of the shadow,’ were a real
if rare experience. The very name given by the
Eskimos to the hypnotic state, ‘the sleep of
the shadow,’ proves that savages do make distinctions
between normal and abnormal conditions of slumber.
In the same way a few genuine wraiths,
or ghosts, or ’veridical hallucinations,’
would be enough to start the animistic hypothesis,
or to confirm it notably, if it was already started.
As to disturbances and movements of objects unexplained,
these, in his own experience, suggested, even to De
Morgan, the hypothesis of a conscious, active, and
purposeful will, not that of any human being
present. Now such a will is hardly to be defined
otherwise than as ‘spiritual’. This
order of phenomena, like those of clairvoyance and
wraiths, might either give rise to the savage animistic
hypothesis, or, at least, might confirm it greatly.
In fact, if the sets of abnormal phenomena existed,
or were held to exist, savage man scarcely needed
the normal phenomena for the basis of his spiritual
belief. The normal phenomena lent him such terms
as ‘spirit,’ ‘shadow,’ but
much of his theory might have been built on the foundation
of the abnormal phenomena alone. A ’veridical
hallucination,’ of the dying would give him a
‘wraith’; a recognised hallucination of
the dead would give him a ghost: the often reported
and unexplained movements and disturbances would give
him a vui, ‘house spirit,’ ‘brownie,’
‘domovoy,’ follet, lar, or lutin.
Or these occurrences might suggest to the thinking
savage that some discontented influence survived from
the recently dead.
Four thousand years have passed since
houses were haunted in Egypt, and have left some sane,
educated, and methodical men to meet the same annoyances
as the ancient Egyptians did, by the same measures.
We do not pretend to discover, without examination,
the causes of the sounds and sights which baffle trained
and not superstitious investigators. But we
do say that similar occurrences, in a kraal or
an Eskimo hut, in a wigwam, in a cave, or under a gunyeh,
would greatly confirm the animistic hypothesis of
savages. The theory of imposture (in some cases)
does undeniably break down, for the people who hold
it cannot even suggest a modus operandi within the
reach of the human beings concerned, as in the case
of the Wesleys. The theory of contagious hallucination
of all the senses is the property of Coleridge alone.
The hypothesis of a nervous force which sets up centres
of conscious action is confined to Hartmann, and to
certain Highland philosophers, cavalierly dismissed
by the Rev. Robert Kirk as ‘men illiterate’.
Instead of making these guesses, the savage thinkers
merely applied the animistic hypothesis, which they
had found to work very well already, and, as De Morgan
says, to colligate the phenomena better than any other
theory. We cannot easily conceive men who know
neither sleep nor dreams, but if the normal phenomena
of sleep and dreams had not existed, the abnormal
phenomena already described, if they occurred, as they
are universally said to do, could have given rise,
when speculated upon, to the belief in spirits.
But, it may reasonably be urged, ’the
natural familiar facts of life, death, sleep, waking,
dreams, breath, and shadows, are all versae causae,
do undeniably exist, and, without the aid of any of
your abnormal facts, afford basis enough for the animistic
hypothesis. Moreover, after countless thousands
of years, during which superstition has muttered about
your abnormal facts, official science still declines
to hear a word on the topic of clairvoyance or telepathy.
You don’t find the Royal Society investigating
second sight, or attending to legends about tables
which rebel against the law of gravitation.’
These are cogent remarks. Normal
facts, perhaps, may have suggested the belief in spirits,
the animistic hypothesis. But we do not find
the hypothesis (among the backward races) where abnormal
facts are not alleged to be matters of comparatively
frequent experience. Consequently we do not know
that the normal facts, alone, suggested the existence
of spirits to early thinkers, we can only make the
statement on a priori grounds. Like George Eliot’s
rural sage we ‘think it sounds a deal likelier’.
But that, after all, though a taking, is not a powerful
and conclusive syllogism.
Again, we certainly do not expect
to see the Royal Society inquiring into second sight,
or clairvoyance, or thought transference. When
the Royal Society was first founded several of its
members, Pepys, F.R.S.; Mr. Robert Boyle, F.R.S.;
the Rev. Joseph Glanvill, F.R.S., went into these
things a good deal. But, in spite of their title,
they were only amateurs. They had no professional
dignity to keep up. They were well aware that
they, unlike the late Mr. Faraday, did not know, by
inspiration or by common-sense, the limits of the
possible. They tried all things, it was such
a superstitious age. Now men of science, or the
majority of them, for there are some exceptions, know
what is, and what is not possible. They know
that germs of life may possibly come down on meteorites
from somewhere else, and they produced an argument
for the existence of a bathybius. But they also
know that a man is not a bird to be in two places
at once, like Pythagoras, and that nobody can see through
a stone wall. These, and similar allegations,
they reckon impossible, and, if the facts happen,
so much the worse for the facts. They can only
be due to imposture or mal-observation, and there is
an end of the matter. This is the view of official
science. Unluckily, not many years ago, official
science was equally certain that the ordinary phenomena
of hypnotism were based on imposture and on mal-observation.
These phenomena, too, were tabooed. But so many
people could testify to them, and they could be so
easily explained by the suggestive force of suggestion,
that they were reluctantly admitted within the sacred
citadel. Many people, sane, not superstitious,
healthy, and even renowned as scientific specialists,
attest the existence of the still rarer phenomena which
are said, in certain cases, to accompany the now more
familiar incidents of hypnotism. But these phenomena
have never yet been explained by any theory which
science recognises, as she does recognise that suggestion
is suggestive. Therefore these rarer phenomena
manifestly do not exist, and cannot be the subject
of legitimate inquiry.
These are unanswerable observations,
and it is only the antiquarian who can venture, in
his humble way, to reply to them. His answer
has a certain force ad hominem, that is, as addressed
to anthropologists. They, too, have but recently
been admitted within the scientific fold; time was
when their facts were regarded as mere travellers’
tales. Mr. Max Muller is now, perhaps, almost
alone in his very low estimate of anthropological
evidence, and, possibly, even that sturdy champion
is beginning to yield ground. Defending the
validity of the testimony on which anthropologists
reason about the evolution of religion, custom, manners,
mythology, law, Mr. Tylor writes:
’It is a matter worthy of consideration
that the accounts of similar phenomena of culture,
recurring in different parts of the world, actually
supply incidental proof of their own authenticity.
. . . The test of recurrence comes in. . . .
The possibility of intentional or unintentional mystification
is often barred by such a state of things as that
a similar statement is made in two remote lands by
two witnesses, of whom A lived a century before B,
and B appears never to have heard of A.’
If for ‘similar phenomena of
culture’ here, we substitute ’similar
abnormal phenomena’ (such as clairvoyance, wraiths,
unexplained disturbances), Mr. Tylor’s argument
in favour of his evidence for institutions applies
equally well to our evidence for mysterious ‘facts’.
‘How distant are the countries,’ he goes
on, ’how wide apart are the dates, how different
the creeds and characters in the catalogue of the
facts of civilisation, needs no further showing’
to the student of Mr. Tylor’s erudite footnotes.
In place of ’facts of civilisation’ read
‘psychical phenomena,’ and Mr. Tylor’s
argument applies to the evidence for these rejected
and scouted beliefs.
The countries from which ‘ghosts’
and ‘wraiths’ and ‘clairvoyance’
are reported are ‘distant’; the dates are
‘wide apart’; the ’creeds and characters
of the observers’ ’are ‘different’;
yet the evidence is as uniform, and as recurrent,
as it is in the case of institutions, manners, customs.
Indeed the evidence for the rejected and abnormal
phenomena is even more ‘recurrent’ than
the evidence for customs and institutions. Polyandry,
totemism, human sacrifice, the taboo, are only reported
as existing in remote and semi-civilised countries.
Clairvoyance, wraiths, ghosts, mysterious disturbances
and movements of objects are reported as existing,
not only in distant ages, but today; not only among
savages or barbarians, but in London, Paris, Milan.
No ages can be more wide apart, few countries much
more distant, than ancient Egypt and modern England:
no characters look more different than that of an
old scribe under Pharaoh, and that of a distinguished
soldier under Queen Victoria. Yet the scribe
of Khemi and General Campbell suffer from the same
inexplicable annoyance, attribute it to the same very
abnormal agency, and attempt (not unsuccessfully) to
communicate with that agency, in precisely the same
way.
This though a striking is an isolated
and perhaps a casual example of recurrence and uniformity
in evidence. Mr. Tylor’s Primitive Culture
is itself a store-house of other examples to which
more may easily be added. For example there
is the old and savage belief in a ‘sending’.
The medicine-man or medium or witch can despatch
a conscious visible and intelligent agent non-normal
to do his bidding at a distance. This belief
is often illustrated in the Scandinavian sagas.
Rink testifies to it among the Eskimo Grinnell among
the Pawnees: Porphyry alleges that by some such
’telepathic impact’ Plotinus from a distance
made a hostile magician named Alexander ‘double
up like an empty bag’ and saw and reported this
agreeable circumstance. Hardly any abnormal
phenomenon or faculty sounds less plausible and the
‘spectral evidence’ for the presence of
a witch’s ‘sending’ when the poor
woman could establish an alibi for her visible self
appeared dubious even to Cotton Mather. But
in their Phantasms of the Living Messrs. Gurney and
Myers give cases in which a visible ‘sending’
was intentionally emitted by Baron Schrenck Notzing
by a stock-broker by a young student of engineering
and by a French hospital nurse to take no other instances.
The person visited frequently by the ‘sendings’
in the last cases was a French physician engaged in
the hospital who reports and attests the facts.
All the cases are given at first hand on the testimony
of the senders and of the recipients of the sendings.
Bulwer Lytton was familiar with the belief and uses
the ‘shining shadow’ in A Strange Story.
Now here is uniform recurrent evidence from widely
severed ages from distant countries from the Polar
North the American prairie Neoplatonic Egypt and
Greece England and New England of the seventeenth
century and England and Germany of today. The
‘creeds and characters of the observers’
are as ‘different’ as Neoplatonism Shamanism
Christianity of divers sects and probably Agnosticism
or indifference. All these conditions of unvarying
testimony constitute good evidence for institutions
and customs; anthropologists who eagerly accept such
testimony in their own studies may decide as to whether
they deserve total neglect when adduced in another
field of anthropology.
Turning from ‘sendings,’
or ‘telepathy’ voluntarily brought to bear
on one living person by another, we might examine ’death-bed
wraiths,’ or the telepathic impact ’if
that hypothesis of theirs be sound’ produced
by a dying on a living human being. A savage
example, in which a Fuegian native on board an English
ship saw his father, who was expiring in Tierra
del Fuego, has the respectable authority
of Mr. Darwin’s Cruise of the Beagle. Instances,
on the other hand, in which Australian blacks, or
Fijians, see the phantasms of dead kinsmen warning
them of their decease (which follows punctually) may
be found in Messrs. Fison and Howitt’s Kamilaroi
and Kurnai.
From New Zealand Mr. Tylor cites
with his authorities the following example:
’A party of Maoris (one of whom told the
story) were seated round a fire in the open air when
there appeared seen only by two of them the figure
of a relative left ill at home. They exclaimed
the figure vanished and on the return of the party
it appeared that the sick man had died about the time
of the vision.’ A traveller in New Zealand
illustrates the native belief in the death-wraith
by an amusing anecdote. A Rangatira or native
gentleman had gone on the war-path. One day
he walked into his wife’s house but after a
few moments could not be found. The military
expedition did not return so the lady taking it
for granted that her husband the owner of the wraith
was dead married an admirer. The hallucination
however was not ‘veridical’; the
warrior came home but he admitted that he had no
remedy and no feud against his successor. The
owner of a wraith which has been seen may be assumed
to be dead. Such is Maori belief. The
modern civilised examples of death-wraiths attested
and recorded in Phantasms of the Living are numerous;
but statistics prove that a lady who marries again
on the strength of a wraith may commit an error of
judgment and become liable to the penalty of bigamy.
The Maoris no statisticians take a more liberal
and tolerant view. These are comparatively scanty
examples from savage life but then they are corroborated
by the wealth of recurrent and coincident evidence
from civilised races ancient and modern.
On the point of clairvoyance, it is
unnecessary to dwell. The second-sighted man,
the seer of events remote in space or not yet accomplished
in time, is familiar everywhere, from the Hebrides
to the Coppermine River, from the Samoyed and Eskimo
to the Zulu, from the Euphrates to the Hague.
The noises heard in ‘haunted houses,’
the knocking, routing, dragging of heavy bodies, is
recorded, Mr. Tylor says, by Dayaks, Singhalese, Siamese,
and Esths; Dennys, in his Folklore of China, notes
the occurrences in the Celestial Empire; Grimm, in
his German Mythology, gives examples, starting from
the communicative knocks of a spirit near Bingen, in
the chronicle of Rudolf (856), and Suetonius tells
a similar tale from imperial Rome. The physician
of Catherine de Medicis, Ambroise Pare, describes
every one of the noises heard by the Wesleys, long
after his day, as familiar, and as caused by devils.
Recurrence and conformity of evidence cannot be found
in greater force.
The anthropological test of evidence
for faith in the rejected phenomena is thus amply
satisfied. Unless we say that these phenomena
are ‘impossible’ whereas totemism the
couvade cannibalism are possible the testimony
to belief in clairvoyance and the other peculiar
occurrences is as good in its way as the evidence
for the practice of wild customs and institutions.
There remains a last and notable circumstance.
All the abnormal phenomena in the modern and mediaeval
tales occur most frequently in the presence of convulsionaries
like the so-called victims of witches like the Hon.
Master Sandilands Lord Torphichen’s son (1720)
like the grandson of William Morse in New England (1680)
and like Bovet’s case of the demon of Spraiton.
The ‘mediums’ of modern
spiritualism, like Francis Fey, are, or pretend to
be, subject to fits, anæsthesia, jerks, convulsive
movements, and trance. As Mr. Tylor says about
his savage jossakeeds, powwows, Birraarks, peaimen,
everywhere ’these people suffer from hysterical,
convulsive, and epileptic affections’.
Thus the physical condition, all the world over, of
persons who exhibit most freely the accepted phenomena,
is identical. All the world over, too, the same
persons are credited with the rejected phenomena,
clairvoyance, ‘discerning of spirits,’
powers of voluntary ’telepathic ’and ‘telekinetic’
impact. Thus we find that uniform and recurrent
evidence vouches for a mass of phenomena which science
scouts. Science has now accepted a portion of
the mass, but still rejects the stranger occurrences.
Our argument is that their invariably alleged presence,
in attendance on the minor occurrences, is, at least,
a point worthy of examination. The undesigned
coincidences of testimony represent a great deal of
smoke, and proverbial wisdom suggests a presumption
in favour of a few sparks of fire. Now, if there
are such sparks, the animistic hypothesis may not,
of course, be valid, ’spirits’
may not exist, but the universal belief
in their existence may have had its origin, not in
normal facts only, but in abnormal facts. And
these facts, at the lowest estimate, must suggest
that man may have faculties, and be surrounded by
agencies, which physical science does not take into
account in its theory of the universe and of human
nature.
We have already argued that the doctrines
of theism and of the soul need not to be false, even
if they were arrived at slowly, after a succession
of grosser opinions. But if the doctrines were
reached by a process which started from real facts
of human nature, observed by savages, but not yet
recognised by physical science, then there may have
been grains of truth even in the cruder and earlier
ideas, and these grains of gold may have been disengaged,
and fashioned, not without Divine aid, into the sacred
things of spiritual religion.
The stories which we have been considering
are often trivial, sometimes comic; but they are universally
diffused, and as well established as universally coincident
testimony can establish anything. Now, if there
be but one spark of real fire to all this smoke, then
the purely materialistic theories of life and of the
world must be reconsidered. They seem very well
established, but so have many other theories seemed,
that are long gone the way of all things human.