A library may be very large; but if
it is in disorder, it is not so useful as one that
is small but well arranged. In the same way, a
man may have a great mass of knowledge, but if he
has not worked it up by thinking it over for himself,
it has much less value than a far smaller amount which
he has thoroughly pondered. For it is only when
a man looks at his knowledge from all sides, and combines
the things he knows by comparing truth with truth,
that he obtains a complete hold over it and gets it
into his power. A man cannot turn over anything
in his mind unless he knows it; he should, therefore,
learn something; but it is only when he has turned
it over that he can be said to know it.
Reading and learning are things that
anyone can do of his own free will; but not so thinking.
Thinking must be kindled, like a fire by a draught;
it must be sustained by some interest in the matter
in hand. This interest may be of purely objective
kind, or merely subjective. The latter comes
into play only in things that concern us personally.
Objective interest is confined to heads that think
by nature; to whom thinking is as natural as breathing;
and they are very rare. This is why most men
of learning show so little of it.
It is incredible what a different
effect is produced upon the mind by thinking for oneself,
as compared with reading. It carries on and intensifies
that original difference in the nature of two minds
which leads the one to think and the other to read.
What I mean is that reading forces alien thoughts
upon the mind thoughts which are as foreign
to the drift and temper in which it may be for the
moment, as the seal is to the wax on which it stamps
its imprint. The mind is thus entirely under
compulsion from without; it is driven to think this
or that, though for the moment it may not have the
slightest impulse or inclination to do so.
But when a man thinks for himself,
he follows the impulse of his own mind, which is determined
for him at the time, either by his environment or
some particular recollection. The visible world
of a man’s surroundings does not, as reading
does, impress a single definite thought upon
his mind, but merely gives the matter and occasion
which lead him to think what is appropriate to his
nature and present temper. So it is, that much
reading deprives the mind of all elasticity; it is
like keeping a spring continually under pressure.
The safest way of having no thoughts of one’s
own is to take up a book every moment one has nothing
else to do. It is this practice which explains
why erudition makes most men more stupid and silly
than they are by nature, and prevents their writings
obtaining any measure of success. They remain,
in Pope’s words:
For ever reading, never to be read!
Men of learning are those who have
done their reading in the pages of a book. Thinkers
and men of genius are those who have gone straight
to the book of Nature; it is they who have enlightened
the world and carried humanity further on its way.
If a man’s thoughts are to have truth and life
in them, they must, after all, be his own fundamental
thoughts; for these are the only ones that he can fully
and wholly understand. To read another’s
thoughts is like taking the leavings of a meal to
which we have not been invited, or putting on the clothes
which some unknown visitor has laid aside. The
thought we read is related to the thought which springs
up in ourselves, as the fossil-impress of some prehistoric
plant to a plant as it buds forth in spring-time.
Reading is nothing more than a substitute
for thought of one’s own. It means putting
the mind into leading-strings. The multitude of
books serves only to show how many false paths there
are, and how widely astray a man may wander if he
follows any of them. But he who is guided by
his genius, he who thinks for himself, who thinks
spontaneously and exactly, possesses the only compass
by which he can steer aright. A man should read
only when his own thoughts stagnate at their source,
which will happen often enough even with the best of
minds. On the other hand, to take up a book for
the purpose of scaring away one’s own original
thoughts is sin against the Holy Spirit. It is
like running away from Nature to look at a museum of
dried plants or gaze at a landscape in copperplate.
A man may have discovered some portion
of truth or wisdom, after spending a great deal of
time and trouble in thinking it over for himself and
adding thought to thought; and it may sometimes happen
that he could have found it all ready to hand in a
book and spared himself the trouble. But even
so, it is a hundred times more valuable if he has
acquired it by thinking it out for himself. For
it is only when we gain our knowledge in this way
that it enters as an integral part, a living member,
into the whole system of our thought; that it stands
in complete and firm relation with what we know; that
it is understood with all that underlies it and follows
from it; that it wears the color, the precise shade,
the distinguishing mark, of our own way of thinking;
that it comes exactly at the right time, just as we
felt the necessity for it; that it stands fast and
cannot be forgotten. This is the perfect application,
nay, the interpretation, of Goethe’s advice
to earn our inheritance for ourselves so that we may
really possess it:
Was due ererbt von deinen Vaelern hast,
Erwirb es, um es zu besitzen.
The man who thinks for himself, forms
his own opinions and learns the authorities for them
only later on, when they serve but to strengthen his
belief in them and in himself. But the book-philosopher
starts from the authorities. He reads other people’s
books, collects their opinions, and so forms a whole
for himself, which resembles an automaton made up
of anything but flesh and blood. Contrarily, he
who thinks for himself creates a work like a living
man as made by Nature. For the work comes into
being as a man does; the thinking mind is impregnated
from without, and it then forms and bears its child.
Truth that has been merely learned
is like an artificial limb, a false tooth, a waxen
nose; at best, like a nose made out of another’s
flesh; it adheres to us only because it is put on.
But truth acquired by thinking of our own is like
a natural limb; it alone really belongs to us.
This is the fundamental difference between the thinker
and the mere man of learning. The intellectual
attainments of a man who thinks for himself resemble
a fine painting, where the light and shade are correct,
the tone sustained, the color perfectly harmonized;
it is true to life. On the other hand, the intellectual
attainments of the mere man of learning are like a
large palette, full of all sorts of colors, which
at most are systematically arranged, but devoid of
harmony, connection and meaning.
Reading is thinking with some one
else’s head instead of one’s own.
To think with one’s own head is always to aim
at developing a coherent whole a system,
even though it be not a strictly complete one; and
nothing hinders this so much as too strong a current
of others’ thoughts, such as comes of continual
reading. These thoughts, springing every one
of them from different minds, belonging to different
systems, and tinged with different colors, never of
themselves flow together into an intellectual whole;
they never form a unity of knowledge, or insight,
or conviction; but, rather, fill the head with a Babylonian
confusion of tongues. The mind that is over-loaded
with alien thought is thus deprived of all clear insight,
and is well-nigh disorganized. This is a state
of things observable in many men of learning; and
it makes them inferior in sound sense, correct judgment
and practical tact, to many illiterate persons, who,
after obtaining a little knowledge from without, by
means of experience, intercourse with others, and
a small amount of reading, have always subordinated
it to, and embodied it with, their own thought.
The really scientific thinker
does the same thing as these illiterate persons, but
on a larger scale. Although he has need of much
knowledge, and so must read a great deal, his mind
is nevertheless strong enough to master it all, to
assimilate and incorporate it with the system of his
thoughts, and so to make it fit in with the organic
unity of his insight, which, though vast, is always
growing. And in the process, his own thought,
like the bass in an organ, always dominates everything
and is never drowned by other tones, as happens with
minds which are full of mere antiquarian lore; where
shreds of music, as it were, in every key, mingle confusedly,
and no fundamental note is heard at all.
Those who have spent their lives in
reading, and taken their wisdom from books, are like
people who have obtained precise information about
a country from the descriptions of many travellers.
Such people can tell a great deal about it; but, after
all, they have no connected, clear, and profound knowledge
of its real condition. But those who have spent
their lives in thinking, resemble the travellers themselves;
they alone really know what they are talking about;
they are acquainted with the actual state of affairs,
and are quite at home in the subject.
The thinker stands in the same relation
to the ordinary book-philosopher as an eye-witness
does to the historian; he speaks from direct knowledge
of his own. That is why all those who think for
themselves come, at bottom, to much the same conclusion.
The differences they present are due to their different
points of view; and when these do not affect the matter,
they all speak alike. They merely express the
result of their own objective perception of things.
There are many passages in my works which I have given
to the public only after some hesitation, because
of their paradoxical nature; and afterwards I have
experienced a pleasant surprise in finding the same
opinion recorded in the works of great men who lived
long ago.
The book-philosopher merely reports
what one person has said and another meant, or the
objections raised by a third, and so on. He compares
different opinions, ponders, criticises, and tries
to get at the truth of the matter; herein on a par
with the critical historian. For instance, he
will set out to inquire whether Leibnitz was not for
some time a follower of Spinoza, and questions of a
like nature. The curious student of such matters
may find conspicuous examples of what I mean in Herbart’s
Analytical Elucidation of Morality and Natural
Right, and in the same author’s Letters
on Freedom. Surprise may be felt that a man
of the kind should put himself to so much trouble;
for, on the face of it, if he would only examine the
matter for himself, he would speedily attain his object
by the exercise of a little thought. But there
is a small difficulty in the way. It does not
depend upon his own will. A man can always sit
down and read, but not think. It is
with thoughts as with men; they cannot always be summoned
at pleasure; we must wait for them to come. Thought
about a subject must appear of itself, by a happy
and harmonious combination of external stimulus with
mental temper and attention; and it is just that which
never seems to come to these people.
This truth may be illustrated by what
happens in the case of matters affecting our own personal
interest. When it is necessary to come to some
resolution in a matter of that kind, we cannot well
sit down at any given moment and think over the merits
of the case and make up our mind; for, if we try to
do so, we often find ourselves unable, at that particular
moment, to keep our mind fixed upon the subject; it
wanders off to other things. Aversion to the
matter in question is sometimes to blame for this.
In such a case we should not use force, but wait for
the proper frame of mind to come of itself. It
often comes unexpectedly and returns again and again;
and the variety of temper in which we approach it
at different moments puts the matter always in a fresh
light. It is this long process which is understood
by the term a ripe resolution. For the work
of coming to a resolution must be distributed; and
in the process much that is overlooked at one moment
occurs to us at another; and the repugnance vanishes
when we find, as we usually do, on a closer inspection,
that things are not so bad as they seemed.
This rule applies to the life of the
intellect as well as to matters of practice.
A man must wait for the right moment. Not even
the greatest mind is capable of thinking for itself
at all times. Hence a great mind does well to
spend its leisure in reading, which, as I have said,
is a substitute for thought; it brings stuff to the
mind by letting another person do the thinking; although
that is always done in a manner not our own.
Therefore, a man should not read too much, in order
that his mind may not become accustomed to the substitute
and thereby forget the reality; that it may not form
the habit of walking in well-worn paths; nor by following
an alien course of thought grow a stranger to its
own. Least of all should a man quite withdraw
his gaze from the real world for the mere sake of
reading; as the impulse and the temper which prompt
to thought of one’s own come far oftener from
the world of reality than from the world of books.
The real life that a man sees before him is the natural
subject of thought; and in its strength as the primary
element of existence, it can more easily than anything
else rouse and influence the thinking mind.
After these considerations, it will
not be matter for surprise that a man who thinks for
himself can easily be distinguished from the book-philosopher
by the very way in which he talks, by his marked earnestness,
and the originality, directness, and personal conviction
that stamp all his thoughts and expressions. The
book-philosopher, on the other hand, lets it be seen
that everything he has is second-hand; that his ideas
are like the number and trash of an old furniture-shop,
collected together from all quarters. Mentally,
he is dull and pointless a copy of a copy.
His literary style is made up of conventional, nay,
vulgar phrases, and terms that happen to be current;
in this respect much like a small State where all the
money that circulates is foreign, because it has no
coinage of its own.
Mere experience can as little as reading
supply the place of thought. It stands to thinking
in the same relation in which eating stands to digestion
and assimilation. When experience boasts that
to its discoveries alone is due the advancement of
the human race, it is as though the mouth were to
claim the whole credit of maintaining the body in
health.
The works of all truly capable minds
are distinguished by a character of decision
and definiteness, which means they are clear
and free from obscurity. A truly capable mind
always knows definitely and clearly what it is that
it wants to express, whether its medium is prose,
verse, or music. Other minds are not decisive
and not definite; and by this they may be known for
what they are.
The characteristic sign of a mind
of the highest order is that it always judges at first
hand. Everything it advances is the result of
thinking for itself; and this is everywhere evident
by the way in which it gives its thoughts utterance.
Such a mind is like a Prince. In the realm of
intellect its authority is imperial, whereas the authority
of minds of a lower order is delegated only; as may
be seen in their style, which has no independent stamp
of its own.
Every one who really thinks for himself
is so far like a monarch. His position is undelegated
and supreme. His judgments, like royal decrees,
spring from his own sovereign power and proceed directly
from himself. He acknowledges authority as little
as a monarch admits a command; he subscribes to nothing
but what he has himself authorized. The multitude
of common minds, laboring under all sorts of current
opinions, authorities, prejudices, is like the people,
which silently obeys the law and accepts orders from
above.
Those who are so zealous and eager
to settle debated questions by citing authorities,
are really glad when they are able to put the understanding
and the insight of others into the field in place of
their own, which are wanting. Their number is
legion. For, as Seneca says, there is no man
but prefers belief to the exercise of judgment unusquisque
mavult credere quam judicare. In their controversies
such people make a promiscuous use of the weapon of
authority, and strike out at one another with it.
If any one chances to become involved in such a contest,
he will do well not to try reason and argument as
a mode of defence; for against a weapon of that kind
these people are like Siegfrieds, with a skin
of horn, and dipped in the flood of incapacity for
thinking and judging. They will meet his attack
by bringing up their authorities as a way of abashing
him argumentum ad verecundiam, and
then cry out that they have won the battle.
In the real world, be it never so
fair, favorable and pleasant, we always live subject
to the law of gravity which we have to be constantly
overcoming. But in the world of intellect we are
disembodied spirits, held in bondage to no such law,
and free from penury and distress. Thus it is
that there exists no happiness on earth like that
which, at the auspicious moment, a fine and fruitful
mind finds in itself.
The presence of a thought is like
the presence of a woman we love. We fancy we
shall never forget the thought nor become indifferent
to the dear one. But out of sight, out of mind!
The finest thought runs the risk of being irrevocably
forgotten if we do not write it down, and the darling
of being deserted if we do not marry her.
There are plenty of thoughts which
are valuable to the man who thinks them; but only
few of them which have enough strength to produce
repercussive or reflect action I mean, to
win the reader’s sympathy after they have been
put on paper.
But still it must not be forgotten
that a true value attaches only to what a man has
thought in the first instance for his own case.
Thinkers may be classed according as they think chiefly
for their own case or for that of others. The
former are the genuine independent thinkers; they
really think and are really independent; they are the
true philosophers; they alone are in earnest.
The pleasure and the happiness of their existence
consists in thinking. The others are the sophists;
they want to seem that which they are not, and seek
their happiness in what they hope to get from the
world. They are in earnest about nothing else.
To which of these two classes a man belongs may be
seen by his whole style and manner. Lichtenberg
is an example for the former class; Herder, there
can be no doubt, belongs to the second.
When one considers how vast and how
close to us is the problem of existence this
equivocal, tortured, fleeting, dream-like existence
of ours so vast and so close that a man
no sooner discovers it than it overshadows and obscures
all other problems and aims; and when one sees how
all men, with few and rare exceptions, have no clear
consciousness of the problem, nay, seem to be quite
unaware of its presence, but busy themselves with
everything rather than with this, and live on, taking
no thought but for the passing day and the hardly
longer span of their own personal future, either expressly
discarding the problem or else over-ready to come
to terms with it by adopting some system of popular
metaphysics and letting it satisfy them; when, I say,
one takes all this to heart, one may come to the opinion
that man may be said to be a thinking being
only in a very remote sense, and henceforth feel no
special surprise at any trait of human thoughtlessness
or folly; but know, rather, that the normal man’s
intellectual range of vision does indeed extend beyond
that of the brute, whose whole existence is, as it
were, a continual present, with no consciousness of
the past or the future, but not such an immeasurable
distance as is generally supposed.
This is, in fact, corroborated by
the way in which most men converse; where their thoughts
are found to be chopped up fine, like chaff, so that
for them to spin out a discourse of any length is impossible.
If this world were peopled by really
thinking beings, it could not be that noise of every
kind would be allowed such generous limits, as is
the case with the most horrible and at the same time
aimless form of it. If Nature had meant man to
think, she would not have given him ears; or, at any
rate, she would have furnished them with airtight
flaps, such as are the enviable possession of the bat.
But, in truth, man is a poor animal like the rest,
and his powers are meant only to maintain him in the
struggle for existence; so he must need keep his ears
always open, to announce of themselves, by night as
by day, the approach of the pursuer.
In the drama, which is the most perfect
reflection of human existence, there are three stages
in the presentation of the subject, with a corresponding
variety in the design and scope of the piece.
At the first, which is also the most
common, stage, the drama is never anything more than
merely interesting. The persons gain our
attention by following their own aims, which resemble
ours; the action advances by means of intrigue and
the play of character and incident; while wit and
raillery season the whole.
At the second stage, the drama becomes
sentimental. Sympathy is roused with the
hero and, indirectly, with ourselves. The action
takes a pathetic turn; but the end is peaceful and
satisfactory.
The climax is reached with the third
stage, which is the most difficult. There the
drama aims at being tragic. We are brought
face to face with great suffering and the storm and
stress of existence; and the outcome of it is to show
the vanity of all human effort. Deeply moved,
we are either directly prompted to disengage our will
from the struggle of life, or else a chord is struck
in us which echoes a similar feeling.
The beginning, it is said, is always
difficult. In the drama it is just the contrary;
for these the difficulty always lies in the end.
This is proved by countless plays which promise very
well for the first act or two, and then become muddled,
stick or falter notoriously so in the fourth
act and finally conclude in a way that
is either forced or unsatisfactory or else long foreseen
by every one. Sometimes, too, the end is positively
revolting, as in Lessing’s Emilia Galotti,
which sends the spectators home in a temper.
This difficulty in regard to the end
of a play arises partly because it is everywhere easier
to get things into a tangle than to get them out again;
partly also because at the beginning we give the author
carte blanche to do as he likes, but, at the
end, make certain definite demands upon him.
Thus we ask for a conclusion that shall be either
quite happy or else quite tragic; whereas human affairs
do not easily take so decided a turn; and then we
expect that it shall be natural, fit and proper, unlabored,
and at the same time foreseen by no one.
These remarks are also applicable
to an epic and to a novel; but the more compact nature
of the drama makes the difficulty plainer by increasing
it.
E nihilo nihil fit. That
nothing can come from nothing is a maxim true in fine
art as elsewhere. In composing an historical picture,
a good artist will use living men as a model, and
take the groundwork of the faces from life; and then
proceed to idealize them in point of beauty or expression.
A similar method, I fancy, is adopted by good novelists.
In drawing a character they take a general outline
of it from some real person of their acquaintance,
and then idealize and complete it to suit their purpose.
A novel will be of a high and noble
order, the more it represents of inner, and the less
it represents of outer, life; and the ratio between
the two will supply a means of judging any novel, of
whatever kind, from Tristram Shandy down to
the crudest and most sensational tale of knight or
robber. Tristram Shandy has, indeed, as good
as no action at all; and there is not much in La
Nouvelle Heloise and Wilhelm Meister.
Even Don Quixote has relatively little; and
what there is, very unimportant, and introduced merely
for the sake of fun. And these four are the best
of all existing novels.
Consider, further, the wonderful romances
of Jean Paul, and how much inner life is shown on
the narrowest basis of actual event. Even in
Walter Scott’s novels there is a great preponderance
of inner over outer life, and incident is never brought
in except for the purpose of giving play to thought
and emotion; whereas, in bad novels, incident is there
on its own account. Skill consists in setting
the inner life in motion with the smallest possible
array of circumstance; for it is this inner life that
really excites our interest.
The business of the novelist is not
to relate great events, but to make small ones interesting.
History, which I like to think of
as the contrary of poetry [Greek: istoroumenon pepoiaemenon],
is for time what geography is for space; and it is
no more to be called a science, in any strict sense
of the word, than is geography, because it does not
deal with universal truths, but only with particular
details. History has always been the favorite
study of those who wish to learn something, without
having to face the effort demanded by any branch of
real knowledge, which taxes the intelligence.
In our time history is a favorite pursuit; as witness
the numerous books upon the subject which appear every
year.
If the reader cannot help thinking,
with me, that history is merely the constant recurrence
of similar things, just as in a kaleidoscope the same
bits of glass are represented, but in different combinations,
he will not be able to share all this lively interest;
nor, however, will he censure it. But there is
a ridiculous and absurd claim, made by many people,
to regard history as a part of philosophy, nay, as
philosophy itself; they imagine that history can take
its place.
The preference shown for history by
the greater public in all ages may be illustrated
by the kind of conversation which is so much in vogue
everywhere in society. It generally consists in
one person relating something and then another person
relating something else; so that in this way everyone
is sure of receiving attention. Both here and
in the case of history it is plain that the mind is
occupied with particular details. But as in science,
so also in every worthy conversation, the mind rises
to the consideration of some general truth.
This objection does not, however,
deprive history of its value. Human life is short
and fleeting, and many millions of individuals share
in it, who are swallowed by that monster of oblivion
which is waiting for them with ever-open jaws.
It is thus a very thankworthy task to try to rescue
something the memory of interesting and
important events, or the leading features and personages
of some epoch from the general shipwreck
of the world.
From another point of view, we might
look upon history as the sequel to zoology; for while
with all other animals it is enough to observe the
species, with man individuals, and therefore individual
events have to be studied; because every man possesses
a character as an individual. And since individuals
and events are without number or end, an essential
imperfection attaches to history. In the study
of it, all that a man learns never contributes to
lessen that which he has still to learn. With
any real science, a perfection of knowledge is, at
any rate, conceivable.
When we gain access to the histories
of China and of India, the endlessness of the subject-matter
will reveal to us the defects in the study, and force
our historians to see that the object of science is
to recognize the many in the one, to perceive the rules
in any given example, and to apply to the life of
nations a knowledge of mankind; not to go on counting
up facts ad infinitum.
There are two kinds of history; the
history of politics and the history of literature
and art. The one is the history of the will;
the other, that of the intellect. The first is
a tale of woe, even of terror: it is a record
of agony, struggle, fraud, and horrible murder en
masse. The second is everywhere pleasing and
serene, like the intellect when left to itself, even
though its path be one of error. Its chief branch
is the history of philosophy. This is, in fact,
its fundamental bass, and the notes of it are heard
even in the other kind of history. These deep
tones guide the formation of opinion, and opinion
rules the world. Hence philosophy, rightly understood,
is a material force of the most powerful kind, though
very slow in its working. The philosophy of a
period is thus the fundamental bass of its history.
The NEWSPAPER, is the second-hand
in the clock of history; and it is not only made of
baser metal than those which point to the minute and
the hour, but it seldom goes right.
The so-called leading article is the
chorus to the drama of passing events.
Exaggeration of every kind is as essential
to journalism as it is to the dramatic art; for the
object of journalism is to make events go as far as
possible. Thus it is that all journalists are,
in the very nature of their calling, alarmists; and
this is their way of giving interest to what they
write. Herein they are like little dogs; if anything
stirs, they immediately set up a shrill bark.
Therefore, let us carefully regulate
the attention to be paid to this trumpet of danger,
so that it may not disturb our digestion. Let
us recognize that a newspaper is at best but a magnifying-glass,
and very often merely a shadow on the wall.
The pen is to thought what
the stick is to walking; but you walk most easily
when you have no stick, and you think with the greatest
perfection when you have no pen in your hand.
It is only when a man begins to be old that he likes
to use a stick and is glad to take up his pen.
When an hypothesis has once
come to birth in the mind, or gained a footing there,
it leads a life so far comparable with the life of
an organism, as that it assimilates matter from the
outer world only when it is like in kind with it and
beneficial; and when, contrarily, such matter is not
like in kind but hurtful, the hypothesis, equally with
the organism, throws it off, or, if forced to take
it, gets rid of it again entire.
To gain immortality an author
must possess so many excellences that while it will
not be easy to find anyone to understand and appreciate
them all, there will be men in every age who are able
to recognize and value some of them. In this
way the credit of his book will be maintained throughout
the long course of centuries, in spite of the fact
that human interests are always changing.
An author like this, who has a claim
to the continuance of his life even with posterity,
can only be a man who, over the wide earth, will seek
his like in vain, and offer a palpable contrast with
everyone else in virtue of his unmistakable distinction.
Nay, more: were he, like the wandering Jew, to
live through several generations, he would still remain
in the same superior position. If this were not
so, it would be difficult to see why his thoughts
should not perish like those of other men.
Metaphors and similes
are of great value, in so far as they explain an unknown
relation by a known one. Even the more detailed
simile which grows into a parable or an allegory, is
nothing more than the exhibition of some relation
in its simplest, most visible and palpable form.
The growth of ideas rests, at bottom, upon similes;
because ideas arise by a process of combining the similarities
and neglecting the differences between things.
Further, intelligence, in the strict sense of the
word, ultimately consists in a seizing of relations;
and a clear and pure grasp of relations is all the
more often attained when the comparison is made between
cases that lie wide apart from one another, and between
things of quite different nature. As long as
a relation is known to me as existing only in a single
case, I have but an individual idea of it in
other words, only an intuitive knowledge of it; but
as soon as I see the same relation in two different
cases, I have a general idea of its whole nature,
and this is a deeper and more perfect knowledge.
Since, then, similes and metaphors
are such a powerful engine of knowledge, it is a sign
of great intelligence in a writer if his similes are
unusual and, at the same time, to the point. Aristotle
also observes that by far the most important thing
to a writer is to have this power of metaphor; for
it is a gift which cannot be acquired, and it is a
mark of genius.
As regards reading, to require
that a man shall retain everything he has ever read,
is like asking him to carry about with him all he has
ever eaten. The one kind of food has given him
bodily, and the other mental, nourishment; and it
is through these two means that he has grown to be
what he is. The body assimilates only that which
is like it; and so a man retains in his mind only
that which interests him, in other words, that which
suits his system of thought or his purposes in life.
If a man wants to read good books,
he must make a point of avoiding bad ones; for life
is short, and time and energy limited.
Repetitio est mater studiorum.
Any book that is at all important ought to be at once
read through twice; partly because, on a second reading,
the connection of the different portions of the book
will be better understood, and the beginning comprehended
only when the end is known; and partly because we
are not in the same temper and disposition on both
readings. On the second perusal we get a new view
of every passage and a different impression of the
whole book, which then appears in another light.
A man’s works are the quintessence
of his mind, and even though he may possess very great
capacity, they will always be incomparably more valuable
than his conversation. Nay, in all essential matters
his works will not only make up for the lack of personal
intercourse with him, but they will far surpass it
in solid advantages. The writings even of a man
of moderate genius may be edifying, worth reading and
instructive, because they are his quintessence the
result and fruit of all his thought and study; whilst
conversation with him may be unsatisfactory.
So it is that we can read books by
men in whose company we find nothing to please, and
that a high degree of culture leads us to seek entertainment
almost wholly from books and not from men.