The following brief remarks on the
critical faculty are chiefly intended to show that,
for the most part, there is no such thing. It
is a rara avis; almost as rare, indeed, as the
phoenix, which appears only once in five hundred years.
When we speak of taste an
expression not chosen with any regard for it we
mean the discovery, or, it may be only the recognition,
of what is right aesthetically, apart from
the guidance of any rule; and this, either because
no rule has as yet been extended to the matter in
question, or else because, if existing, it is unknown
to the artist, or the critic, as the case may be.
Instead of taste, we might use the expression
aesthetic sense, if this were not tautological.
The perceptive critical taste is,
so to speak, the female analogue to the male quality
of productive talent or genius. Not capable of
begetting great work itself, it consists in
a capacity of reception, that is to say, of
recognizing as such what is right, fit, beautiful,
or the reverse; in other words, of discriminating
the good from the bad, of discovering and appreciating
the one and condemning the other.
In appreciating a genius, criticism
should not deal with the errors in his productions
or with the poorer of his works, and then proceed to
rate him low; it should attend only to the qualities
in which he most excels. For in the sphere of
intellect, as in other spheres, weakness and perversity
cleave so firmly to human nature that even the most
brilliant mind is not wholly and at all times free
from them. Hence the great errors to be found
even in the works of the greatest men; or as Horace
puts it, quandoque bonus dormitat Homerus.
That which distinguishes genius, and
should be the standard for judging it, is the height
to which it is able to soar when it is in the proper
mood and finds a fitting occasion a height
always out of the reach of ordinary talent. And,
in like manner, it is a very dangerous thing to compare
two great men of the same class; for instance, two
great poets, or musicians, or philosophers, or artists;
because injustice to the one or the other, at least
for the moment, can hardly be avoided. For in
making a comparison of the kind the critic looks to
some particular merit of the one and at once discovers
that it is absent in the other, who is thereby disparaged.
And then if the process is reversed, and the critic
begins with the latter and discovers his peculiar
merit, which is quite of a different order from that
presented by the former, with whom it may be looked
for in vain, the result is that both of them suffer
undue depreciation.
There are critics who severally think
that it rests with each one of them what shall be
accounted good, and what bad. They all mistake
their own toy-trumpets for the trombones of fame.
A drug does not effect its purpose
if the dose is too large; and it is the same with
censure and adverse criticism when it exceeds the
measure of justice.
The disastrous thing for intellectual
merit is that it must wait for those to praise the
good who have themselves produced nothing but what
is bad; nay, it is a primary misfortune that it has
to receive its crown at the hands of the critical
power of mankind a quality of which most
men possess only the weak and impotent semblance, so
that the reality may be numbered amongst the rarest
gifts of nature. Hence La Bruyere’s remark
is, unhappily, as true as it is neat. Âpres l’esprit
de discernement, he says, ce qu’il y a
au monde de plus rare, ce sont les diamans et les
perles. The spirit of discernment! the critical
faculty! it is these that are lacking. Men do
not know how to distinguish the genuine from the false,
the corn from the chaff, gold from copper; or to perceive
the wide gulf that separates a genius from an ordinary
man. Thus we have that bad state of things described
in an old-fashioned verse, which gives it as the lot
of the great ones here on earth to be recognized only
when they are gone:
Es ist nun das Geschick der Grossen
fiier auf Erden,
Erst wann sie nicht mehr sind; von uns
erkannt zu werden.
When any genuine and excellent work
makes its appearance, the chief difficulty in its
way is the amount of bad work it finds already in
possession of the field, and accepted as though it
were good. And then if, after a long time, the
new comer really succeeds, by a hard struggle, in
vindicating his place for himself and winning reputation,
he will soon encounter fresh difficulty from some affected,
dull, awkward imitator, whom people drag in, with
the object of calmly setting him up on the altar beside
the genius; not seeing the difference and really thinking
that here they have to do with another great man.
This is what Yriarte means by the first lines of his
twenty-eighth Fable, where he declares that the ignorant
rabble always sets equal value on the good and the
bad:
Siempre acostumbra hacer el vulgo necio
De lo bueno y lo malo igual aprecio.
So even Shakespeare’s dramas
had, immediately after his death, to give place to
those of Ben Jonson, Massinger, Beaumont and Fletcher,
and to yield the supremacy for a hundred years.
So Kant’s serious philosophy was crowded out
by the nonsense of Fichte, Schelling, Jacobi, Hegel.
And even in a sphere accessible to all, we have seen
unworthy imitators quickly diverting public attention
from the incomparable Walter Scott. For, say
what you will, the public has no sense for excellence,
and therefore no notion how very rare it is to find
men really capable of doing anything great in poetry,
philosophy, or art, or that their works are alone
worthy of exclusive attention. The dabblers,
whether in verse or in any other high sphere, should
be every day unsparingly reminded that neither gods,
nor men, nor booksellers have pardoned their mediocrity:
mediocribus
esse poetis
Non homines, non Di, non concessere columnae.
Are they not the weeds that prevent
the corn coming up, so that they may cover all the
ground themselves? And then there happens that
which has been well and freshly described by the lamented
Feuchtersleben, who died so young: how people
cry out in their haste that nothing is being done,
while all the while great work is quietly growing to
maturity; and then, when it appears, it is not seen
or heard in the clamor, but goes its way silently,
in modest grief:
“Ist doch” rufen
sie vermessen Nichts im Werke, nichts
gethan!” Und das Grosse, reift indessen Still
heran.
Es ersheint nun: niemand sieht
es, Niemand hoert es im Geschrei Mit bescheid’ner
Trauer zieht es Still vorbei.
This lamentable death of the critical
faculty is not less obvious in the case of science,
as is shown by the tenacious life of false and disproved
theories. If they are once accepted, they may
go on bidding defiance to truth for fifty or even
a hundred years and more, as stable as an iron pier
in the midst of the waves. The Ptolemaic system
was still held a century after Copernicus had promulgated
his theory. Bacon, Descartes and Locke made their
way extremely slowly and only after a long time; as
the reader may see by d’Alembert’s celebrated
Preface to the Encyclopedia. Newton was
not more successful; and this is sufficiently proved
by the bitterness and contempt with which Leibnitz
attacked his theory of gravitation in the controversy
with Clarke. Although Newton lived for almost forty
years after the appearance of the Principia,
his teaching was, when he died, only to some extent
accepted in his own country, whilst outside England
he counted scarcely twenty adherents; if we may believe
the introductory note to Voltaire’s exposition
of his theory. It was, indeed, chiefly owing
to this treatise of Voltaire’s that the system
became known in France nearly twenty years after Newton’s
death. Until then a firm, resolute, and patriotic
stand was made by the Cartesian Vortices; whilst
only forty years previously, this same Cartesian philosophy
had been forbidden in the French schools; and now
in turn d’Agnesseau, the Chancellor, refused
Voltaire the Imprimatur for his treatise on
the Newtonian doctrine. On the other hand, in
our day Newton’s absurd theory of color still
completely holds the field, forty years after the
publication of Goethe’s. Hume, too, was
disregarded up to his fiftieth year, though he began
very early and wrote in a thoroughly popular style.
And Kant, in spite of having written and talked all
his life long, did not become a famous man until he
was sixty.
Artists and poets have, to be sure,
more chance than thinkers, because their public is
at least a hundred times as large. Still, what
was thought of Beethoven and Mozart during their lives?
what of Dante? what even of Shakespeare? If the
latter’s contemporaries had in any way recognized
his worth, at least one good and accredited portrait
of him would have come down to us from an age when
the art of painting flourished; whereas we possess
only some very doubtful pictures, a bad copperplate,
and a still worse bust on his tomb. And in like
manner, if he had been duly honored, specimens of his
handwriting would have been preserved to us by the
hundred, instead of being confined, as is the case,
to the signatures to a few legal documents. The
Portuguese are still proud of their only poet Camoens.
He lived, however, on alms collected every evening
in the street by a black slave whom he had brought
with him from the Indies. In time, no doubt,
justice will be done everyone; tempo e galant uomo;
but it is as late and slow in arriving as in a court
of law, and the secret condition of it is that the
recipient shall be no longer alive. The precept
of Jesus the son of Sirach is faithfully followed:
Judge none blessed before his death. He,
then, who has produced immortal works, must find comfort
by applying to them the words of the Indian myth,
that the minutes of life amongst the immortals seem
like years of earthly existence; and so, too, that
years upon earth are only as the minutes of the immortals.
This lack of critical insight is also
shown by the fact that, while in every century the
excellent work of earlier time is held in honor, that
of its own is misunderstood, and the attention which
is its due is given to bad work, such as every decade
carries with it only to be the sport of the next.
That men are slow to recognize genuine merit when
it appears in their own age, also proves that they
do not understand or enjoy or really value the long-acknowledged
works of genius, which they honor only on the score
of authority. The crucial test is the fact that
bad work Fichte’s philosophy, for
example if it wins any reputation, also
maintains it for one or two generations; and only
when its public is very large does its fall follow
sooner.
Now, just as the sun cannot shed its
light but to the eye that sees it, nor music sound
but to the hearing ear, so the value of all masterly
work in art and science is conditioned by the kinship
and capacity of the mind to which it speaks.
It is only such a mind as this that possesses the
magic word to stir and call forth the spirits that
lie hidden in great work. To the ordinary mind
a masterpiece is a sealed cabinet of mystery, an
unfamiliar musical instrument from which the player,
however much he may flatter himself, can draw none
but confused tones. How different a painting looks
when seen in a good light, as compared with some dark
corner! Just in the same way, the impression
made by a masterpiece varies with the capacity of the
mind to understand it.
A fine work, then, requires a mind
sensitive to its beauty; a thoughtful work, a mind
that can really think, if it is to exist and live
at all. But alas! it may happen only too often
that he who gives a fine work to the world afterwards
feels like a maker of fireworks, who displays with
enthusiasm the wonders that have taken him so much
time and trouble to prepare, and then learns that he
has come to the wrong place, and that the fancied
spectators were one and all inmates of an asylum for
the blind. Still even that is better than if his
public had consisted entirely of men who made fireworks
themselves; as in this case, if his display had been
extraordinarily good, it might possibly have cost
him his head.
The source of all pleasure and delight
is the feeling of kinship. Even with the sense
of beauty it is unquestionably our own species in the
animal world, and then again our own race, that appears
to us the fairest. So, too, in intercourse with
others, every man shows a decided preference for those
who resemble him; and a blockhead will find the society
of another blockhead incomparably more pleasant than
that of any number of great minds put together.
Every man must necessarily take his chief pleasure
in his own work, because it is the mirror of his own
mind, the echo of his own thought; and next in order
will come the work of people like him; that is to say,
a dull, shallow and perverse man, a dealer in mere
words, will give his sincere and hearty applause only
to that which is dull, shallow, perverse or merely
verbose. On the other hand, he will allow merit
to the work of great minds only on the score of authority,
in other words, because he is ashamed to speak his
opinion; for in reality they give him no pleasure
at all. They do not appeal to him; nay, they repel
him; and he will not confess this even to himself.
The works of genius cannot be fully enjoyed except
by those who are themselves of the privileged order.
The first recognition of them, however, when they exist
without authority to support them, demands considerable
superiority of mind.
When the reader takes all this into
consideration, he should be surprised, not that great
work is so late in winning reputation, but that it
wins it at all. And as a matter of fact, fame
comes only by a slow and complex process. The
stupid person is by degrees forced, and as it were,
tamed, into recognizing the superiority of one who
stands immediately above him; this one in his turn
bows before some one else; and so it goes on until
the weight of the votes gradually prevail over their
number; and this is just the condition of all genuine,
in other words, deserved fame. But until then,
the greatest genius, even after he has passed his
time of trial, stands like a king amidst a crowd of
his own subjects, who do not know him by sight and
therefore will not do his behests; unless, indeed,
his chief ministers of state are in his train.
For no subordinate official can be the direct recipient
of the royal commands, as he knows only the signature
of his immediate superior; and this is repeated all
the way up into the highest ranks, where the under-secretary
attests the minister’s signature, and the minister
that of the king. There are analogous stages to
be passed before a genius can attain widespread fame.
This is why his reputation most easily comes to a
standstill at the very outset; because the highest
authorities, of whom there can be but few, are most
frequently not to be found; but the further down he
goes in the scale the more numerous are those who
take the word from above, so that his fame is no more
arrested.
We must console ourselves for this
state of things by reflecting that it is really fortunate
that the greater number of men do not form a judgment
on their own responsibility, but merely take it on
authority. For what sort of criticism should
we have on Plato and Kant, Homer, Shakespeare and
Goethe, if every man were to form his opinion by what
he really has and enjoys of these writers, instead
of being forced by authority to speak of them in a
fit and proper way, however little he may really feel
what he says. Unless something of this kind took
place, it would be impossible for true merit, in any
high sphere, to attain fame at all. At the same
time it is also fortunate that every man has just
so much critical power of his own as is necessary for
recognizing the superiority of those who are placed
immediately over him, and for following their lead.
This means that the many come in the end to submit
to the authority of the few; and there results that
hierarchy of critical judgments on which is based the
possibility of a steady, and eventually wide-reaching,
fame.
The lowest class in the community
is quite impervious to the merits of a great genius;
and for these people there is nothing left but the
monument raised to him, which, by the impression it
produces on their senses, awakes in them a dim idea
of the man’s greatness.
Literary journals should be a dam
against the unconscionable scribbling of the age,
and the ever-increasing deluge of bad and useless
books. Their judgments should be uncorrupted,
just and rigorous; and every piece of bad work done
by an incapable person; every device by which the
empty head tries to come to the assistance of the
empty purse, that is to say, about nine-tenths of all
existing books, should be mercilessly scourged.
Literary journals would then perform their duty, which
is to keep down the craving for writing and put a
check upon the deception of the public, instead of
furthering these evils by a miserable toleration,
which plays into the hands of author and publisher,
and robs the reader of his time and his money.
If there were such a paper as I mean,
every bad writer, every brainless compiler, every
plagiarist from other’s books, every hollow
and incapable place-hunter, every sham-philosopher,
every vain and languishing poetaster, would shudder
at the prospect of the pillory in which his bad work
would inevitably have to stand soon after publication.
This would paralyze his twitching fingers, to the true
welfare of literature, in which what is bad is not
only useless but positively pernicious. Now,
most books are bad and ought to have remained unwritten.
Consequently praise should be as rare as is now the
case with blame, which is withheld under the influence
of personal considerations, coupled with the maxim
accedas socius, laudes lauderis ut absens.
It is quite wrong to try to introduce
into literature the same toleration as must necessarily
prevail in society towards those stupid, brainless
people who everywhere swarm in it. In literature
such people are impudent intruders; and to disparage
the bad is here duty towards the good; for he who
thinks nothing bad will think nothing good either.
Politeness, which has its source in social relations,
is in literature an alien, and often injurious, element;
because it exacts that bad work shall be called good.
In this way the very aim of science and art is directly
frustrated.
The ideal journal could, to be sure,
be written only by people who joined incorruptible
honesty with rare knowledge and still rarer power
of judgment; so that perhaps there could, at the very
most, be one, and even hardly one, in the whole country;
but there it would stand, like a just Aeropagus, every
member of which would have to be elected by all the
others. Under the system that prevails at present,
literary journals are carried on by a clique, and
secretly perhaps also by booksellers for the good
of the trade; and they are often nothing but coalitions
of bad heads to prevent the good ones succeeding.
As Goethe once remarked to me, nowhere is there so
much dishonesty as in literature.
But, above all, anonymity, that shield
of all literary rascality, would have to disappear.
It was introduced under the pretext of protecting
the honest critic, who warned the public, against the
resentment of the author and his friends. But
where there is one case of this sort, there will be
a hundred where it merely serves to take all responsibility
from the man who cannot stand by what he has said,
or possibly to conceal the shame of one who has been
cowardly and base enough to recommend a book to the
public for the purpose of putting money into his own
pocket. Often enough it is only a cloak for covering
the obscurity, incompetence and insignificance of the
critic. It is incredible what impudence these
fellows will show, and what literary trickery they
will venture to commit, as soon as they know they
are safe under the shadow of anonymity. Let me
recommend a general Anti-criticism, a universal
medicine or panacea, to put a stop to all anonymous
reviewing, whether it praises the bad or blames the
good: Rascal! your name! For a man
to wrap himself up and draw his hat over his face,
and then fall upon people who are walking about without
any disguise this is not the part of a gentleman,
it is the part of a scoundrel and a knave.
An anonymous review has no more authority
than an anonymous letter; and one should be received
with the same mistrust as the other. Or shall
we take the name of the man who consents to preside
over what is, in the strict sense of the word, une
société anonyme as a guarantee for the veracity
of his colleagues?
Even Rousseau, in the preface to the
Nouvelle Heloise, declares tout honnête
homme doit avouer les livres qu’il public;
which in plain language means that every honorable
man ought to sign his articles, and that no one is
honorable who does not do so. How much truer
this is of polemical writing, which is the general
character of reviews! Riemer was quite right
in the opinion he gives in his Reminiscences of
Goethe: An overt enemy, he says, an enemy
who meets you face to face, is an honorable man, who
will treat you fairly, and with whom you can come
to terms and be reconciled: but an enemy who
conceals himself is a base, cowardly scoundrel,
who has not courage enough to avow his own judgment;
it is not his opinion that he cares about, but only
the secret pleasures of wreaking his anger without
being found out or punished. This will also have
been Goethe’s opinion, as he was generally the
source from which Riemer drew his observations.
And, indeed, Rousseau’s maxim applies to every
line that is printed. Would a man in a mask ever
be allowed to harangue a mob, or speak in any assembly;
and that, too, when he was going to attack others
and overwhelm them with abuse?
Anonymity is the refuge for all literary
and journalistic rascality. It is a practice
which must be completely stopped. Every article,
even in a newspaper, should be accompanied by the
name of its author; and the editor should be made
strictly responsible for the accuracy of the signature.
The freedom of the press should be thus far restricted;
so that when a man publicly proclaims through the
far-sounding trumpet of the newspaper, he should be
answerable for it, at any rate with his honor, if
he has any; and if he has none, let his name neutralize
the effect of his words. And since even the most
insignificant person is known in his own circle, the
result of such a measure would be to put an end to
two-thirds of the newspaper lies, and to restrain the
audacity of many a poisonous tongue.