For every animal, and more especially
for man, a certain conformity and proportion between
the will and the intellect is necessary for existing
or making any progress in the world. The more
precise and correct the proportion which nature establishes,
the more easy, safe and agreeable will be the passage
through the world. Still, if the right point is
only approximately reached, it will be enough to ward
off destruction. There are, then, certain limits
within which the said proportion may vary, and yet
preserve a correct standard of conformity. The
normal standard is as follows. The object of
the intellect is to light and lead the will on its
path, and therefore, the greater the force, impetus
and passion, which spurs on the will from within,
the more complete and luminous must be the intellect
which is attached to it, that the vehement strife of
the will, the glow of passion, and the intensity of
the emotions, may not lead man astray, or urge him
on to ill considered, false or ruinous action; this
will, inevitably, be the result, if the will is very
violent and the intellect very weak. On the other
hand, a phlegmatic character, a weak and languid will,
can get on and hold its own with a small amount of
intellect; what is naturally moderate needs only moderate
support. The general tendency of a want of proportion
between the will and the intellect, in other words,
of any variation from the normal proportion I have
mentioned, is to produce unhappiness, whether it be
that the will is greater than the intellect, or the
intellect greater than the will. Especially is
this the case when the intellect is developed to an
abnormal degree of strength and superiority, so as
to be out of all proportion to the will, a condition
which is the essence of real genius; the intellect
is then not only more than enough for the needs and
aims of life, it is absolutely prejudicial to them.
The result is that, in youth, excessive energy in
grasping the objective world, accompanied by a vivid
imagination and a total lack of experience, makes
the mind susceptible, and an easy prey to extravagant
ideas, nay, even to chimeras; and the result is an
eccentric and phantastic character. And when,
in later years, this state of mind yields and passes
away under the teaching of experience, still the genius
never feels himself at home in the common world of
every day and the ordinary business of life; he will
never take his place in it, and accommodate himself
to it as accurately as the person of moral intellect;
he will be much more likely to make curious mistakes.
For the ordinary mind feels itself so completely at
home in the narrow circle of its ideas and views of
the world that no one can get the better of it in
that sphere; its faculties remain true to their original
purpose, viz., to promote the service of the
will; it devotes itself steadfastly to this end, and
abjures extravagant aims. The genius, on the
other hand, is at bottom a monstrum per excessum;
just as, conversely, the passionate, violent and unintelligent
man, the brainless barbarian, is a monstrum per
defectum.
The will to live, which forms
the inmost core of every living being, exhibits itself
most conspicuously in the higher order of animals,
that is, the cleverer ones; and so in them the nature
of the will may be seen and examined most clearly.
For in the lower orders its activity is not so evident;
it has a lower degree of objectivation; whereas,
in the class which stands above the higher order of
animals, that is, in men, reason enters in; and with
reason comes discretion, and with discretion, the
capacity of dissimulation, which throws a veil over
the operations of the will. And in mankind, consequently,
the will appears without its mask only in the affections
and the passions. And this is the reason why
passion, when it speaks, always wins credence, no matter
what the passion may be; and rightly so. For
the same reason the passions are the main theme of
poets and the stalking horse of actors. The conspicuousness
of the will in the lower order of animals explains
the delight we take in dogs, apes, cats, etc.;
it is the entirely naïve way in which they express
themselves that gives us so much pleasure.
The sight of any free animal going
about its business undisturbed, seeking its food,
or looking after its young, or mixing in the company
of its kind, all the time being exactly what it ought
to be and can be, what a strange pleasure
it gives us! Even if it is only a bird, I can
watch it for a long time with delight; or a water rat
or a hedgehog; or better still, a weasel, a deer,
or a stag. The main reason why we take so much
pleasure in looking at animals is that we like to see
our own nature in such a simplified form. There
is only one mendacious being in the world, and that
is man. Every other is true and sincere, and
makes no attempt to conceal what it is, expressing
its feelings just as they are.
Many things are put down to the force
of habit which are rather to be attributed to the
constancy and immutability of original, innate character,
according to which under like circumstances we always
do the same thing: whether it happens for the
first or the hundredth time, it is in virtue of the
same necessity. Real force of habit, as a matter
of fact, rests upon that indolent, passive disposition
which seeks to relieve the intellect and the will
of a fresh choice, and so makes us do what we did
yesterday and have done a hundred times before, and
of which we know that it will attain its object.
But the truth of the matter lies deeper, and a more
precise explanation of it can be given than appears
at first sight. Bodies which may be moved by mechanical
means only are subject to the power of inertia; and
applied to bodies which may be acted on by motives,
this power becomes the force of habit. The actions
which we perform by mere habit come about, in fact,
without any individual separate motive brought into
play for the particular case: hence, in performing
them, we really do not think about them. A motive
was present only on the first few occasions on which
the action happened, which has since become a habit:
the secondary after-effect of this motive is the present
habit, and it is sufficient to enable the action to
continue: just as when a body had been set in
motion by a push, it requires no more pushing in order
to continue its motion; it will go on to all eternity,
if it meets with no friction. It is the same
in the case of animals: training is a habit which
is forced upon them. The horse goes on drawing
his cart quite contentedly, without having to be urged
on: the motion is the continued effect of those
strokes of the whip, which urged him on at first:
by the law of inertia they have become perpetuated
as habit. All this is really more than a mere
parable: it is the underlying identity of the
will at very different degrees of its objectivation,
in virtue of which the same law of motion takes such
different forms.
Vive muchos años is the ordinary
greeting in Spain, and all over the earth it is quite
customary to wish people a long life. It is presumably
not a knowledge of life which directs such a wish;
it is rather knowledge of what man is in his inmost
nature, the will to live.
The wish which everyone has that he
may be remembered after his death, a wish
which rises to the longing for posthumous glory in
the case of those whose aims are high, seems
to me to spring from this clinging to life. When
the time comes which cuts a man off from every possibility
of real existence, he strives after a life which is
still attainable, even though it be a shadowy and
ideal one.
The deep grief we feel at the loss
of a friend arises from the feeling that in every
individual there is something which no words can express,
something which is peculiarly his own and therefore
irreparable. Omne individuum ineffabile.
We may come to look upon the death
of our enemies and adversaries, even long after it
has occurred, with just as much regret as we feel for
that of our friends, viz., when we miss them
as witnesses of our brilliant success.
That the sudden announcement of a
very happy event may easily prove fatal rests upon
the fact that happiness and misery depend merely on
the proportion which our claims bear to what we get.
Accordingly, the good things we possess, or are certain
of getting, are not felt to be such; because all pleasure
is in fact of a negative nature and effects the relief
of pain, while pain or evil is what is really positive;
it is the object of immediate sensation. With
the possession or certain expectation of good things
our demands rises, and increases our capacity for
further possession and larger expectations. But
if we are depressed by continual misfortune, and our
claims reduced to a minimum, the sudden advent of
happiness finds no capacity for enjoying it. Neutralized
by an absence of pre-existing claims, its effects
are apparently positive, and so its whole force is
brought into play; hence it may possibly break our
feelings, i.e., be fatal to them. And so,
as is well known, one must be careful in announcing
great happiness. First, one must get the person
to hope for it, then open up the prospect of it, then
communicate part of it, and at last make it fully
known. Every portion of the good news loses its
efficacy, because it is anticipated by a demand, and
room is left for an increase in it. In view of
all this, it may be said that our stomach for good
fortune is bottomless, but the entrance to it is narrow.
These remarks are not applicable to great misfortunes
in the same way. They are more seldom fatal,
because hope always sets itself against them.
That an analogous part is not played by fear in the
case of happiness results from the fact that we are
instinctively more inclined to hope than to fear;
just as our eyes turn of themselves towards light
rather than darkness.
Hope is the result of confusing the
desire that something should take place with the probability
that it will. Perhaps no man is free from this
folly of the heart, which deranges the intellect’s
correct appreciation of probability to such an extent
that, if the chances are a thousand to one against
it, yet the event is thought a likely one. Still
in spite of this, a sudden misfortune is like a death
stroke, whilst a hope that is always disappointed
and still never dies, is like death by prolonged torture.
He who has lost all hope has also
lost all fear; this is the meaning of the expression
“desperate.” It is natural to a man
to believe what he wishes to be true, and to believe
it because he wishes it, If this characteristic of
our nature, at once beneficial and assuaging, is rooted
out by many hard blows of fate, and a man comes, conversely,
to a condition in which he believes a thing must happen
because he does not wish it, and what he wishes to
happen can never be, just because he wishes it, this
is in reality the state described as “desperation.”
That we are so often deceived in others
is not because our judgment is at fault, but because
in general, as Bacon says, intellectus luminis
sicci non est, sed recipit infusionem a voluntate et
affectibus: that is to say, trifles unconsciously
bias us for or against a person from the very beginning.
It may also be explained by our not abiding by the
qualities which we really discover; we go on to conclude
the presence of others which we think inseparable
from them, or the absence of those which we consider
incompatible. For instance, when we perceive
generosity, we infer justice; from piety, we infer
honesty; from lying, deception; from deception, stealing,
etc.; a procedure which opens the door to many
false views, partly because human nature is so strange,
partly because our standpoint is so one-sided.
It is true, indeed, that character always forms a
consistent and connected whole; but the roots of all
its qualities lie too deep to allow of our concluding
from particular data in a given case whether certain
qualities can or cannot exist together.
We often happen to say things that
may in some way or other be prejudicial to us; but
we keep silent about things that might make us look
ridiculous; because in this case effect follows very
quickly on cause.
The pain of an unfulfilled wish is
small in comparison with that of repentance; for the
one stands in the presence of the vast open future,
whilst the other has the irrevocable past closed behind
it.
Geduld, patientia, patience,
especially the Spanish sufrimiento, is strongly
connected with the notion of suffering.
It is therefore a passive state, just as the opposite
is an active state of the mind, with which, when great,
patience is incompatible. It is the innate virtue
of a phlegmatic, indolent, and spiritless people,
as also of women. But that it is nevertheless
so very useful and necessary is a sign that the world
is very badly constituted.
Money is human happiness in the abstract:
he, then, who is no longer capable of enjoying human
happiness in the concrete, devotes his heart entirely
to money.
Obstinacy is the result of the will
forcing itself into the place of the intellect.
If you want to find out your real
opinion of anyone, observe the impression made upon
you by the first sight of a letter from him.
The course of our individual life
and the events in it, as far as their true meaning
and connection is concerned, may be compared to a piece
of rough mosaic. So long as you stand close in
front of it, you cannot get a right view of the objects
presented, nor perceive their significance or beauty.
Both come in sight only when you stand a little way
off. And in the same way you often understand
the true connection of important events in your life,
not while they are going on, nor soon after they are
past, but only a considerable time afterwards.
Is this so, because we require the
magnifying effect of imagination? or because we can
get a general view only from a distance? or because
the school of experience makes our judgment ripe?
Perhaps all of these together: but it is certain
that we often view in the right light the actions
of others, and occasionally even our own, only after
the lapse of years. And as it is in one’s
own life, so it is in history.
Happy circumstances in life are like
certain groups of trees. Seen from a distance
they look very well: but go up to them and amongst
them, and the beauty vanishes; you don’t know
where it can be; it is only trees you see. And
so it is that we often envy the lot of others.
The doctor sees all the weakness of
mankind, the lawyer all the wickedness, the theologian
all the stupidity.
A person of phlegmatic disposition
who is a blockhead, would, with a sanguine nature,
be a fool.
Now and then one learns something,
but one forgets the whole day long.
Moreover our memory is like a sieve,
the holes of which in time get larger and larger:
the older we get, the quicker anything entrusted to
it slips from the memory, whereas, what was fixed fast
in it in early days is there still. The memory
of an old man gets clearer and clearer, the further
it goes back, and less clear the nearer it approaches
the present time; so that his memory, like his eyes,
becomes short-sighted.
In the process of learning you may
be apprehensive about bewildering and confusing the
memory, but not about overloading it, in the strict
sense of the word. The faculty for remembering
is not diminished in proportion to what one has learnt,
just as little as the number of moulds in which you
cast sand, lessens its capacity for being cast in new
moulds. In this sense the memory is bottomless.
And yet the greater and more various any one’s
knowledge, the longer he takes to find out anything
that may suddenly be asked him; because he is like
a shopkeeper who has to get the article wanted from
a large and multifarious store; or, more strictly
speaking, because out of many possible trains of thought
he has to recall exactly that one which, as a result
of previous training, leads to the matter in question.
For the memory is not a repository of things you wish
to preserve, but a mere dexterity of the intellectual
powers; hence the mind always contains its sum of knowledge
only potentially, never actually.
It sometimes happens that my memory
will not reproduce some word in a foreign language,
or a name, or some artistic expression, although I
know it very well. After I have bothered myself
in vain about it for a longer or a shorter time, I
give up thinking about it altogether. An hour
or two afterwards, in rare cases even later still,
sometimes only after four or five weeks, the word
I was trying to recall occurs to me while I am thinking
of something else, as suddenly as if some one had
whispered it to me. After noticing this phenomenon
with wonder for very many years, I have come to think
that the probable explanation of it is as follows.
After the troublesome and unsuccessful search, my will
retains its craving to know the word, and so sets a
watch for it in the intellect. Later on, in the
course and play of thought, some word by chance occurs
having the same initial letters or some other resemblance
to the word which is sought; then the sentinel springs
forward and supplies what is wanting to make up the
word, seizes it, and suddenly brings it up in triumph,
without my knowing where and how he got it; so it
seems as if some one had whispered it to me. It
is the same process as that adopted by a teacher towards
a child who cannot repeat a word; the teacher just
suggests the first letter of the word, or even the
second too; then the child remembers it. In default
of this process, you can end by going methodically
through all the letters of the alphabet.
In the ordinary man, injustice rouses
a passionate desire for vengeance; and it has often
been said that vengeance is sweet. How many sacrifices
have been made just to enjoy the feeling of vengeance,
without any intention of causing an amount of injury
equivalent to what one has suffered. The bitter
death of the centaur Nessus was sweetened by the certainty
that he had used his last moments to work out an extremely
clever vengeance. Walter Scott expresses the same
human inclination in language as true as it is strong:
“Vengeance is the sweetest morsel to the mouth
that ever was cooked in hell!” I shall now attempt
a psychological explanation of it.
Suffering which falls to our lot in
the course of nature, or by chance, or fate, does
not, ceteris paribus, seem so painful as suffering
which is inflicted on us by the arbitrary will of
another. This is because we look upon nature
and chance as the fundamental masters of the world;
we see that the blow we received from them might just
as well have fallen on another. In the case of
suffering which springs from this source, we bewail
the common lot of humanity rather than our own misfortune.
But that it is the arbitrary will of another which
inflicts the suffering, is a peculiarly bitter addition
to the pain or injury it causes, viz., the consciousness
that some one else is superior to us, whether by force
or cunning, while we lie helpless. If amends are
possible, amends heal the injury; but that bitter
addition, “and it was you who did that to me,”
which is often more painful than the injury itself,
is only to be neutralized by vengeance. By inflicting
injury on the one who has injured us, whether we do
it by force or cunning, is to show our superiority
to him, and to annul the proof of his superiority to
us. That gives our hearts the satisfaction towards
which it yearns. So where there is a great deal
of pride and vanity, there also will there be a great
desire of vengeance. But as the fulfillment of
every wish brings with it more or less of a sense
of disappointment, so it is with vengeance. The
delight we hope to get from it is mostly embittered
by compassion. Vengeance taken will often tear
the heart and torment the conscience: the motive
to it is no longer active, and what remains is the
evidence of our malice.