By the ancients, Logic and Dialectic
were used as synonymous terms; although [Greek:
logizesthai], “to think over, to consider, to
calculate,” and [Greek: dialegesthai], “to
converse,” are two very different things.
The name Dialectic was, as we are
informed by Diogenes Laertius, first used by Plato;
and in the Phaedrus, Sophist, Republic, bk.
vii., and elsewhere, we find that by Dialectic he
means the regular employment of the reason, and skill
in the practice of it. Aristotle also uses the
word in this sense; but, according to Laurentius Valla,
he was the first to use Logic too in a similar way.
Dialectic, therefore, seems to be an older word than
Logic. Cicero and Quintilian use the words in
the same general signification.
This use of the words and synonymous
terms lasted through the Middle Ages into modern times;
in fact, until the present day. But more recently,
and in particular by Kant, Dialectic has often been
employed in a bad sense, as meaning “the art
of sophistical controversy”; and hence Logic
has been preferred, as of the two the more innocent
designation. Nevertheless, both originally meant
the same thing; and in the last few years they have
again been recognised as synonymous.
It is a pity that the words have thus
been used from of old, and that I am not quite at
liberty to distinguish their meanings. Otherwise,
I should have preferred to define Logic (from
[Greek: logos], “word” and “reason,”
which are inseparable) as “the science of the
laws of thought, that is, of the method of reason”;
and Dialectic (from [Greek: dialegesthai],
“to converse” and every conversation
communicates either facts or opinions, that is to say,
it is historical or deliberative) as “the art
of disputation,” in the modern sense of the
word. It it clear, then, that Logic deals with
a subject of a purely a priori character, separable
in definition from experience, namely, the laws of
thought, the process of reason or the [Greek:
logos], the laws, that is, which reason follows when
it is left to itself and not hindered, as in the case
of solitary thought on the part of a rational being
who is in no way misled. Dialectic, on the other
hand, would treat of the intercourse between two rational
beings who, because they are rational, ought to think
in common, but who, as soon as they cease to agree
like two clocks keeping exactly the same time, create
a disputation, or intellectual contest. Regarded
as purely rational beings, the individuals would, I
say, necessarily be in agreement, and their variation
springs from the difference essential to individuality;
in other words, it is drawn from experience.
Logic, therefore, as the science of
thought, or the science of the process of pure reason,
should be capable of being constructed a priori.
Dialectic, for the most part, can be constructed only
a posteriori; that is to say, we may learn
its rules by an experiential knowledge of the disturbance
which pure thought suffers through the difference
of individuality manifested in the intercourse between
two rational beings, and also by acquaintance with
the means which disputants adopt in order to make
good against one another their own individual thought,
and to show that it is pure and objective. For
human nature is such that if A. and B. are engaged
in thinking in common, and are communicating their
opinions to one another on any subject, so long as
it is not a mere fact of history, and A. perceives
that B.’s thoughts on one and the same subject
are not the same as his own, he does not begin by
revising his own process of thinking, so as to discover
any mistake which he may have made, but he assumes
that the mistake has occurred in B.’s.
In other words, man is naturally obstinate; and this
quality in him is attended with certain results, treated
of in the branch of knowledge which I should like to
call Dialectic, but which, in order to avoid misunderstanding,
I shall call Controversial or Eristical Dialectic.
Accordingly, it is the branch of knowledge which treats
of the obstinacy natural to man. Eristic is only
a harsher name for the same thing.
Controversial Dialectic is the art
of disputing, and of disputing in such a way as to
hold one’s own, whether one is in the right or
the wrong per fas et nefas. A
man may be objectively in the right, and nevertheless
in the eyes of bystanders, and sometimes in his own,
he may come off worst. For example, I may advance
a proof of some assertion, and my adversary may refute
the proof, and thus appear to have refuted the assertion,
for which there may, nevertheless, be other proofs.
In this case, of course, my adversary and I change
places: he comes off best, although, as a matter
of fact, he is in the wrong.
Aristotle divides all conclusions
into logical and dialectical, in the manner described,
and then into eristical. (3) Eristic is the
method by which the form of the conclusion is correct,
but the prémisses, the materials from which it
is drawn, are not true, but only appear to be true.
Finally (4) Sophistic is the method in which
the form of the conclusion is false, although it seems
correct. These three last properly belong to
the art of Controversial Dialectic, as they have no
objective truth in view, but only the appearance of
it, and pay no regard to truth itself; that is to
say, they aim at victory. Aristotle’s book
on Sophistic Conclusions was edited apart from
the others, and at a later date. It was the last
book of his Dialectic.]
If the reader asks how this is, I
reply that it is simply the natural baseness of human
nature. If human nature were not base, but thoroughly
honourable, we should in every debate have no other
aim than the discovery of truth; we should not in
the least care whether the truth proved to be in favour
of the opinion which we had begun by expressing, or
of the opinion of our adversary. That we should
regard as a matter of no moment, or, at any rate, of
very secondary consequence; but, as things are, it
is the main concern. Our innate vanity, which
is particularly sensitive in reference to our intellectual
powers, will not suffer us to allow that our first
position was wrong and our adversary’s right.
The way out of this difficulty would be simply to
take the trouble always to form a correct judgment.
For this a man would have to think before he spoke.
But, with most men, innate vanity is accompanied by
loquacity and innate dishonesty. They speak before
they think; and even though they may afterwards perceive
that they are wrong, and that what they assert is
false, they want it to seem the contrary. The
interest in truth, which may be presumed to have been
their only motive when they stated the proposition
alleged to be true, now gives way to the interests
of vanity: and so, for the sake of vanity, what
is true must seem false, and what is false must seem
true.
However, this very dishonesty, this
persistence in a proposition which seems false even
to ourselves, has something to be said for it.
It often happens that we begin with the firm conviction
of the truth of our statement; but our opponent’s
argument appears to refute it. Should we abandon
our position at once, we may discover later on that
we were right after all; the proof we offered was false,
but nevertheless there was a proof for our statement
which was true. The argument which would have
been our salvation did not occur to us at the moment.
Hence we make it a rule to attack a counter-argument,
even though to all appearances it is true and forcible,
in the belief that its truth is only superficial,
and that in the course of the dispute another argument
will occur to us by which we may upset it, or succeed
in confirming the truth of our statement. In this
way we are almost compelled to become dishonest; or,
at any rate, the temptation to do so is very great.
Thus it is that the weakness of our intellect and
the perversity of our will lend each other mutual support;
and that, generally, a disputant fights not for truth,
but for his proposition, as though it were a battle
pro aris et focis. He sets to work per
fas et nefas; nay, as we have seen, he cannot easily
do otherwise. As a rule, then, every man will
insist on maintaining whatever he has said, even though
for the moment he may consider it false or doubtful.
To some extent every man is armed
against such a procedure by his own cunning and villainy.
He learns by daily experience, and thus comes to have
his own natural Dialectic, just as he has his
own natural Logic. But his Dialectic is
by no means as safe a guide as his Logic. It
is not so easy for any one to think or draw an inference
contrary to the laws of Logic; false judgments are
frequent, false conclusions very rare. A man
cannot easily be deficient in natural Logic, but he
may very easily be deficient in natural Dialectic,
which is a gift apportioned in unequal measure.
In so far natural Dialectic resembles the faculty
of judgment, which differs in degree with every man;
while reason, strictly speaking, is the same.
For it often happens that in a matter in which a man
is really in the right, he is confounded or refuted
by merely superficial arguments; and if he emerges
victorious from a contest, he owes it very often not
so much to the correctness of his judgment in stating
his proposition, as to the cunning and address with
which he defended it.
Here, as in all other cases, the best
gifts are born with a man; nevertheless, much may
be done to make him a master of this art by practice,
and also by a consideration of the tactics which may
be used to defeat an opponent, or which he uses himself
for a similar purpose. Therefore, even though
Logic may be of no very real, practical use, Dialectic
may certainly be so; and Aristotle, too, seems to me
to have drawn up his Logic proper, or Analytic, as
a foundation and preparation for his Dialectic, and
to have made this his chief business. Logic is
concerned with the mere form of propositions; Dialectic,
with their contents or matter in a word,
with their substance. It was proper, therefore,
to consider the general form of all propositions before
proceeding to particulars.
Aristotle does not define the object
of Dialectic as exactly as I have done it here; for
while he allows that its principal object is disputation,
he declares at the same time that it is also the discovery
of truth. Again, he says, later on, that if, from
the philosophical point of view, propositions are
dealt with according to their truth, Dialectic regards
them according to their plausibility, or the measure
in which they will win the approval and assent of
others. He is aware that the objective truth of
a proposition must be distinguished and separated
from the way in which it is pressed home, and approbation
won for it; but he fails to draw a sufficiently sharp
distinction between these two aspects of the matter,
so as to reserve Dialectic for the latter alone.
The rules which he often gives for Dialectic contain
some of those which properly belong to Logic; and
hence it appears to me that he has not provided a clear
solution of the problem.
Eristic so far differs from Sophistic
that, while the master of Eristic aims at mere victory,
the Sophist looks to the reputation, and with it,
the monetary rewards which he will gain. But whether
a proposition is true in respect of its contents is
far too uncertain a matter to form the foundation
of the distinction in question; and it is a matter
on which the disputant least of all can arrive at
certainty; nor is it disclosed in any very sure form
even by the result of the disputation. Therefore,
when Aristotle speaks of Dialectic, we must
include in it Sophistic, Eristic, and Peirastic, and
define it as “the art of getting the best of
it in a dispute,” in which, unquestionably,
the safest plan is to be in the right to begin with;
but this in itself is not enough in the existing disposition
of mankind, and, on the other hand, with the weakness
of the human intellect, it is not altogether necessary.
Other expedients are required, which, just because
they are unnecessary to the attainment of objective
truth, may also be used when a man is objectively in
the wrong; and whether or not this is the case, is
hardly ever a matter of complete certainty.
I am of opinion, therefore, that a
sharper distinction should be drawn between Dialectic
and Logic than Aristotle has given us; that to Logic
we should assign objective truth as far as it is merely
formal, and that Dialectic should be confined to the
art of gaining one’s point, and contrarily,
that Sophistic and Eristic should not be distinguished
from Dialectic in Aristotle’s fashion, since
the difference which he draws rests on objective and
material truth; and in regard to what this is, we
cannot attain any clear certainty before discussion;
but we are compelled, with Pilate, to ask, What
is truth? For truth is in the depths, [Greek:
en butho hae halaetheia] (a saying of Democritus,
Diog. Laert., ix., 72). Two men often
engage in a warm dispute, and then return to their
homes each of the other’s opinion, which he
has exchanged for his own. It is easy to say that
in every dispute we should have no other aim than
the advancement of truth; but before dispute no one
knows where it is, and through his opponent’s
arguments and his own a man is misled.]
We must always keep the subject of
one branch of knowledge quite distinct from that of
any other. To form a clear idea of the province
of Dialectic, we must pay no attention to objective
truth, which is an affair of Logic; we must regard
it simply as the art of getting the best of it
in a dispute, which, as we have seen, is all the
easier if we are actually in the right. In itself
Dialectic has nothing to do but to show how a man
may defend himself against attacks of every kind,
and especially against dishonest attacks; and, in the
same fashion, how he may attack another man’s
statement without contradicting himself, or generally
without being defeated. The discovery of objective
truth must be separated from the art of winning acceptance
for propositions; for objective truth is an entirely
different matter: it is the business of sound
judgment, reflection and experience, for which there
is no special art.
Such, then, is the aim of Dialectic.
It has been defined as the Logic of appearance; but
the definition is a wrong one, as in that case it
could only be used to repel false propositions.
But even when a man has the right on his side, he
needs Dialectic in order to defend and maintain it;
he must know what the dishonest tricks are, in order
to meet them; nay, he must often make use of them
himself, so as to beat the enemy with his own weapons.
Accordingly, in a dialectical contest
we must put objective truth aside, or, rather, we
must regard it as an accidental circumstance, and
look only to the defence of our own position and the
refutation of our opponent’s.
In following out the rules to this
end, no respect should be paid to objective truth,
because we usually do not know where the truth lies.
As I have said, a man often does not himself know whether
he is in the right or not; he often believes it, and
is mistaken: both sides often believe it.
Truth is in the depths. At the beginning of a
contest each man believes, as a rule, that right is
on his side; in the course of it, both become doubtful,
and the truth is not determined or confirmed until
the close.
Dialectic, then, need have nothing
to do with truth, as little as the fencing master
considers who is in the right when a dispute leads
to a duel. Thrust and parry is the whole business.
Dialectic is the art of intellectual fencing; and
it is only when we so regard it that we can erect
it into a branch of knowledge. For if we take
purely objective truth as our aim, we are reduced
to mere Logic; if we take the maintenance of false
propositions, it is mere Sophistic; and in either
case it would have to be assumed that we were aware
of what was true and what was false; and it is seldom
that we have any clear idea of the truth beforehand.
The true conception of Dialectic is, then, that which
we have formed: it is the art of intellectual
fencing used for the purpose of getting the best of
it in a dispute; and, although the name Eristic
would be more suitable, it is more correct to call
it controversial Dialectic, Dialectica eristica.
Dialectic in this sense of the word
has no other aim but to reduce to a regular system
and collect and exhibit the arts which most men employ
when they observe, in a dispute, that truth is not
on their side, and still attempt to gain the day.
Hence, it would be very inexpedient to pay any regard
to objective truth or its advancement in a science
of Dialectic; since this is not done in that original
and natural Dialectic innate in men, where they strive
for nothing but victory. The science of Dialectic,
in one sense of the word, is mainly concerned to tabulate
and analyse dishonest stratagems, in order that in
a real debate they may be at once recognised and defeated.
It is for this very reason that Dialectic must admittedly
take victory, and not objective truth, for its aim
and purpose.
I am not aware that anything has been
done in this direction, although I have made inquiries
far and wide. It is, therefore, an uncultivated
soil. To accomplish our purpose, we must draw
from our experience; we must observe how in the debates
which often arise in our intercourse with our fellow-men
this or that stratagem is employed by one side or
the other. By finding out the common elements
in tricks repeated in different forms, we shall be
enabled to exhibit certain general stratagems which
may be advantageous, as well for our own use, as for
frustrating others if they use them.
What follows is to be regarded as a first attempt.