The poets, who forty years ago proclaimed
their intention of working a revolution in English
literature, and who have succeeded in their purpose,
recommended especially a more simple and truthful view
of nature. The established canons of poetry
were to be discarded as artificial; as to the matter,
the poet was to represent mere nature as he saw her;
as to form, he was to be his own law. Freedom
and nature were to be his watchwords.
No theory could be more in harmony
with the spirit of the age, and the impulse which
had been given to it by the burning words of Jean
Jacques Rousseau. The school which arose expressed
fairly the unrest and unruliness of the time, its
weariness of artificial restraint and unmeaning laws,
its craving after a nobler and a more earnest life,
its sense of a glory and mystery in the physical universe,
hidden from the poets of the two preceding centuries,
and now revealed by science. So far all was
hopeful. But it soon became apparent, that each
poet’s practical success in carrying out the
theory was, paradoxically enough, in inverse proportion
to his belief in it; that those who like Wordsworth,
Southey, and Keats, talked most about naturalness
and freedom, and most openly reprobated the school
of Pope, were, after all, least natural and least
free; that the balance of those excellences inclined
much more to those who, like Campbell, Rogers, Crabbe,
and Moore, troubled their heads with no theories, but
followed the best old models which they knew; and that
the rightful sovereign of the new Parnassus, Lord
Byron, protested against the new movement, while he
followed it; upheld to the last the models which it
was the fashion to decry, confessed to the last, in
poetry as in morals, “Video meliora proboque,
deteriora sequor,” and uttered again
and again prophecies of the downfall of English poetry
and English taste, which seem to be on the eve of
realisation.
Now no one will, we presume, be silly
enough to say that humanity has gained nothing by
all the very beautiful poetry which has been poured
out on it during the last thirty years in England.
Nevertheless, when we see poetry dying down among
us year by year, although the age is becoming year
by year more marvellous and inspiring, we have a right
to look for some false principle in a school which
has had so little enduring vitality, which seems now
to be able to perpetuate nothing of itself but its
vices.
The answer so easy twenty years ago,
that the new poetry was spoiled by an influx of German
bad taste, will hardly hold good now, except with
a very few very ignorant people. It is now known,
of course, that whatsoever quarrel Lessing, Schiller,
and Goethe may have had with Pope, it was not on account
of his being too severe an artist, but too loose a
one; not for being too classical, but not classical
enough; that English poets borrowed from them nothing
but their most boyish and immature types of thought,
and that these were reproduced, and laughed at here,
while the men themselves were writing works of a purity,
and loftiness, and completeness, unknown to the world except
in the writings of Milton for nearly two
centuries. This feature, however, of the new
German poetry, was exactly the one which no English
poet deigned to imitate, save Byron alone; on whom,
accordingly, Goethe always looked with admiration and
affection. But the rest went their way unheeding;
and if they have defects, those defects are their
own; for when they did copy the German taste, they,
for the most part, deliberately chose the evil, and
refused the good; and have their reward in a fame
which we believe will prove itself a very short-lived
one.
We cannot deny, however, that, in
spite of all faults, these men had a strength.
They have exercised an influence. And they have
done so by virtue of seeing a fact which more complete,
and in some cases more manly poets, did not see.
Strangely enough, Shelley, the man who was the greatest
sinner of them all against the canons of good taste,
was the man who saw that new fact, if not most clearly,
still most intensely, and who proclaimed it most boldly.
His influence, therefore, is outliving that of his
compeers, and growing and spreading, for good and
for evil; and will grow and spread for years to come,
as long as the present great unrest goes on smouldering
in men’s hearts, till the hollow settlement
of 1815 is burst asunder anew, and men feel that they
are no longer in the beginning of the end, but in
the end itself, and that this long thirty years’
prologue to the reconstruction of rotten Europe is
played out at last, and the drama itself begun.
Such is the way of Providence; the
race is not to the swift, nor the battle to the strong,
nor the prophecy to the wise. The Spirit bloweth
where He listeth, and sends on his errands those
who deny Him, rebel against Him profligates,
madmen, and hysterical Rousseaus, hysterical Shelleys,
uttering words like the east wind. He uses strange
tools in His cosmogony: but He does not use them
in vain. By bad men if not by good, by fools
if not by wise, God’s work is done, and done
right well.
There was, then, a strength and a
truth in all these men; and it was this that
more or less clearly, they all felt that they were
standing between two worlds; and the ruins of an older
age; upon the threshold of a new one. To Byron’s
mind, the decay and rottenness of the old was, perhaps,
the most palpable; to Shelley’s, the possible
glory of the new. Wordsworth declared a
little too noisily, we think, as if he had been the
first to discover the truth the dignity
and divineness of the most simple human facts and relationships.
Coleridge declares that the new can only assume living
form by growing organically out of the old institutions.
Keats gives a sad and yet a wholesome answer to them
both, as, young and passionate, he goes down with
Faust “to the Mothers”
To the rich warm youth of the nations,
Childlike in virtue and faith, though childlike in
passion and pleasure, Childlike still, still near
to the gods, while the sunset of Eden Lingered in
rose-red rays on the peaks of Ionian mountains.
And there, amid the old classic forms,
he cries: “These things, too, are eternal
A thing of beauty is a joy for ever.
These, or things even fairer than
they, must have their place in the new world, if it
is to be really a home for the human race.”
So he sings, as best he can, the half-educated and
consumptive stable-keeper’s son, from his prison-house
of London brick, and in one mighty yearn after that
beauty from which he is debarred, breaks his young
heart, and dies, leaving a name not “writ in
water,” as he dreamed, but on all fair things,
all lovers’ hearts, for evermore.
Here, then, to return, is the reason
why the hearts of the present generation have been
influenced so mightily by these men, rather than by
those of whom Byron wrote, with perfect sincerity:
Scott, Rogers, Campbell, Moore, and Crabbe will try
’Gainst you the question with posterity.
These lines, written in 1818, were
meant to apply only to Coleridge, Wordsworth, and
Southey. Whether they be altogether just or unjust
is not now the question. It must seem somewhat
strange to our young poets that Shelley’s name
is not among those who are to try the question of
immortality against the Lake School; and yet many of
his most beautiful poems had been already written.
Were, then, “The Revolt of Islam” and
“Alastor” not destined, it seems, in Byron’s
opinion, to live as long as the “Lady of the
Lake” and the “Mariners of England?”
Perhaps not. At least the omission of Shelley’s
name is noteworthy. But still more noteworthy
are these words of his to Mr. Murray, dated January
23, 1819:
“Read Pope most of
you don’t but do . . . and the inevitable
consequence would be, that you would burn all that
I have ever written, and all your other wretched Claudians
of the day (except Scott and Crabbe) into the bargain.”
And here arises a new question Is
Shelley, then, among the Claudians? It is a
hard saying. The present generation will receive
it with shouts of laughter. Some future one,
which studies and imitates Shakespeare instead of
anatomising him, and which gradually awakens to the
now forgotten fact, that a certain man named Edmund
Spenser once wrote a poem, the like of which the earth
never saw before, and perhaps may never see again,
may be inclined to acquiesce in the verdict, and believe
that Byron had a discrimination in this matter, as
in a hundred more, far more acute than any of his
compeers, and had not eaten in vain, poor fellow, of
the tree of the knowledge of good and evil.
In the meanwhile, we may perceive in the poetry of
the two men deep and radical differences, indicating
a spiritual difference between them even more deep,
which may explain the little notice which Byron takes
of Shelley’s poetry, and the fact that the two
men had no deep sympathy for each other, and could
not in any wise “pull together” during
the sojourn in Italy. Doubtless, there were
plain outward faults of temper and character on both
sides; neither was in a state of mind which could trust
itself, or be trusted by those who loved them best.
Friendship can only consist with the calm and self-restraint
and self-respect of moral and intellectual health;
and both were diseased, fevered, ready to take offence,
ready, unwittingly, to give it. But the diseases
of the two were different, as their natures were;
and Shelley’s fever was not Byron’s.
Now it is worth remarking, that it
is Shelley’s form of fever, rather than Byron’s,
which has been of late years the prevailing epidemic.
Since Shelley’s poems have become known in England,
and a timid public, after approaching in fear and
trembling the fountain which was understood to be
poisoned, has begun first to sip, and then, finding
the magic water at all events sweet enough, to quench
its thirst with unlimited draughts, Byron’s
fiercer wine has lost favour. Well at
least the taste of the age is more refined, if that
be matter of congratulation. And there is an
excuse for preferring champagne to waterside porter,
heady with grains of paradise and quassia, salt
and cocculus indicus. Nevertheless, worse ingredients
than oenanthic acid may lurk in the delicate draught,
and the Devil’s Elixir may be made fragrant,
and sweet, and transparent enough, as French moralists
well know, for the most fastidious palate. The
private sipping of eua-de-cologne, say the London physicians,
has increased mightily of late; and so has the reading
of Shelley. It is not surprising. Byron’s
Corsairs and Laras have been, on the whole, impossible
during the thirty years’ peace! and piracy and
profligacy are at all times, and especially nowadays,
expensive amusements, and often require a good private
fortune rare among poets. They have,
therefore, been wisely abandoned as ideals, except
among a few young persons, who used to wear turn-down
collars, and are now attempting moustaches and Mazzini
hats. But even among them, and among their betters rather
their more-respectables nine-tenths
of the bad influence which is laid at Byron’s
door really is owing to Shelley. Among the many
good-going gentlemen and ladies, Byron is generally
spoken of with horror he is “so wicked,”
forsooth; while poor Shelley, “poor dear Shelley,”
is “very wrong, of course,” but “so
refined,” “so beautiful,” “so
tender” a fallen angel, while Byron
is a satyr and a devil. We boldly deny the verdict.
Neither of the two are devils; as for angels, when
we have seen one, we shall be better able to give
an opinion; at present, Shelley is in our eyes far
less like one of those old Hebrew and Miltonic angels,
fallen or unfallen, than Byron is. And as for
the satyr; the less that is said for Shelley, on that
point, the better. If Byron sinned more desperately
and flagrantly than he, it was done under the temptations
of rank, wealth, disappointed love, and under the
impulses of an animal nature, to which Shelley’s
passions were
As moonlight unto sunlight, and as water unto wine.
At all events, Byron never set to
work to consecrate his own sin into a religion and
proclaim the worship of uncleanness as the last and
highest ethical development of “pure” humanity.
No Byron may be brutal; but he never cants.
If at moments he finds himself in hell, he never
turns round to the world and melodiously informs them
that it is heaven, if they could but see it in its
true light.
The truth is, that what has put Byron
out of favour with the public of late has been not
his faults but his excellences. His artistic
good taste, his classical polish, his sound shrewd
sense, his hatred of cant, his insight into humbug
above all, his shallow, pitiable habit of being always
intelligible these are the sins which condemn
him in the eyes of a mesmerising, table-turning, spirit-rapping,
spiritualising, Romanising generation, who read Shelley
in secret, and delight in his bad taste, mysticism,
extravagance, and vague and pompous sentimentalism.
The age is an effeminate one, and it can well afford
to pardon the lewdness of the gentle and sensitive
vegetarian, while it has no mercy for that of the sturdy
peer proud of his bull neck and his boxing, who kept
bears and bull-dogs, drilled Greek ruffians at Missoloughi,
and “had no objection to a pot of beer;”
and who might, if he had reformed, have made a gallant
English gentleman; while Shelley, if once his intense
self-opinion had deserted him, would have probably
ended in Rome as an Oratorian or a Passionist.
We would that it were only for this
count that Byron has had to make way for Shelley.
There is, as we said before, a deeper moral difference
between the men, which makes the weaker, rather than
the stronger, find favour in young men’s eyes.
For Byron has the most intense and awful sense of
moral law of law external to himself.
Shelley has little or none; less, perhaps, than any
known writer who has ever meddled with moral questions.
Byron’s cry is, I am miserable because law
exists; and I have broken it, broken it so habitually,
that now I cannot help breaking it. I have tried
to eradicate the sense of it by speculation, by action;
but I cannot
The tree of knowledge is not the tree of life.
There is a moral law independent of
us, and yet the very marrow of our life, which punishes
and rewards us by no arbitrary external penalties,
but by our own consciousness of being what we are:
The mind which is immortal, makes itself
Requital for its good or evil thoughts;
Is its own origin of ill, and end
And its own place and time its innate sense
When stript of this mortality derives
No colour from the fleeting things about,
But is absorbed in sufferance or in joy,
Born from the knowledge of its own desert.
This idea, confused, intermitted,
obscured by all forms of evil for it was
not discovered, but only in the process of discovery is
the one which comes out with greater and greater strength,
through all Corsairs, Laras, and Parasinas, till it
reaches its completion in “Cain” and in
“Manfred,” of both of which we do boldly
say, that if any sceptical poetry at all be right,
which we often question, they are right and not wrong;
that in “Cain,” as in “Manfred,”
the awful problem which, perhaps, had better not have
been put at all, is nevertheless fairly put, and the
solution, as far as it is seen, fairly confessed;
namely, that there is an absolute and eternal law
in the heart of man which sophistries of his own or
of other beings may make him forget, deny, blaspheme;
but which exists eternally, and will assert itself.
If this be not the meaning of “Manfred,”
especially of that great scene in the chamois hunter’s
cottage, what is? If this be not the meaning
of “Cain,” and his awful awakening after
the murder, not to any mere dread of external punishment,
but to an overwhelming, instinctive, inarticulate
sense of having done wrong, what is?
Yes; that law exists, let it never
be forgotten, is the real meaning of Byron, down to
that last terrible “Don Juan,” in which
he sits himself down, in artificial calm, to trace
the gradual rotting and degradation of a man without
law, the slave of his own pleasures; a picture happily
never finished, because he who painted it was taken
away before he had learnt, perhaps when he was beginning
to turn back from the lower depth within
the lowest deep.
Now to this whole form of consciousness,
poor Shelley’s mind is altogether antipodal.
His whole life through was a denial of external law,
and a substitution in its place of internal sentiment.
Byron’s cry is: There is a law, and therefore
I am miserable. Why cannot I keep the law?
Shelley’s is: There is a law, and therefore
I am miserable. Why should not the law be abolished? Away
with it, for it interferes with my sentiments Away
with marriage, “custom and faith, the foulest
birth of time.” We do not wish to
follow him down into the fearful sins which he defended
with the small powers of reasoning and
they were peculiarly small which he possessed.
Let any one who wishes to satisfy himself of the
real difference between Byron’s mind and Shelley’s,
compare the writings in which each of them treats
the same subject namely, that frightful
question about the relation of the sexes, which forms,
evidently, Manfred’s crime; and see if the result
is not simply this, that Shelley glorifies what Byron
damns. “Lawless love” is Shelley’s
expressed ideal of the relation of the sexes; and
his justice, his benevolence, his pity, are all equally
lawless. “Follow your instincts,”
is his one moral rule, confounding the very lowest
animal instincts with those lofty ideas of might,
which it was the will of Heaven that he should retain,
ay, and love, to the very last, and so reducing them
all to the level of sentiments. “Follow
your instincts” But what if our instincts
lead us to eat animal food? “Then you must
follow the instincts of me, Percy Bysshe Shelley.
I think it horrible, cruel; it offends my taste.”
What if our instincts lead us to tyrannise over our
fellow-men? “Then you must repress those
instincts. I, Shelley, think that, too, horrible
and cruel.” Whether it be vegetarianism
or liberty, the rule is practically the same sentiment
which, in his case, as in the case of all sentimentalists,
turns out to mean at last, not the sentiments of mankind
in general, but the private sentiments of the writer.
This is Shelley; a sentimentalist pure and simple;
incapable of anything like inductive reasoning; unable
to take cognisance of any facts but those which please
his taste, or to draw any conclusion from them but
such as also pleases his taste; as, for example, in
that eighth stanza of the “Ode to Liberty,”
which, had it been written by any other man but Shelley,
possessing the same knowledge as he, one would have
called a wicked and deliberate lie but
in his case, is to be simply passed over with a sigh,
like a young lady’s proofs of table-turning and
rapping spirits. She wished to see it so and
therefore so she saw it.
For Shelley’s nature is utterly
womanish. Not merely his weak points, but his
strong ones, are those of a woman. Tender and
pitiful as a woman; and yet, when angry, shrieking,
railing, hysterical as a woman. The physical
distaste for meat and fermented liquors, coupled with
the hankering after physical horrors, are especially
feminine. The nature of a woman looks out of
that wild, beautiful, girlish face the
nature: but not the spirit; not
The reason firm, the temperate will,
Endurance, foresight, strength and skill.
The lawlessness of the man, with the
sensibility of the woman. . . . Alas for him!
He, too, might have discovered what Byron did; for
were not his errors avenged upon him within, more terribly
even than without? His cries are like the wails
of a child, inarticulate, peevish, irrational; and
yet his pain fills his whole being, blackens the very
face of nature to him: but he will not confess
himself in the wrong. Once only, if we recollect
rightly, the truth flashes across him for a moment,
and the clouds of selfish sorrow:
Alas, I have nor hope nor health,
Nor peace within, nor calm around;
Nor that content surpassing wealth
The sage in meditation found,
And walked with inward glory crowned.
“Nor” alas
for the spiritual bathos, which follows that short
gleam of healthy feeling, and coming to himself
fame nor power, nor
love, nor leisure,
Others I see whom these surround,
Smiling they live and call life
pleasure,
To me that cup has been dealt in another measure!
Poor Shelley! As if the peace
within, and the calm around, and the content surpassing
wealth, were things which were to be put in the same
category with fame, and power, and love, and leisure.
As if they were things which could be “dealt”
to any man; instead of depending (as Byron, who, amid
all his fearful sins, was a man, knew well enough)
upon a man’s self, a man’s own will, and
that will exerted to do a will exterior to itself,
to know and to obey a law. But no, the cloud
of sentiment must close over again, and
Yet now despair itself is mild
Even as the winds and waters are;
I could lie down like a tired child,
And weep away this life of care,
Which I have borne, and still must bear,
Till death like sleep might seize
on me,
And I might feel in the warm air,
My cheek grow cold, and hear the
sea
Breathe o’er my dying brain its last monotony!
Too beautiful to laugh at, however
empty and sentimental. True: but why beautiful?
Because there is a certain sincerity in it, which
breeds coherence and melody, which, in short, makes
it poetry. But what if such a tone of mind be
consciously encouraged, even insincerely affected
as the ideal state for a poet’s mind, as his
followers have done?
The mischief which such a man would
do is conceivable enough. He stands out, both
by his excellences and his defects, as the spokesman
and ideal of all the unrest and unhealth of sensitive
young men for many a year after. His unfulfilled
prophecies only help to increase that unrest.
Who shall blame either him for uttering those prophecies,
or them for longing for their fulfilment? Must
we not thank the man who gives us fresh hope that
this earth will not be always as it is now?
His notion of what it will be may be, as Shelley’s
was, vague, even in some things wrong and undesirable.
Still, we must accept his hope and faith in the spirit,
not in the letter. So have thousands of young
men felt, who would have shrunk with disgust from
some of poor Shelley’s details of the “good
time coming.” And shame on him who should
wish to rob them of such a hope, even if it interfered
with his favourite “scheme of unfulfilled prophecy.”
So men have felt Shelley’s spell a wondrous
one perhaps, they think, a life-giving
regenerative one. And yet what dream at once
more shallow and more impossible? Get rid of
kings and priests; marriage may stay, pending discussions
on the rights of women. Let the poet speak what
he is to say being, of course, a matter of utterly
secondary import, provided only that he be a poet;
and then the millennium will appear of itself, and
the devil be exorcised with a kiss from all hearts except,
of course, these of “pale priests” and
“tyrants with their sneer of cold command”
(who, it seems, have not been got rid of after all),
and the Cossacks and Croats whom they may choose to
call to their rescue. And on the appearance of
the said Cossacks and Croats, the poet’s vision
stops short, and all is blank beyond. A recipe
for the production of millenniums which has this one
advantage, that it is small enough to be comprehended
by the very smallest minds, and reproduced thereby,
with a difference, in such spasmodic melodies as seem
to those small minds to be imitations of Shelley’s
nightingale notes.
For nightingale notes they truly are.
In spite of all his faults and there
are few poetic faults in which he does not indulge,
to their very highest power in spite of
his “interfluous” and “innumerous,”
and the rest of his bad English in spite
of bombast, horrors, maundering, sheer stuff and nonsense
of all kinds, there is a plaintive natural melody
about this man, such as no other English poet has
ever uttered, except Shakespeare in some few immortal
songs. Who that has read Shelley does not recollect
scraps worthy to stand by Ariel’s song chaste,
simple, unutterably musical? Yes, when he will
be himself Shelley the scholar and the gentleman
and the singer and leave philosophy and
politics, which he does not understand, and shriekings
and cursings, which are unfit for any civilised and
self-respecting man, he is perfect. Like the
American mocking-bird, he is harsh only when aping
other men’s tunes his true power
lies in his own “native wood-notes wild.”
But it is not this faculty of his
which has been imitated by his scholars; for it is
not this faculty which made him their ideal, however
it may have attracted them. All which sensible
men deplore in him is that which poetasters have exalted
in him. His morbidity and his doubt have become
in their eyes his differential energy, because too
often, it was all in him with which they had wit to
sympathise. They found it easy to curse and complain,
instead of helping to mend. So had he.
They found it pleasant to confound institutions with
the abuses which defaced them. So had he.
They found it pleasant to give way to their spleen.
So had he. They found it pleasant to believe
that the poet was to regenerate the world, without
having settled with what he was to regenerate it.
So had he. They found it more pleasant to obey
sentiment than inductive laws. So had he.
They found it more pleasant to hurl about enormous
words and startling figures than to examine reverently
the awful depths of beauty which lie in the simplest
words and the severest figures. So had he.
And thus arose a spasmodic, vague,
extravagant, effeminate, school of poetry, which has
been too often hastily and unfairly fathered upon
Byron. Doubtless Byron has helped to its formation;
but only in as far as his poems possess, or rather
seem to possess, elements in common with Shelley’s.
For that conscious struggle against law, by which
law is discovered, may easily enough be confounded
with the utter repudiation of it. Both forms
of mind will discuss the same questions; both will
discuss them freely, with a certain plainness and
daring, which may range through all grades, from the
bluntness of Socrates down to reckless immodesty and
profaneness. The world will hardly distinguish
between the two; it did not in Socrates’ case,
mistaking his reverent irreverence for Atheism, and
martyred him accordingly, as it has since martyred
Luther’s memory. Probably, too, if a living
struggle is going on in the writer’s mind, he
will not have distinguished the two elements in himself;
he will be profane when he fancies himself only arguing
for truth; he will be only arguing for truth, where
he seems to the respectable undoubting to be profane.
And in the meanwhile, whether the respectable understand
him or not, the young and the inquiring, much more
the distempered, who would be glad to throw off moral
law, will sympathise with him often more than he sympathises
with himself. Words thrown off in the heat of
passion; shameful self-revealings which he has written
with his very heart’s blood: ay, even fallacies
which he has put into the mouths of dramatic characters
for the very purpose of refuting them, or at least
of calling on all who read to help him to refute them,
and to deliver him from the ugly dream all
these will, by the lazy, the frivolous, the feverish,
the discontented, be taken for integral parts and
noble traits of the man to whom they are attracted,
by finding that he, too, has the same doubts and struggles
as themselves, that he has a voice and art to be their
spokesman. And hence arises confusion on confusion,
misconception on misconception. The man is honoured
for his dishonour. Chronic disease is taken
for a new type of health; and Byron is admired and
imitated for that which Byron is trying to tear out
of his own heart, and trample under foot as his curse
and bane, something which is not Byron’s self,
but Byron’s house-fiend, and tyrant, and shame.
And in the meanwhile that which calls itself respectability
and orthodoxy, and is unless Augustine lied neither
of them, stands by; and instead of echoing the voice
of Him who said: “Come to me ye that are
weary and heavy laden, and I will give you rest,”
mumbles proudly to itself, with the Pharisees of old:
“This people, which knoweth not the law, is
accursed.”
We do not seek to excuse Byron any
more than we do Shelley. They both sinned.
They both paid bitter penalty for their sin.
How far they were guilty, or which of them was the
more guilty, we know not. We can judge no man.
It is as poets and teachers, not as men and responsible
spirits; not in their inward beings, known only to
Him who made them, not even to themselves, but in
their outward utterance, that we have a right to compare
them. Both have done harm. Neither have,
we firmly believe, harmed any human being who had
not already the harm within himself. It is not
by introducing evil, but by calling into consciousness
and more active life evil which was already lurking
in the heart, that any writer makes men worse.
Thousands doubtless have read Byron and Shelley, and
worse books, and have risen from them as pure as when
they sat down. In evil as well as in good, the
eye only sees that which it brings with it the power
of seeing say rather, the wish to see.
But it is because, in spite of all our self-glorifying
pæans, our taste has become worse and not better,
that Shelley, the man who conceitedly despises and
denies law, is taking the place of Byron, the man who
only struggles against it, and who shows his honesty
and his greatness most by confessing that his struggles
are ineffectual; that, Titan as he may look to the
world, his strength is misdirected, a mere furious
weakness, which proclaims him a slave in fetters,
while prurient young gentlemen are fancying him heaping
hills on hills, and scaling Olympus itself.
They are tired of that notion, however, now.
They have begun to suspect that Byron did not scale
Olympus after all. How much more pleasant a leader,
then, must Shelley be, who unquestionably did scale
his little Olympus having made it himself
first to fit his own stature. The man who has
built the hay-rick will doubtless climb it again,
if need be, as often as desired, and whistle on the
top, after the fashion of the rick-building guild,
triumphantly enough. For after all Shelley’s
range of vision is very narrow, his subjects few,
his reflections still fewer, when compared, not only
with such a poet as Spenser, but with his own contemporaries;
above all with Byron. He has a deep heart, but
not a wide one; an intense eye, but not a catholic
one. And, therefore, he never wrote a real drama;
for in spite of all that has been said to the contrary,
Beatrice Cenci is really none other than Percy Bysshe
Shelley himself in petticoats.
But we will let them both be.
Perhaps they know better now.
One very ugly superstition, nevertheless,
we must mention, of which these two men have been,
in England at least, the great hierophants; namely,
the right of “genius” to be “eccentric.”
Doubtless there are excuses for such a notion; but
it is one against which every wise man must set his
face like a flint; and at the risk of being called
a “Philister” and a “flunky,”
take part boldly with respectability and this wicked
world, and declare them to be for once utterly in the
right. Still there are excuses for it.
A poet, especially one who wishes to be not merely
a describer of pretty things, but a “Vates”
and seer of new truth, must often say things which
other people do not like to say, and do things which
others do not like to do. And, moreover, he
will be generally gifted, for the very purpose of
enabling him to say and do these strange things, with
a sensibility more delicate than common, often painful
enough to himself. How easy for such a man to
think that he has a right not to be as other men are;
to despise little conventionalities, courtesies, even
decencies; to offend boldly and carelessly, conscious
that he has something right and valuable within himself
which not only atones for such defects, but allows
him to indulge in them, as badges of his own superiority!
This has been the notion of artistic genius which
has spread among us of late years, just in proportion
as the real amount of artistic genius has diminished;
till we see men, on the mere ground of being literary
men, too refined to keep accounts, or pay their butchers’
bills; affecting the pettiest absurdities in dress,
in manner, in food; giving themselves credit for being
unable to bear a noise, keep their temper, educate
their own children, associate with their fellow-men;
and a thousand other paltry weaknesses, morosenesses,
self-indulgences, fastidiousnesses, vulgarities for
all this is essentially vulgar, and demands, not honour
and sympathy, but a chapter in Mr. Thackeray’s
“Book of Snobs.” Non sic itur ad
astra. Self-indulgence and exclusiveness can
only be a proof of weakness. It may accompany
talent, but it proves that talent to be partial and
defective. The brain may be large, but the manhood,
the “virtus,” is small, where such
things are allowed, much more where they are gloried
in. A poet such a man may be, but a world poet
never. He is sectarian, a poetical Quaker, a
Puritan, who, forgetting that the truth which he possesses
is equally the right and inheritance of every man
he meets, takes up a peculiar dress or phraseology,
as symbols of his fancied difference from his human
brothers. All great poets, till Shelley and Byron,
as far as we can discern, have been men especially
free from eccentricities; careful not merely of the
chivalries and the respectabilities, but also of the
courtesies and the petty conventionalities, of the
age in which they lived; altogether well-bred men
of the world. The answer, that they learnt the
ways of courts, does not avail; for if they had had
no innate good-breeding, reticence, respect for forms
and customs, they would never have come near courts
at all. It is not a question of rank and fashion,
but of good feeling, common sense, unselfishness.
Goethe, Milton, Spenser, Shakespeare, Rabelais, Ariosto,
were none of them high-born men; several of them low-born;
who only rose to the society of high-horn men because
they were themselves innately high-bred, polished,
complete, without exaggerations, affectations, deformities,
weaknesses of mind and taste, whatever may have been
their weaknesses on certain points of morals.
The man of all men most bepraised by the present generation
of poets, is perhaps Wolfgang von Goethe. Why
is it, then, that of all men he is the one whom they
strive to be most unlike?
And if this be good counsel for the
man who merely wishes and no blame to him to
sing about beautiful things in a beautiful way, it
applies with tenfold force to the poet who desires
honestly to proclaim great truths. If he has
to offend the prejudices of the world in important
things, that is all the more reason for his bowing
to those prejudices in little things, and being content
to be like his neighbours in outward matters, in order
that he may make them like himself in inward ones.
Shall such a man dare to hinder his own message,
to drive away the very hearers to whom he believes
himself to be sent, for the sake of his own nerves,
laziness, antipathies, much more of his own vanity
and pride? If he does so, he is unfaithful to
that very genius on which he prides himself.
He denies its divinity, by treating it as his own
possession, to be displayed or hidden as he chooses,
for his own enjoyment, his own self-glorification.
Well for such a man if a day comes to him in which
he will look back with shame and self-reproach, not
merely on every scandal which he may have caused by
breaking the moral and social laws of humanity, by
neglecting to restrain his appetites, pay his bills,
and keep his engagements; but also on every conceited
word and look, every gaucherie and rudeness, every
self-indulgent moroseness and fastidiousness, as sins
against the sacred charge which has been committed
to him; and determine with that Jew of old, who, to
judge from his letter to Philemon, was one of the
most perfect gentlemen of God’s making who ever
walked this earth, to become “all things to all
men, if by any means he may save some.”