INTRODUCTION
Every child that is born is born of
a community and into a community, which existed before
his birth and will continue to exist after his death.
He learns to speak the language which the community
spoke before he was born, and which the community
will continue to speak after he has gone. In
learning the language he acquires not only words but
ideas; and the words and ideas he acquires, the thoughts
he thinks and the words in which he utters them, are
those of the community from which he learnt them,
which taught them before he was born and will go on
teaching them after he is dead. He not only learns
to speak the words and think the ideas, to reproduce
the mode of thought, as he does the form of speech,
of the circumambient community: he is taught
and learns to act as those around him do as
the community has done and will tend to do. The
community the narrower community of the
family, first, and, afterwards, the wider community
to which the family belongs teaches him
how he ought to speak, what he ought to think, and
how he ought to act. The consciousness of the
child reproduces the consciousness of the community
to which he belongs the common consciousness,
which existed before him and will continue to exist
after him.
The common consciousness is not only
the source from which the individual gets his mode
of speech, thought and action, but the court of appeal
which decides what is fact. If a question is raised
whether the result of a scientific experiment is what
it is alleged by the original maker of the experiment
to be, the appeal is to the common consciousness:
any one who chooses to make the experiment in the way
described will find the result to be of the kind alleged;
if everyone else, on experiment, finds it to be so,
it is established as a fact of common consciousness;
if no one else finds it to be so, the alleged discovery
is not a fact but an erroneous inference.
Now, it is not merely with regard
to external facts or facts apprehended through the
senses, that the common consciousness is accepted
as the court of appeal. The allegation may be
that an emotion, of a specified kind alarm
or fear, wonder or awe is, in specified
circumstances, experienced as a fact of the common
consciousness. Or a body of men may have a common
purpose, or a common idea, as well as an emotion of,
say, common alarm. If the purpose, idea or emotion,
be common to them and experienced by all of them, it
is a fact of their common consciousness. In this
case, as in the case of any alleged but disputed discovery
in science, the common consciousness is the court
of appeal which decides the facts, and determines
whether what an individual thinks he has discovered
in his consciousness is really a fact of the common
consciousness. The idea of powers superior to
man, the emotion of awe or reverence, which goes with
the idea, and the purpose of communicating with the
power in question are facts, not peculiar to this
or that individual consciousness, but facts of the
common consciousness of all mankind.
The child up to a certain age has
no consciousness of self: the absence of self-consciousness
is one of the charms of children. The child imitates
its elders, who speak of him and to him by his name.
He speaks of himself in the third person and not in
the first person singular, and designates himself
by his proper name and not by means of the personal
pronoun ‘I’; eventually the child acquires
the use and to some extent learns the meaning of the
first personal pronoun; that is, if the language of
the community to which he belongs has developed so
far as to have produced such a pronoun. For there
was a period in the evolution of speech when, as yet,
a first personal pronoun had not been evolved; and
that, probably, for the simple reason that the idea
which it denotes was as unknown to the community as
it is to the child whose absence of self-consciousness
is so pleasing. For a period, the length of which
may have been millions of years, the common consciousness,
the consciousness of the community, did not discover
or discriminate, in language or in thought, the existence
of the individual self.
The importance of this consideration
lies in its bearing upon the question, in what form
the idea of powers superior to man disclosed itself
in the common consciousness at that period. It
is held by many students of the science of religion
that fetishism preceded polytheism in the history
of religion; and it is undoubted that polytheism flourished
at the expense of fetishism. But what is exactly
the difference between fetishism and polytheism?
No one now any longer holds that a fetish is regarded,
by believers in fetish, as a material object and nothing
more: everyone recognises that the material object
to which the term is applied is regarded as the habitation
of a spiritual being. The material object in
question is to the fetish what the idol of a god is
to a god. If the material object, through which,
or in which, the fetish-spirit manifests itself, bears
no resemblance to human form, neither do the earliest
stocks or blocks in which gods manifest themselves
bear any resemblance to human form. Such unshaped
stocks do not of themselves tell us whether they are
fetishes or gods to their worshippers. The test
by which the student of the science of religion determines
the question is a very simple one: it is, who
worships the object in question? If the object
is the private property of some individual, it is
fetish; if it is worshipped by the community as a
whole, it, or rather the spirit which manifests itself
therein, is a god of the community. The functions
of the two beings differ accordingly: the god
receives the prayers of the community and has power
to grant them; the fetish has power to grant the wishes
of the individual who owns it. The consequence
of this difference in function is that as the wishes
of the individual may be inconsistent with the welfare
of other members of the community; as the fetish may
be, and actually is, used to procure injury and death
to other members of the community; a fetish is anti-social
and a danger to the community, whereas a god of the
community is there expressly as a refuge and a help
for the community. The fetish fulfils the desires
of the individual, the self; the god listens to the
prayers of the community.
Let us now return to that stage in
the evolution of the community when, as yet, neither
the language nor the thought of the community had
discovered or discriminated the existence of the individual
self. If at that stage there was in the common
consciousness any idea, however dim or confused, of
powers superior to man; if that idea was accompanied
or coloured by any emotion, whether of fear or awe
or reverence; if that emotion prompted action of any
kind; then, such powers were not conceived to be fetishes,
for the function of a fetish is to fulfil the desires
of an individual self; and until the existence of
the individual self is realised, there is no function
for a fetish to perform.
It may well be that the gradual development
of self-consciousness, and the slow steps by which
language helped to bring forth the idea of self, were
from the first, and throughout, accompanied by the
gradual development of the idea of fetishism.
But the very development of the idea of a power which
could fulfil the desires of self, as distinguished
from, and often opposed to, the interests of the community,
would stimulate the growth of the idea of a power whose
special and particular function was to tend the interests
of the community as a whole. Thus the idea of
a fetish and the idea of a god could only persist
on condition of becoming more and more inconsistent
with, and contradictory of, one another. If the
lines followed by the two ideas started from the same
point, it was only to diverge the more, the further
they were pursued. And the tendency of fetishism
to disappear from the later and higher stages of religion
is sufficient to show that it did not afford an adequate
or satisfactory expression of the idea contained in
the common consciousness of some power or being greater
than man. That idea is constantly striving, throughout
the history of religion, to find or give expression
to itself; it is constantly discovering that such
expressions as it has found for itself do it wrong;
and it is constantly throwing, or in the process of
throwing, such expressions aside. Fetishism was
thrown aside sooner than polytheism: for it was
an expression not only inadequate but contradictory
to the idea that gave it birth. The emotions of
fear and suspicion, with which the community regarded
fetishes, were emotions different from the awe or
reverence with which the community approached its
gods.
What practically provokes and stimulates
the individual’s dawning consciousness of himself,
or the community’s consciousness of the individual
as in a way distinct from itself, is the dash between
the desires, wishes, interests of the one, and the
desires, wishes and interests of the other. But
though the interests of the one are sometimes at variance
with those of the other, still in some cases, also,
the interests of the individual even though
they be purely individual interests are
not inconsistent with those of the community; and
in most cases they are identical with them the
individual promotes his own interests by serving those
of the community, and promotes those of the community
by serving his own. In a word, the interests
of the one are not so clearly and plainly cut off
from those of the other, that the individual can always
be condemned for seeking to gratify his self-interests
or his own personal desires. That is presumably
one reason why fetishism is so wide-spread and so
long-lived in Western Africa, for instance: though
fetishes may be used for anti-social purposes, they
may be and are also used for purposes which if selfish
are not, or are not felt to be, anti-social.
The individual owner of a fetish does not feel that
his ownership does or ought to cut him off from membership
of the community. And so long as such feeling
is common, so long an indecisive struggle between
gods and fetishes continues.
Now this same cause the
impossibility of condemning the individual for seeking
to promote his own interests will be found
on examination to be operative elsewhere, viz.
in magic. The relation of magic to religion is
as much a matter of doubt and dispute as is that of
fetishism to religion. And I propose to treat
magic in much the same way as I have treated fetishism.
The justification which I offer for so doing is to
be found in the parallel or analogy that may be drawn
between them. The distinction which comes to be
drawn within the common consciousness between the
self and the community manifests itself obviously
in the fact that the interests and desires of the
individual are felt to be different, and yet not to
be different, from those of the community; and so
they are felt to be, yet not to be, condemnable from
the point of view of the common consciousness.
Now, this is precisely the judgment which is passed
upon magic, wherever it is cultivated. It is
condemnable, it is viewed with suspicion, fear and
condemnation; and yet it is also and at the same time
viewed and practised with general approval. It
may be used on behalf of the community and for the
good of the community, and with public approval, as
it is when it is used to make the rain which the community
needs. It may be viewed with toleration, as it
is when it is believed to benefit an individual without
entailing injury on the community. But it is
visited with condemnation, and perhaps with punishment,
when it is employed for purposes, such as murder,
which the common consciousness condemns. Accordingly
the person who has the power to work the marvels comprehended
under the name of magic is viewed with condemnation,
toleration or approval, according as he uses his power
for purposes which the common consciousness condemns,
tolerates or approves. The power which such a
person exerts is power personal to him; and yet it
is in a way a power greater and other than himself,
for he has it not always under his control or command:
whether he uses it for the benefit of the community
or for the injury of some individual, he cannot count
on its always coming off. And this fact is not
without its influence and consequences. If he
is endeavouring to use it for the injury of some person,
he will explain his failure as due to some error he
has committed in the modus operandi, or to the
counter-operations of some rival. But if he is
endeavouring to exercise it for the benefit of the
community, failure makes others doubtful whether he
has the power to act on behalf of the community; while,
on the contrary, a successful issue makes it clear
that he has the power, and places him, in the opinion
both of the community and of himself, in an exceptional
position: his power is indeed in a way personal
to himself, but it is also greater and other than himself.
His sense of it, and the community’s sense of
it, is reinforced and augmented by the approval of
the common consciousness, and by the feeling that
a power, in harmony with the common consciousness and
the community’s desires, is working in him and
through him. This power, thus exercised, of working
marvels for the common good is obviously more closely
analogous to that of a prophet working miracles, than
it is to that of the witch working injury or death.
And, in the same way that I have already suggested
that gods and fetishes may have been evolved from
a prior indeterminate concept, which was neither but
might become either; so I would now suggest that miracles
are not magic, nor is magic miracles, but that the
two have been differentiated from a common source.
And if the polytheistic gods, which are to be found
where fetishism is believed in, present us with a
very low stage in the development of the idea of a
’perfect personality,’ so too the sort
of miracles which are believed in, where the belief
in magic flourishes, present us with a very low stage
in the development of the idea of an almighty God.
Axe-heads that float must have belonged originally
to such a low stage; and rods that turn into serpents
were the property of the ‘magicians of Egypt’
as well as of Aaron.
The common source, then, from which
flows the power of working marvels for the community’s
good, or of working magic in the interest of one individual
member and perhaps to the injury of another, is a personal
power, which in itself that is to say, apart
from the intention with which it is used and apart
from the consequences which ensue is neither
commendable nor condemnable from the community’s
point of view; and which consequently can neither
be condemned nor commended by the common consciousness,
until the difference between self and the community
has become manifest, and the possibility of a divergence
between the interests of self or alter and those
of the community has been realised. Further,
this power, in whichever way it comes to be exercised,
marks a strong individuality; and may be the first,
as it is certainly a most striking, manifestation
of the fact of individuality: it marks off, at
once, the individual possessing such power from the
rest of the community. And the common consciousness
is puzzled by the apparition. Just as it tolerates
fetishes though it disapproves of them and is afraid
of them, so it tolerates the magician, though it is
afraid of him and does not cordially approve of him,
even when he benefits an individual client without
injuring the community. But though the man of
power may use, and apparently most often does use,
his power, in the interest of some individual and to
the detriment of the community; and though it is this
condemnable use which is everywhere most conspicuous,
and probably earliest developed; still there is no
reason why he should not use, and as a matter of fact
he sometimes does use, his power on behalf of the community
to promote the food-supply of the community or to
produce the rain which is desired. In this case,
then, the individual, having a power which others
have not, is not at variance with the community but
in harmony with the common consciousness, and becomes
an organ by which it acts. When, then, the belief
in gods, having the interests of the community at
heart, presents itself or develops within the common
consciousness, the individual who has the power on
behalf of the community to make rain or increase the
food supply is marked out by the belief of the community or
it may be by the communings of his own heart as
specially related to the gods. Hence we find,
in the low stages of the evolution of religion, the
proceedings, by which the man of power had made rain
for the community or increased the food-supply, either
incorporated into the ritual of the gods, or surviving
traditionally as incidents in the life of a prophet,
e.g. the rain-making of Elijah. In the same
way therefore as I have suggested that the resemblances
between gods and fetishes are to be explained by the
theory that the two go back to a common source, and
that neither is developed from the other, so I suggest
that the resemblances between the conception of prophet
and that of magician point not to the priority of either
to the other, but to the derivation or evolution of
both from a prior and less determinate concept.
Just as a fetish is a material thing,
and something more, so a magician is a man and something
more. Just as a god is an idol and something
more, so a prophet or priest is a man and something
more. The fetish is a material thing which manifests
a power that other things do not exhibit; and the
magician is a man possessing a power which other men
have not. The difference between the magician
and the prophet or priest is the same as the difference
between the fetish and the god. It is the difference
between that which subserves the wishes of the individual,
which may be, and often are, anti-social, and that
which furthers the interests of the community.
Of this difference each child who is born into the
community learns from his elders: it is part
of the common consciousness of the community.
And it could not become a fact of the common consciousness
until the existence of self became recognised in thought
and expressed in language. With that recognition
of difference, or possible difference, between the
individual and the community, between the desires of
the one and the welfare of the other, came the recognition
of a difference between fetish and god, between magician
and priest. The power exercised by either was
greater than that of man; but the power manifested
in the one was exercised with a view to the good of
the community; in the case of the other, not.
Thus, from the beginning, gods were not merely beings
exercising power greater than that of man, but beings
exercising their power for the good of man. It
is as such that, from the beginning to the end, they
have figured both in the common consciousness of the
community, and in the consciousness of every member
born into the community. They have figured in
both; and, because they have figured both in the individual
consciousness and the common consciousness, they have,
from the beginning, been something present to both,
something at once within the individual and without.
But as the child recognises objects long before he
becomes aware of the existence of himself, so man,
in his infancy, sought this power or being in the
external world long before he looked for it within
himself.
It is because man looked for this
being or power in the external world that he found,
or thought he found, it there. He looked for it
and found it, in the same way as to this day the African
negro finds a fetish. A negro found a stone and
took it for his fetish, as Professor Tylor relates,
as follows: ’He was once going out
on important business, but crossing the threshold
he trod on this stone and hurt himself. Ha! ha!
thought he, art thou there? So he took the stone,
and it helped him through his undertaking for days.’
So too when the community’s attention is arrested
by something in the external world, some natural phenomenon
which is marvellous in their eyes, their attitude
of mind, the attitude of the common consciousness,
translated into words is: ‘Ha! ha! art
thou there?’ This attitude of mind is one of
expectancy: man finds a being, possessed of greater
power than man’s, because he is ready to find
it and expecting it.
So strong is this expectancy, so ready
is man to find this being, superior to man, that he
finds it wherever he goes, wherever he looks.
There is probably no natural phenomenon whatever that
has not somewhere, at some time, provoked the question
or the reflection ’Art thou there?’ And
it is because man has taken upon himself to answer
the question, and to say: ’Thou art there,
in the great and strong wind which rends the mountains;
or, in the earthquake; or, in the fire’ that
polytheism has arisen. Perhaps, however, we should
rather use the word ‘polydaemonism’ than
‘polytheism.’ By a god is usually
meant a being who has come to possess a proper name;
and, probably, a spirit is worshipped for some considerable
time, before the appellative, by which he is addressed,
loses its original meaning, and comes to be the proper
name by which he, and he alone, is addressed.
Certainly, the stage in which spirits without proper
names are worshipped seems to be more primitive than
that in which the being worshipped is a god, having
a proper name of his own. And the difference
between the two stages of polydaemonism and polytheism
is not merely limited to the fact that the beings
worshipped have proper names in the later stage, and
had none in the earlier. A development or a difference
in language implies a development or difference in
thought. If the being or spirit worshipped has
come to be designated by a proper name, he has lost
much of the vagueness that characterises a nameless
spirit, and he has come to be much more definite and
much more personal. Indeed, a change much more
sinister, from the religious point of view, is wrought,
when the transition from polydaemonism to polytheism
is accomplished.
In the stage of human evolution known
as animism, everything which acts or is
supposed to act is supposed to be, like
man himself, a person. But though, in the animistic
stage, all powers are conceived by man as being persons,
they are not all conceived as having human form:
they may be animals, and have animal forms; or birds,
and have bird-form; they may be trees, clouds, streams,
the wind, the earthquake or the fire. In some,
or rather in all, of these, man has at some time found
the being or the power, greater than man, of whom
he has at all times been in quest, with the enquiry,
addressed to each in turn, ‘Art thou there?’
The form of the question, the use of the personal
pronoun, shows that he is seeking for a person.
And students of the science of religion are generally
agreed that man, throughout the history of religion,
has been seeking for a power or being superior to
man and greater than he. It is therefore a personal
power and a personal being that man has been in search
of, throughout his religious history. He has
pushed his search in many directions often
simultaneously in different directions; and, he has
abandoned one line of enquiry after another, because
he has found that it did not lead him whither he would
be. Thus, as we have seen, he pushed forward,
at the same time, in the direction of fetishism and
of polytheism, or rather of polydaemonism; but fetishism
failed to bring him satisfaction, or rather failed
to satisfy the common consciousness, the consciousness
of the community, because it proved on trial to subserve
the wishes the anti-social wishes of
the individual, and not the interests of the community.
The beings or powers that man looked to find and which
he supposed he found, whether as fetishes in this
or that object, or as daemons in the sky, the fire
or the wind, in beast or bird or tree, were taken
to be personal beings and personal powers, bearing
the same relation to that in which, or through which,
they manifested themselves, as man bears to his body.
They do not seem to have been conceived as being men,
or the souls of men which manifested themselves in
animals or trees. At the time when polydaemonism
has, as yet, not become polytheism, the personal beings,
worshipped in this or that external form, have not
as yet been anthropomorphised. Indeed, the process
which constitutes the change from polydaemonism to
polytheism consists in the process, or rather is the
process, by which the spirits, the personal beings,
worshipped in tree, or sky, or cloud, or wind, or
fire came gradually to be anthropomorphised to
be invested with human parts and passions and to be
addressed like human beings with proper names.
But when anthropomorphic polytheism is thus pushed
to its extreme logical conclusions, its tendency is
to collapse in the same way, and for the same reasons,
as fetishism, before it, had collapsed. What man
had been in search of, from the beginning, and was
still in search of, was some personal being or power,
higher than and superior to man. What anthropomorphic
polytheism presented him with, in the upshot, was with
beings, not superior, but, in some or many cases, undeniably
inferior to man. As such they could not thenceforth
be worshipped. In Europe their worship was overthrown
by Christianity. But, on reflection, it seems
clear not only that, as such, they could not thenceforth
be worshipped; but that, as such, they never had been
worshipped. In the consciousness of the community,
the object of worship had always been, from the beginning,
some personal being superior to man. The apostle
of Christianity might justifiably speak to polytheists
of the God ‘whom ye ignorantly worship.’
It is true, and it is important to notice, that the
sacrifices and the rites and ceremonies, which together
made up the service of worship, had been consciously
and intentionally rendered to deities represented
in human form; and, in this sense, anthropomorphic
deities had been worshipped. But, if worship
is something other than sacrifice and rite and ceremony,
then the object of worship the personal
being, greater than man presented to the
common consciousness, is something other than the
anthropomorphic being, inferior in much to man, of
whom poets speak in mythology and whom artists represent
in bodily shape.
Just as fetishism developed and persisted,
because it did contain, though it perverted, one element
of religious truth the accessibility of
the power worshipped to the worshipper so
too anthropomorphism, notwithstanding the consequences
to which, in mythology, it led, did contain, or rather,
was based on, one element of truth, viz. that
the divine is personal, as well as the human.
Its error was to set up, as divine personalities,
a number of reproductions or reflections of human
personality. It leads to the conclusion, as a
necessary consequence, that the divine personality
is but a shadow of the human personality, enlarged
and projected, so to speak, upon the clouds, but always
betraying, in some way or other, the fact that it is
but the shadow, magnified or distorted, of man.
It excludes the possibility that the divine personality,
present to the common consciousness as the object
of worship, may be no reproduction of the human personality,
but a reality to which the human personality has the
power of approximating. Be this as it may, we
are justified in saying, indeed we are compelled to
recognise, that in mythology, all the world over,
we see a process of reflection at work, by which the
beings, originally apprehended as superior to man,
come first to be anthropomorphised, that is to be
apprehended as having the parts and passions of men,
and then, consequently, to be seen to be no better
than men. This discovery it is which in the long
run proves fatal to anthropomorphism.
We have seen, above, the reason why
fetishism becomes eventually distasteful to the common
consciousness: the beings, superior to man, which
are worshipped by the community, are worshipped as
having the interests of the community in their charge,
and as having the good of the community at heart;
whereas a fetish is sought and found by the individual,
to advance his private interests, even to the cost
and loss of other individuals and of the community
at large. Thus, from the earliest period at which
beings, superior to man, are differentiated into gods
and fetishes, gods are accepted by the common consciousness
as beings who maintain the good of the community and
punish those who infringe it; while fetishes become
beings who assist individual members to infringe the
customary morality of the tribe. Thus, from the
first, the beings, of whom the community is conscious
as superior to man, are beings, having in charge, first,
the customary morality of the tribe; and, afterwards,
the conscious morality of the community.
This conception, it was, of the gods,
as guardians of morality and of the common good, that
condemned fetishism; and this conception it was, which
was to prove eventually the condemnation of polytheism.
A multitude of beings even though they
be divine beings means a multitude, that
is a diversity, of ideas. Diversity of ideas,
difference of opinion, is what is implied by every
mythology which tells of disputes and wars between
the gods. Every god, who thus disputed and fought
with other gods, must have felt that he had right
on his side, or else have fought for the sake of fighting.
Consequently the gods of polytheism are either destitute
of morality, or divided in opinion as to what is right.
In neither case, therefore, are the gods, of whom
mythology tells, the beings, superior to man, who,
from the beginning, were present in the common consciousness
to be worshipped. From the outset, the object
of the community’s worship had been conceived
as a moral power. If, then, the many gods of
polytheism were either destitute or disregardful of
morality, they could not be the moral power of which
the common consciousness had been dimly aware:
that moral power, that moral personality, must be
other than they. As the moral consciousness of
the community discriminated fetishes from gods and
tended to rule out fetishes from the sphere of religion;
so too, eventually, the moral consciousness of the
community came to be offended by the incompatibility
between the moral ideal and the conception of a multitude
of gods at variance with each other. If the common
consciousness was slow in coming to recognise the
unity of the Godhead and it was slower in
some people than in others the unity was
logically implied, from the beginning, in the conception
of a personal power, greater and higher than man,
and having the good of the community at heart.
The history of religion is, in effect, from one point
of view, the story of the process by which this conception,
however dim, blurred or vague, at first, tends to
become clarified and self-consistent.
That, however, is not the only point
of view from which the history of religion can, or
ought to be, regarded. So long as we look at it
from that point of view, we shall be in danger of
seeing nothing in the history of religion but an intellectual
process, and nothing in religion itself but a mental
conception. There is, however, another element
in religion, as is generally recognised; and that an
emotional element, as is usually admitted. What
however is the nature of that emotion, is a question
on which there has always been diversity of opinion.
The beings, who figured in the common consciousness
as gods, were apprehended by the common consciousness
as powers superior to man; and certainly as powers
capable of inflicting suffering on the community.
As such, then, they must have been approached with
an emotion of the nature of reverence, awe or fear.
The important, the determining, fact, however, is
that they were approached. The emotion, therefore,
which prompted the community to approach them, is at
any rate distinguishable from the mere fright which
would have kept the community as far away from these
powers as possible. The emotion which prompted
approach could not have been fear, pure and simple.
It must have been more in the nature of awe or reverence;
both of which feelings are clearly distinguishable
from fear. Thus, we may fear disease or disgrace;
but the fear we feel carries with it neither awe nor
reverence. Again, awe is an inhibitive feeling,
it is a feeling which as in the case of
the awe-struck person rather prevents than
promotes action or movement. And the determining
fact about the religious emotion is that it was the
emotion with which the community approached its gods.
That emotion is now, and probably always was, reverential
in character. The occasion, on which a community
approaches its gods, often is, and doubtless often
was, a time when misfortune had befallen the community.
The misfortune was viewed as a visitation of the god’s
wrath upon his community; and fear that
’fear of the Lord, which is the beginning of
wisdom’ doubtless played a large
part in the complex emotion which stirred the community,
not to run away but to approach the god for the purpose
of appeasing his wrath. In the complexity of
an emotion which led to action of this kind, we must
recognise not merely fear but some trust and confidence so
much, at least, as prevented the person who experienced
it from running away simply. The emotion is not
too complex for man, in however primitive a stage
of development: it is not more complex than that
which brings a dog to his master, though it knows it
is going to be thrashed.
That some trust and confidence is
indispensable in the complex feeling with which a
community approaches its gods, for the purpose of
appeasing their wrath still more, for beseeching
favours from them seems indisputable.
But we must not exaggerate it. Wherever there
are gods at all, they are regarded by the community
as beings who can be approached: so much confidence,
at least, is placed in them by the community that
believes in them. Even if they are offended and
wrathful, the community is confident that they can
be appeased: the community places so much trust
in them. Indeed its trust goes even further:
it is sure that they do not take offence without reasonable
grounds. If they display wrath against the community
and send calamity upon it, it is, and in the opinion
of the community, can only be, because some member
of the community has done that which he should not
have done. The gods may be, on occasion, wrathful;
but they are just. They are from the beginning
moral beings according to such standard
of morality as the community possesses and
it is breaches of the tribe’s customary morality
that their wrath is directed against. They are,
from the beginning, and for long afterwards in the
history of religion, strict to mark what is amiss,
and, in that sense, they are jealous gods. And
this aspect of the Godhead it is which fills the larger
part of the field of religious consciousness, not only
in the case of peoples who have failed to recognise
the unity of the Godhead, but even in the case of
a people like the Jews, who did recognise it.
The other aspect of the Godhead, as the God, not merely
of mercy and forgiveness, but of love, was an aspect
fully revealed in Christianity alone, of all the religions
in the world.
But the love God displays to all his
children, to the prodigal son as well as to others,
is not a mere attribute assigned to Him. It is
not a mere quality with which one religion may invest
Him, and of which another religion, with equal right,
may divest Him. The idea of God does not consist
merely of attributes and qualities, so that, if you
strip off all the attributes and qualities, nothing
is left, and the idea is shown to be without content,
meaning or reality.
The Godhead has been, in the common
consciousness, from the beginning, a being, a personal
being, greater than man; and it is as such that He
has manifested Himself in the common consciousness,
from the beginning until the present day. To
this personality, as to others, attributes and qualities
may be falsely ascribed, which are inconsistent with
one another and are none of His. Some of the
attributes thus falsely ascribed may be discovered,
in the course of the history of religion, to have
been falsely ascribed; and they will then be set aside.
Thus, fetishism ascribed, or sought to ascribe, to
the Godhead, the quality of willingness to promote
even the anti-social desires of the owner of the fetish.
And fetishism exfoliated, or peeled off from the religious
organism. Anthropomorphism, which ascribed to
the divine personality the parts and passions of man,
along with a power greater than man’s to violate
morality, is gradually dropped, as its inconsistency
with the idea of God comes gradually to be recognised
and loathed. So too with polytheism: a pantheon
which is divided against itself cannot stand.
Thus, fetishism, anthropomorphism and polytheism ascribe
qualities to the Godhead, which are shown to be attributes
assigned to the Godhead and imposed upon it from without,
for eventually they are found by experience to be
incompatible with the idea of God as it is revealed
in the common consciousness.
On the other hand, the process of
the history of religion, the process of the manifestation
or revelation of the Godhead, does not proceed solely
by this negative method, or method of exclusion.
If an attribute, such as that of human form, or of
complicity in anti-social purposes, is ascribed, by
anthropomorphism or fetishism, to the divine personality,
and is eventually felt by the common consciousness
to be incompatible with the idea of God, the result
is not merely that the attribute in question drops
off, and leaves the idea of the divine personality
exactly where it was, and what it was, before the
attribute had been foisted on it. The incompatibility
of the quality, falsely ascribed or assigned, becomes if,
and when, it does become manifest and intolerable,
just in proportion as the idea of God, which has always
been present, however vaguely and ill-defined, in
the common consciousness, comes to manifest itself
more definitely. The attribution, to the divine
personality, of qualities, which are eventually found
incompatible with it, may prove the occasion of the
more precise and definite manifestation; we may say
that action implies reaction, and so false ideas provoke
true ones, but the false ideas do not create the new
ones. The false ideas may stimulate closer attention
to the actual facts of the common consciousness and
thus may stimulate the formation of truer ideas about
them, by leading to a concentration of attention upon
the actual facts. But it is from this closer
attention, this concentration of attention, that the
newer and truer knowledge comes, and not from the
false ideas. What we speak of, from one point
of view, as closer attention to the facts of the common
consciousness, may, from another point of view, be
spoken of as an increasing manifestation, or a clearer
revelation, of the divine personality, revealed or
manifested to the common consciousness. Those
are two views, or two points of view, of one and the
same process. But whichever view we take of it,
the process does not proceed solely by the negative
method of exclusion: it is a process which results
in the unfolding and disclosure, not merely of what
is in the common consciousness, at any given moment,
but of what is implied in the divine personality revealed
to the common consciousness. If we choose to
speak of this unfolding or disclosure as evolution,
the process, which the history of religion undertakes
to set forth, will be the evolution of the idea of
God. But, in that case, the process which we
designate by the name of evolution, will be a process
of disclosure and revelation. Disclosure implies
that there is something to disclose; revelation, that
there is something to be revealed to the common consciousness the
presence of the Godhead, of divine personality.