THE FRENCH DECLARATION OF RIGHTS OF AUGUST 26, 1789, AND ITS
SIGNIFICANCE.
The declaration of “the rights
of man and of citizens” by the French Constituent
Assembly on August 26, 1789, is one of the most significant
events of the French Revolution. It has been criticised
from different points of view with directly opposing
results. The political scientist and the historian,
thoroughly appreciating its importance, have repeatedly
come to the conclusion that the Declaration had no
small part in the anarchy with which France was visited
soon after the storming of the Bastille. They
point to its abstract phrases as ambiguous and therefore
dangerous, and as void of all political reality and
practical statesmanship. Its empty pathos, they
say, confused the mind, disturbed calm judgment, aroused
passions, and stifled the sense of duty, for
of duty there is not a word. Others, on the contrary,
and especially Frenchmen, have exalted it as a revelation
in the world’s history, as a catechism of the
“principles of 1789” which form the eternal
foundation of the state’s structure, and they
have glorified it as the most precious gift that France
has given to mankind.
Less regarded than its historical
and political significance is the importance of this
document in the history of law, an importance which
continues even to the present day. Whatever may
be the value or worthlessness of its general phrases,
it is under the influence of this document that the
conception of the public rights of the individual has
developed in the positive law of the states of the
European continent. Until it appeared public
law literature recognized the rights of heads of states,
the privileges of class, and the privileges of individuals
or special corporations, but the general rights of
subjects were to be found essentially only in the
form of duties on the part of the state, not in the
form of definite legal claims of the individual.
The Declaration of the Rights of Man for the first
time originated in all its vigor in positive law the
conception, which until then had been known only to
natural law, of the personal rights of the members
of the state over against the state as a whole.
This was next seen in the first French constitution
of September 3, 1791, which set forth, upon the basis
of a preceding declaration of rights, a list of droits
naturels et civils as rights that were guaranteed
by the constitution. Together with the right of
suffrage, the “droits garantis par la constitution”,
which were enumerated for the last time in the constitution
of November 4, 1848, form to-day the basis of French
theory and practice respecting the personal public
rights of the individual. And under the influence
of the French declaration there have been introduced
into almost all of the constitutions of the other
Continental states similar enumerations of rights,
whose separate phrases and formulas, however, are
more or less adapted to the particular conditions
of their respective states, and therefore frequently
exhibit wide differences in content.
In Germany most of the constitutions
of the period prior to 1848 contained a section upon
the rights of subjects, and in the year 1848 the National
Constitutional Convention at Frankfort adopted “the
fundamental rights of the German people”, which
were published on December 27, 1848, as Federal law.
In spite of a resolution of the Bund of August
23, 1851, declaring these rights null and void, they
are of lasting importance, because many of their specifications
are to-day incorporated almost word for word in the
existing Federal law. These enumerations of rights
appear in greater numbers in the European constitutions
of the period after 1848. Thus, first of all,
in the Prussian constitution of January 31, 1850,
and in Austria’s “Fundamental Law of the
State” of December 21, 1867, on the general rights
of the state’s citizens. And more recently
they have been incorporated in the constitutions of
the new states in the Balkan peninsula.
A noteworthy exception to this are
the constitutions of the North German Confederation
of July 26, 1867, and of the German Empire of April
16, 1871, which lack entirely any paragraph on fundamental
rights. The constitution of the Empire, however,
could the better dispense with such a declaration
as it was already contained in most of the constitutions
of the individual states, and, as above stated, a series
of Federal laws has enacted the most important principles
of the Frankfort fundamental rights. Besides,
with the provisions of the Federal constitution as
to amendments, it was not necessary to make any special
place for them in that instrument, as the Reichstag,
to whose especial care the guardianship of the fundamental
rights must be entrusted, has no difficult forms to
observe in amending the constitution. As a matter
of fact the public rights of the individual are much
greater in the German Empire than in most of the states
where the fundamental rights are specifically set
forth in the constitution. This may be seen, for
example, by a glance at the legislation and the judicial
and administrative practice in Austria.
But whatever may be one’s opinion
to-day upon the formulation of abstract principles,
which only become vitalized through the process of
detailed legislation, as affecting the legal position
of the individual in the state, the fact that the
recognition of such principles is historically bound
up with that first declaration of rights makes it an
important task of constitutional history to ascertain
the origin of the French Declaration of Rights of
1789. The achievement of this task is of great
importance both in explaining the development of the
modern state and in understanding the position which
this state assures to the individual. Thus far
in the works on public law various precursors of the
declaration of the Constituent Assembly, from Magna
Charta to the American Declaration of Independence,
have been enumerated and arranged in regular sequence,
yet any thorough investigation of the sources from
which the French drew is not to be found.
It is the prevailing opinion that
the teachings of the Contrat Social gave the
impulse to the Declaration, and that its prototype
was the Declaration of Independence of the thirteen
United States of North America. Let us first
of all inquire into the correctness of these assumptions.