The principle of
sincerity.
It is always understood as an expression
of condemnation when anything in Literature or Art
is said to be done for effect; and yet to produce
an effect is the aim and end of both.
There is nothing beyond a verbal ambiguity
here if we look at it closely, and yet there is a
corresponding uncertainty in the conception of Literature
and Art commonly entertained, which leads many writers
and many critics into the belief that what are called
“effects” should be sought, and when found
must succeed. It is desirable to clear up this
moral ambiguity, as I may call it, and to show that
the real method of securing the legitimate effect
is not to aim at it, but to aim at the truth, relying
on that for securing effect. The condemnation
of whatever is “done for effect” obviously
springs from indignation at a disclosed insincerity
in the artist, who is self-convicted of having neglected
truth for the sake of our applause; and we refuse our
applause to the flatterer, or give it contemptuously
as to a mountebank whose dexterity has amused us.
It is unhappily true that much insincere
Literature and Art, executed solely with a view to
effect, does succeed by deceiving the public.
But this is only because the simulation of truth or
the blindness of the public conceals the insincerity.
As a maxim, the Principle of Sincerity is admitted.
Nothing but what is true, or is held to be true, can
succeed; anything which looks like insincerity is condemned.
In this respect we may compare it with the maxim of
Honesty the best policy. No far-reaching intellect
fails to perceive that if all men were uniformly upright
and truthful, Life would be more victorious, and Literature
more noble. We find, however, both in Life and
Literature, a practical disregard of the truth of
these propositions almost equivalent to a disbelief
in them. Many men are keenly alive to the social
advantages of honesty in the practice of
others. They are also strongly impressed with
the conviction that in their own particular case the
advantage will sometimes lie in not strictly adhering
to the rule. Honesty is doubtless the best policy
in the long run; but somehow the run here seems so
very long, and a short-cut opens such allurements to
impatient desire. It requires a firm calm insight,
or a noble habit of thought, to steady the wavering
mind, and direct it away from delusive short-cuts:
to make belief practice, and forego immediate triumph.
Many of those who unhesitatingly admit Sincerity to
be one great condition of success in Literature find
it difficult, and often impossible, to resist the
temptation of an insincerity which promises immediate
advantage. It is not only the grocers who sand
their sugar before prayers. Writers who know
well enough that the triumph of falsehood is an unholy
triumph, are not deterred from falsehood by that knowledge.
They know, perhaps, that, even if undetected, it will
press on their own consciences; but the knowledge
avails them little. The immediate pressure of
the temptation is yielded to, and Sincerity remains
a text to be preached to others. To gain applause
they will misstate facts, to gain victory in argument
they will misrepresent the opinions they oppose; and
they suppress the rising misgivings by the dangerous
sophism that to discredit error is good work, and by
the hope that no one will detect the means by which
the work is effected. The saddest aspect of this
procedure is that in Literature, as in Life, a temporary
success often does reward dishonesty. It would
be insincere to conceal it. To gain a reputation
as discoverers men will invent or suppress facts.
To appear learned they will array their writings in
the ostentation of borrowed citations. To solicit
the “sweet voices” of the crowd they will
feign sentiments they do not feel, and utter what they
think the crowd will wish to hear, keeping back whatever
the crowd will hear with disapproval. And, as
I said, such men often succeed for a time; the fact
is so, and we must not pretend that it is otherwise.
But it no more disturbs the fundamental truth of the
Principle of Sincerity, than the perturbations in
the orbit of Mars disturb the truth of Kepler’s
law.
It is impossible to deny that dishonest
men often grow rich and famous, becoming powerful
in their parish or in parliament. Their portraits
simper from shop windows; and they live and die respected.
This success is theirs; yet it is not the success
which a noble soul will envy. Apart from the
risk of discovery and infamy, there is the certainty
of a conscience ill at ease, or if at ease, so blunted
in its sensibilities, so given over to lower lusts,
that a healthy instinct recoils from such a state.
Observe, moreover, that in Literature the possible
rewards of dishonesty are small, and the probability
of detection great. In Life a dishonest man is
chiefly moved by desires towards some tangible result
of money or power; if he get these he has got all.
The man of letters has a higher aim: the very
object of his toil is to secure the sympathy and respect
of men; and the rewards of his toil may be paid in
money, fame, or consciousness of earnest effort.
The first of these may sometimes be gained without
Sincerity. Fame may also, for a time, be erected
on an unstable ground, though it will inevitably be
destroyed again. But the last and not least reward
is to be gained by every one without fear of failure,
without risk of change. Sincere work is good
work, be it never so humble; and sincere work is not
only an indestructible delight to the worker by its
very genuineness, but is immortal in the best sense,
for it lives for ever in its influence. There
is no good Dictionary, not even a good Index, that
is not in this sense priceless, for it has honestly
furthered the work of the world, saving labour to
others, setting an example to successors.
Whether I make a careful Index, or
an inaccurate one, will probably in no respect affect
the money-payment I shall receive. My sins will
never fall heavily on me; my virtue will gain me neither
extra pence nor praise. I shall be hidden by
obscurity from the indignation of those whose valuable
time is wasted over my pretence at accuracy, as from
the silent gratitude of those whose time is saved
by my honest fidelity. The consciousness of faithfulness
even to the poor index maker may be a better reward
than pence or praise; but of course we cannot expect
the unconscientious to believe this. If I sand
my sugar, and tell lies over my counter, I may gain
the rewards of dishonesty, or I may be overtaken by
its Nemesis. But if I am faithful in my work the
reward cannot be withheld from me. The obscure
workers who, knowing that they will never earn renown
yet feel an honourable pride in doing their work faithfully,
may be likened to the benevolent who feel a noble delight
in performing generous actions which will never be
known to be theirs, the only end they seek in such
actions being the good which is wrought for others,
and their delight being the sympathy with others.
I should be ashamed to insist on truths
so little likely to be disputed, did they not point
directly at the great source of bad Literature, which,
as was said in our first chapter, springs from a want
of proper moral guidance rather than from deficiency
of talent. The Principle of Sincerity comprises
all those qualities of courage, patience, honesty,
and simplicity which give momentum to talent, and
determine successful Literature. It is not enough
to have the eye to see; there must also be the courage
to express what the eye has seen, and the steadfastness
of a trust in truth. Insight, imagination, grace
of style are potent; but their power is delusive unless
sincerely guided. If any one should object that
this is a truism, the answer is ready: Writers
disregard its truth, as traders disregard the truism
of honesty being the best policy. Nay, as even
the most upright men are occasionally liable to swerve
from the truth, so the most upright authors will in
some passages desert a perfect sincerity; yet the ideal
of both is rigorous truth. Men who are never flagrantly
dishonest are at times unveracious in small matters,
colouring or suppressing facts with a conscious purpose;
and writers who never stole an idea nor pretended
to honours for which they had not striven, may be found
lapsing into small insincerities, speaking a language
which is not theirs, uttering opinions which they
expect to gain applause rather than the opinions really
believed by them. But if few men are perfectly
and persistently sincere, Sincerity is nevertheless
the only enduring strength.
The principle is universal, stretching
from the highest purposes of Literature down to its
smallest details. It underlies the labour of the
philosopher, the investigator, the moralist, the poet,
the novelist, the critic, the historian, and the compiler.
It is visible in the publication of opinions, in the
structure of sentences, and in the fidelity of citations.
Men utter insincere thoughts, they express themselves
in echoes and affectations, and they are careless or
dishonest in their use of the labours of others, all
the time believing in the virtue of sincerity, all
the time trying to make others believe honesty to
be the best policy.
Let us glance for a moment at the
most important applications of the principle.
A man must be himself convinced if he is to convince
others. The prophet must be his own disciple,
or he will make none. Enthusiasm is contagious:
belief creates belief. There is no influence issuing
from unbelief or from languid acquiescence. This
is peculiarly noticeable in Art, because Art depends
on sympathy for its influence, and unless the artist
has felt the emotions he depicts we remain unmoved:
in proportion to the depth of his feeling is our sympathetic
response; in proportion to the shallowness or falsehood
of his presentation is our coldness or indifference.
Many writers who have been fond of quoting the Si
Vis me flere of Horace have written
as if they did not believe a word of it; for they
have been silent on their own convictions, suppressed
their own experience, and falsified their own feelings
to repeat the convictions and fine phrases of another.
I am sorry that my experience assures me that many
of those who will read with complete assent all here
written respecting the power of Sincerity, will basely
desert their allegiance to the truth the next time
they begin to write; and they will desert it because
their misguided views of Literature prompt them to
think more of what the public is likely to applaud
than of what is worth applause; unfortunately for
them their estimation of this likelihood is generally
based on a very erroneous assumption of public wants:
they grossly mistake the taste they pander to.
In all sincere speech there is power,
not necessarily great power, but as much as the speaker
is capable of. Speak for yourself and from yourself,
or be silent. It can be of no good that you should
tell in your “clever” feeble way what
another has already told us with the dynamic energy
of conviction. If you can tell us something that
your own eyes have seen, your own mind has thought,
your own heart has felt, you will have power over
us, and all the real power that is possible for you.
If what you have seen is trivial, if what you have
thought is erroneous, if what you have felt is feeble,
it would assuredly be better that you should not speak
at all; but if you insist on speaking Sincerity will
secure the uttermost of power.
The delusions of self-love cannot
be prevented, but intellectual misconceptions as to
the means of achieving success may be corrected.
Thus although it may not be possible for any introspection
to discover whether we have genius or effective power,
it is quite possible to know whether we are trading
upon borrowed capital, and whether the eagle’s
feathers have been picked up by us, or grow from our
own wings. I hear some one of my young readers
exclaim against the disheartening tendency of what
is here said. Ambitious of success, and conscious
that he has no great resources within his own experience,
he shrinks from the idea of being thrown upon his
naked faculty and limited resources, when he feels
himself capable of dexterously using the resources
of others, and so producing an effective work.
“Why,” he asks, “must I confine myself
to my own small experience, when I feel persuaded that
it will interest no one? Why express the opinions
to which my own investigations have led me when I
suspect that they are incomplete, perhaps altogether
erroneous, and when I know that they will not be popular
because they are unlike those which have hitherto
found favour? Your restrictions would reduce
two-thirds of our writers to silence!”
This reduction would, I suspect, be
welcomed by every one except the gagged writers; but
as the idea of its being operative is too chimerical
for us to entertain it, and as the purpose of these
pages is to expound the principles of success and
failure, not to make Quixotic onslaughts on the windmills
of stupidity and conceit, I answer my young interrogator:
“Take warning and do not write. Unless you
believe in yourself, only noodles will believe in
you, and they but tepidly. If your experience
seems trivial to you, it must seem trivial to us.
If your thoughts are not fervid convictions, or sincere
doubts, they will not have the power of convictions
and doubts. To believe in yourself is the first
step; to proclaim your belief the next. You cannot
assume the power of another. No jay becomes an
eagle by borrowing a few eagle feathers. It is
true that your sincerity will not be a guarantee of
power. You may believe that to be important and
novel which we all recognise as trivial and old.
You may be a madman, and believe yourself a prophet.
You may be a mere echo, and believe yourself a voice.
These are among the delusions against which none of
us are protected. But if Sincerity is not necessarily
a guarantee of power, it is a necessary condition
of power, and no genius or prophet can exist without
it.”
“The highest merit we ascribe
to Moses, Plato, and Milton,” says Emerson,
“is that they set at nought books and traditions,
and spoke not what men thought, but what they thought.
A man should learn to detect and watch that gleam
of light which flashes across his mind from within;
more than the lustre of the firmament of bards and
sages. Yet he dismisses without notice his thought
because it is his. In every work of genius we
recognise our own rejected thoughts; they come back
to us with a certain alienated majesty.”
It is strange that any one who has recognised the
individuality of all works of lasting influence, should
not also recognise the fact that his own individuality
ought to be steadfastly preserved. As Emerson
says in continuation, “Great works of art have
no more affecting lesson for us than this. They
teach us to abide by our spontaneous impressions with
good-humoured inflexibility, then most when the whole
cry of voices is on the other side. Else tomorrow
a stranger will say with masterly good sense, precisely
what we have thought and felt all the time, and we
shall be forced to take with shame our opinion from
another.” Accepting the opinions of another
and the tastes of another is very different from agreement
in opinion and taste. Originality is independence,
not rebellion; it is sincerity, not antagonism.
Whatever you believe to be true and false, that proclaim
to be true and false; whatever you think admirable
and beautiful, that should be your model, even if
all your friends and all the critics storm at you
as a crochet-monger and an eccentric. Whether
the public will feel its truth and beauty at once,
or after long years, or never cease to regard it as
paradox and ugliness, no man can foresee; enough for
you to know that you have done your best, have been
true to yourself, and that the utmost power inherent
in your work has been displayed.
An orator whose purpose is to persuade
men must speak the things they wish to hear; an orator,
whose purpose is to move men, must also avoid disturbing
the emotional effect by any obtrusion of intellectual
antagonism; but an author whose purpose is to instruct
men, who appeals to the intellect, must be careless
of their opinions, and think only of truth. It
will often be a question when a man is or is not wise
in advancing unpalateable opinions, or in preaching
hérésies; but it can never be a question that
a man should be silent if unprepared to speak the
truth as he conceives it. Deference to popular
opinion is one great source of bad writing, and is
all the more disastrous because the deference is paid
to some purely hypothetical requirement. When
a man fails to see the truth of certain generally
accepted views, there is no law compelling him to
provoke animosity by announcing his dissent. He
may be excused if he shrink from the lurid glory of
martyrdom; he may be justified in not placing himself
in a position of singularity. He may even be
commended for not helping to perplex mankind with doubts
which he feels to be founded on limited and possibly
erroneous investigation. But if allegiance to
truth lays no stern command upon him to speak out
his immature dissent, it does lay a stern command not
to speak out hypocritical assent. There are many
justifications of silence; there can be none of insincerity.
Nor is this less true of minor questions;
it applies equally to opinions on matters of taste
and personal feeling. Why should I echo what
seem to me the extravagant praises of Raphael’s
“Transfiguration,” when, in truth, I do
not greatly admire that famous work ? There is
no necessity for me to speak on the subject at all;
but if I do speak, surely it is to utter my impressions,
and not to repeat what others have uttered. Here,
then, is a dilemma; if I say what I really feel about
this work, after vainly endeavouring day after day
to discover the transcendent merits discovered by
thousands (or at least proclaimed by them), there
is every likelihood of my incurring the contempt of
connoisseurs, and of being reproached with want of
taste in art. This is the bugbear which scares
thousands. For myself, I would rather incur the
contempt of connoisseurs than my own; the repreach
of defective taste is more endurable than the reproach
of insincerity. Suppose I am deficient in the
requisite knowledge and sensibility, shall I be less
so by pretending to admire what really gives me no
exquisite enjoyment? Will the pleasure I feel
in pictures be enhanced because other men consider
me right in my admlration, or diminished because they
consider me wrong?
[I have never thoroughly understood
the painful anxiety of people to be shielded against
the dishonouring suspicion of not rightly appreciating
pictures, even when the very phrases they use betray
their ignorance and insensibility. Many will
avow their indifference to music, and almost boast
of their ignorance of science; will sneer at abstract
theories, and profess the most tepid interest in history,
who would feel it an unpardonable insult if you doubted
their enthusiasm for painting and the “old masters”
(by them secretly identified with the brown masters).
It is an insincerity fostered by general pretence.
Each man is afraid to declare his real sentiments
in the presence of others equally timid. Massive
authority overawes genuine feeling].
The opinion of the majority is
not lightly to be rejected; but neither is it to be
carelessly echoed. There is something noble in
the submission to a great renown, which makes all
reverence a healthy attitude if it be genuine.
When I think of the immense fame of Raphael, and of
how many high and delicate minds have found exquisite
delight even in the “Transfiguration,”
and especially when I recall how others of his works
have affected me, it is natural to feel some diffidence
in opposing the judgment of men whose studies have
given them the best means of forming that judgment a
diffidence which may keep me silent on the matter.
To start with the assumption that you are right, and
all who oppose you are fools, cannot be a safe method.
Nor in spite of a conviction that much of the admiration
expressed for the “Transfiguration” is
lip-homage and tradition, ought the non-admiring to
assume that all of it is insincere. It is quite
compatible with modesty to be perfectly independent,
and with sincerity to be respectful to the opinions
and tastes of others. If you express any opinion,
you are bound to express your real opinion; let critics
and admirers utter what dithyrambs they please.
Were this terror of not being thought correct in taste
once got rid of, how many stereotyped judgments on
books and pictures would be broken up! and the result
of this sincerity would be some really valuable criticism.
In the presence of Raphael’s “Sistine
Madonna,” Titian’s “Peter the Martyr,”
or Masaccio’s great frescoes in the Brancacci
Chapel, one feels as if there had been nothing written
about these mighty works, so little does any eulogy
discriminate the elements of their profound effects,
so little have critics expressed their own thoughts
and feelings. Yet every day some wandering connoisseur
stands before these pictures, and at once, without
waiting to let them sink deep into his mind, discovers
all the merits which are stereotyped in the criticisms,
and discovers nothing else. He does not wait
to feel, he is impatient to range himself with men
of taste; he discards all genuine impressions, replacing
them with vague conceptions of what he is expected
to see.
Inasmuch as Success must be determined
by the relation between the work and the public, the
sincerity which leads a man into open revolt against
established opinions may seem to be an obstacle.
Indeed, publishers, critics, and friends are always
loud in their prophecies against originality and independence
on this very ground; they do their utmost to stifle
every attempt at novelty, because they fix their eyes
upon a hypothetical public taste, and think that only
what has already been proved successful can again
succeed; forgetting that whatever has once been done
need not be done over again, and forgetting that what
is now commonplace was once originality. There
are cases in which a disregard of public opinion will
inevitably call forth opprobrium or neglect; but there
is no case in which Sincerity is not strength.
If I advance new views in Philosophy or Theology,
I cannot expect to have many adherents among minds
altogether unprepared for such views; yet it is certain
that even those who most fiercely oppose me will recognise
the power of my voice if it is not a mere echo; and
the very novelty will challenge attention, and at
last gain adherents if my views have any real insight.
At any rate the point to be considered is this, that
whether the novel views excite opposition or applause,
the one condition of their success is that they be
believed in by the propagator. The public can
only be really moved by what is genuine. Even
an error if believed in will have greater force than
an insincere truth. Lip-advocacy only rouses
lip-homage. It is belief which gives momentum.
Nor is it any serious objection to
what is here said, that insincerity and timid acquiescence
in the opinion and tastes of thc public do often gain
applause and temporary success. Sanding the sugar
is not immediately unprofitable. There is an
unpleasant popularity given to falsehood in this world
of ours; but we love the truth notwithstanding, and
with a more enduring love. Who does not know what
it is to listen to public speakers pouring forth expressions
of hollow belief and sham enthusiasm, snatching at
commonplaces with a fervour as of faith, emphasising
insincerities as if to make up by emphasis what is
wanting in feeling, all the while saying not only
what they do not believe, but what the listeners know
they do not believe, and what the listeners, though
they roar assent, do not themselves believe a
turbulence of sham, the very noise of which stuns
the conscience? Is such an orator really enviable,
although thunders of applause may have greeted his
efforts? Is that success, although the newspapers
all over the kingdom may be reporting the speech?
What influence remains when the noise of the shouts
has died away? Whereas, if on the same occasion
one man gave utterance to a sincere thought, even
if it were not a very wise thought, although the silence
of the public perhaps its hisses may
have produced an impression of failure, yet there is
success, for the thought will re-appear and mingle
with the thoughts of men to be adopted or combated
by them, and may perhaps in a few years mark out the
speaker as a man better worth listening to than the
noisy orator whose insincerity was so much cheered.
The same observation applies to books.
An author who waits upon the times, and utters only
what he thinks the world will like to hear, who sails
with the stream, admiring everything which it is “correct
taste” to admire, despising everything which
has not yet received that Hall-mark, sneering at the
thoughts of a great thinker not yet accepted as such,
and slavishly repeating the small phrases of a thinker
who has gained renown, flippant and contemptuous towards
opinions which he has not taken the trouble to understand,
and never venturing to oppose even the errors of men
in authority, such an author may indeed by dint of
a certain dexterity in assorting the mere husks of
opinion gain the applause of reviewers, who will call
him a thinker, and of indolent men and women who will
pronounce him “so clever ;” but triumphs
of this kind are like oratorical triumphs after dinner.
Every autumn the earth is strewed with the dead leaves
of such vernal successes.
I would not have the reader conclude
that because I advocate plain-speaking even of unpopular
views, I mean to imply that originality and sincerity
are always in opposition to public opinion. There
are many points both of doctrine and feeling in which
the world is not likely to be wrong. But in all
cases it is desirable that men should not pretend
to believe opinions which they really reject, or express
emotions they do not feel. And this rule is universal.
Even truthful and modest men will sometimes violate
the rule under the mistaken idea of being eloquent
by means of the diction of eloquence. This is
a source of bad Literature. There are certain
views in Religion, Ethics, and Politics, which readily
lend themselves to eloquence, because eloquent men
have written largely on them, and the temptation to
secure this facile effect often seduces men to advocate
these views in preference to views they really see
to be more rational. That this eloquence at second-hand
is but feeble in its effect, does not restrain others
from repeating it. Experience never seems to teach
them that grand speech comes only from grand thoughts,
passionate speech from passionate emotions. The
pomp and roll of words, the trick of phrase, the rhytlnn
and the gesture of an orator, may all be imitated,
but not his eloquence. No man was ever eloquent
by trying to be eloquent, but only by being so.
Trying leads to the vice of “fine writing” the
plague-spot of Literature, not only unhealthy in itself,
and vulgarising the grand language which should be
reserved for great thoughts, but encouraging that
tendency to select only those views upon which a spurious
enthusiasm can most readily graft the representative
abstractions and stirring suggestions which will move
public applause. The “fine writer”
will always prefer the opinion which is striking to
the opinion which is true. He frames his sentences
by the ear, and is only dissatisfied with them when
their cadences are ill-distributed, or their diction
is too familiar. It seldom occurs to him that
a sentence should accurately express his meaning and
no more; indeed there is not often a definite meaning
to be expressed, for the thought which arose vanished
while he tried to express it, and the sentence, instead
of being determined by and moulded on a thought, is
determined by some verbal suggestion. Open any
book or periodical, and see how frequently the writer
does not, cannot, mean what he says; and you will observe
that in general the defect does not arise from any
poverty in our language, but from the habitual carelessness
which allows expressions to be written down unchallenged
provided they are sufficiently harmonious, and not
glaringly inadequate.
The slapdash insincerity of modern
style entirely sets at nought the first principle
of writing, which is accuracy. The art of writing
is not, as many seem to imagine, the art of bringing
fine phrases into rhythmical order, but the art of
placing before the reader intelligible symbols of
the thoughts and feelings in the writer’s mind.
Endeavour to be faithful, and if there is any beauty
in your thought, your style will be beautiful; if
there is any real emotion to express, the expression
will be moving. Never rouge your style. Trust
to your native pallor rather than to cosmetics.
Try to make us see what you see and to feel what you
feel, and banish from your mind whatever phrases others
may have used to express what was in their thoughts,
but is not in yours. Have you never observed
what a light impression writers have produced, in
spite of a profusion of images, antithèses, witty
epigrams, and rolling periods, whereas some simpler
style, altogether wanting in such “brilliant
passage,” has gained the attention and respect
of thousands? Whatever is stuck on as ornament
affects us as ornament; we do not think an old hag
young and handsome because the jewels flash from her
brow and bosom; if we envy her wealth, we do not admire
her beauty.
What “fine writing” is
to prosaists, insincere imagery is to poets: it
is introduced for effect, not used as expression.
To the real poet an image comes spontaneously, or
if it comes as an afterthought, it is chosen because
it expresses his meaning and helps to paint the picture
which is in his mind, not because it is beautiful in
itself. It is a symbol, not an ornament.
Whether the image rise slowly before the mind during
contemplation, or is seen in the same flash which discloses
the picture, in each case it arises by natural association,
and is seen, not sought. The inferior
poet is dissatisfied with what he sees, and casts
about in search after something more striking.
He does not wait till an image is borne in upon the
tide of memory, he seeks for an image that will be
picturesque; and being without the delicate selective
instinct which guides the fine artist, he generally
chooses something which we feel to be not exactly
in its right place. He thus
“With gold and silver covers every part,
And hides with ornament his want of art.”
Be true to your own soul, and do not
try to express the thought of another. “If
some people,” says Ruskin, “really see
angels where others see only empty space, let them
paint angels: only let not anybody else think
they can paint an angel too, on any calculated principles
of the angelic.” Unhappily this is precisely
what so many will attempt, inspired by the success
of the angelic painter. Nor will the failure of
others warn them.
Whatever is sincerely felt or believed,
whatever forms part of the imaginative experience,
and is not simply imitation or hearsay, may fitly
be given to the world, and will always maintain an
infinite superiority over imitative splendour; because
although it by no means follows that whatever has
formed part of the artist’s experience must
be impressive, or can do without artistic presentation,
yet his artistic power will always be greater over
his own material than over another’s. Emerson
has well remarked “that those facts, words, persons
which dwell in a man’s memory without his being
able to say why, remain because they have a relation
to him not less real for being as yet unapprehended.
They are symbols of value to him as they can interpret
parts of his consciousness which he would vainly seek
words for in the conventional images of books and
other minds. What attracts my attention shall
have it; as I will go to the man who knocks at my door
while a thousand persons as worthy go by it to whom
I give no regard. It is enough that these particulars
speak to me. A few anecdotes, a few traits of
character, manners, faces, a few incidents have an
emphasis in your memory out of all proportion to their
apparent significance if you measure them by ordinary
standards. They relate to your gift. Let
them have their weight, and do not reject them, or
cast about for illustrations and facts more usual
in literature.”
In the notes to the last edition of
his poems, Wordsworth specified the particular occasions
which furnished him with particular images. It
was the things he had seen which he put into
his verses; and that is why they affect us. It
matters little whether the poet draws his images directly
from present experience, or indirectly from memory whether
the sight of the slow-sailing swan, that “floats
double swan and shadow” be at once transferred
to the scene of the poem he is writing, or come back
upon him in after years to complete some picture in
his mind; enough that the image be suggested, and
not sought.
The sentence from Ruskin, quoted just
now, will guard against the misconception that a writer,
because told to rely on his own experience, is enjoined
to forego the glory and delight of creation even of
fantastic types. He is only told never to pretend
to see what he has not seen. He is urged to follow
Imagination in her most erratic course, though like
a will-o’-wisp she lead over marsh and fen away
from the haunts of mortals; but not to pretend that
he is following a will-o’-wisp when his vagrant
fancy never was allured by one. It is idle to
paint fairies and goblins unless you have a genuine
vision of them which forces you to paint them.
They are poetical objects, but only to poetic minds.
“Be a plain photographer if you possibly can,”
says Ruskin, “if Nature meant you for anything
else she will force you to it; but never try to be
a prophet; go on quietly with your hard camp work,
and the spirit will come to you as it did to Eldad
and Medad if you are appointed to it.”
Yes: if you are appointed to it; if your faculties
are such that this high success is possible, it will
come, provided the faculties are employed with sincerity.
Otherwise it cannot come. No insincere effort
can secure it.
If the advice I give to reject every
insincerity in writing seem cruel, because it robs
the writer of so many of his effects –if
it seem disheartening to earnestly warn a man not
to try to be eloquent, but only to be eloquent
when his thoughts move with an impassioned Largo if
throwing a writer back upon his naked faculty seem
especially distasteful to those who have a painful
misgiving that their faculty is small, and that the
uttermost of their own power would be far from impressive,
my answer is that I have no hope of dissuading feeble
writers from the practice of insincerity, but as under
no circumstances can they become good writers and
achieve success, my analysis has no reference to them,
my advice has no aim at them. It is to the young
and strong, to the ambitious and the earnest, that
my words are addressed. It is to wipe the film
from their eyes, and make them see, as they will see
directly the truth is placed before them, how easily
we are all seduced into greater or less insincerity
of thought, of feeling, and of style, either by reliance
on other writers, from whom we catch the trick of
thought and turn of phrase, or from some preconceived
view of what the public will prefer. It is to
the young and strong I say: Watch vigilantly
every phrase you write, and assure yourself that it
expresses what you mean; watch vigilantly every thought
you express, and assure yourself that it is yours,
not another’s; you may share it with another,
but you must not adopt it from him for the nonce.
Of course, if you are writing humorously or dramatically,
you will not be expected to write your own serious
opinions. Humour may take its utmost licence,
yet be sincere. The dramatic genius may incarnate
itself in a hundred shapes, yet in each it will speak
what it feels to be the truth. If you are imaginatively
representing the feelings of another, as in some playful
exaggeration or some dramatic personation, the truth
required of you is imaginative truth, not your personal
views and feelings. But when you write in your
own person you must be rigidly veracious, neither
pretending to admire what you do not admire, or to
despise what in secret you rather like, nor surcharging
your admiration and enthusiasm to bring you into unison
with the public chorus. This vigilance may render
Literature more laborious; but no one ever supposed
that success was to be had on easy terms; and if you
only write one sincere page where you might have written
twenty insincere pages, the one page is worth writing it
is Literature.
Sincerity is not only effective and
honourable, it is also much less difficult than is
commonly supposed. To take a trifling example:
If for some reason I cannot, or do not, choose to
verify a quotation which may be useful to my purpose,
what is to prevent my saying that the quotation is
taken at second-hand? It is true, if my quotations
are for the most part second-hand and are acknowledged
as such, my erudition will appear scanty. But
it will only appear what it is. Why should I
pretend to an erudition which is not mine? Sincerity
forbids it. Prudence whispers that the pretence
is, after all, vain, because those, and those alone,
who can rightly estimate erudition will infallibly
detect my pretence, whereas those whom I have deceived
were not worth deceiving. Yet in spite of Sincerity
and Prudence, how shamelessly men compile second-hand
references, and display in borrowed footnotes a pretence
of labour and of accuracy! I mention this merely
to show how, even in the humbler class of compilers,
the Principle of Sincerity may find fit illustrations,
and how honest work, even in references, belongs to
the same category as honest work in philosophy or poetry.
Editor.