It must be remembered that George
Eliot does not use the novel merely for the purpose
of inculcating certain doctrines, and that her genius
for artistic creation is of a very high order.
In dealing with her as a thinker and as a moral and
religious teacher, she is to be regarded, first of
all, as a poet and an artist. Her ethics are
subordinate to her art; her religion is subsidiary
to her genius. That she always deliberately set
about the task of introducing her positivism into the
substance of her novels is not to be supposed.
This would be to imply a forgetfulness on her part
of her own methods, and a prostration of art to purposes
she would have scorned to adopt. This is evidently
true, however, that certain features of the positive
and the evolution philosophy had so thoroughly approved
themselves to her mind as to cause them to be accepted
as a completely satisfactory explanation of the world,
so far as any explanation is possible. So heartily
were they received, so fully did they become incorporated
with the substance of her thinking, that she viewed
all human experiences in their light. They had
ceased to be theory and speculation with her.
When she thought about the world, when she observed
the acts of men, the positivist explanation was at
once applied, and instinctively.
That she did teach positivism is unfortunately
true, so far as her literary touch and expression
is concerned. That philosophy affects all her
books with its subtly insinuating flavor, and it gives
meaning and bias to most of them. They thus gain
in definiteness of purpose, in moral vigor, in minutely
faithful study of some phases of human experience,
and in a massive impression of thoughtfulness which
her work creates. At the same time, they undoubtedly
lose in value as studies of life; in free range of
expression for her genius, her poetry and her art;
and in that spiritual vision which looks forward with
keen gazing eyes of hope and confident inquiry.
Her teaching, like most teaching,
is a mingled good and evil. In more than one
direction her ethical and religious influence was most
wholesome and effective. She brought into clear
light a few great facts, and made them the more conspicuous
by the strong emphasis she gave them. This is,
in the main, the method of all teaching and of all
progress. Development seldom proceeds in a direct
line, but rather, so far as man is concerned, by forcible
emphasis laid on some great fact which has been previously
neglected. The idealism of a previous age had
shown the value of certain facts and tendencies in
human nature, but it had exaggerated some faculties
and capacities of man, as well as neglected others.
In consequence, our own time swings to the other extreme,
and cannot have too much of evolution and positivism.
Idealism is in human nature, and will
give itself expression. Positivism is also a
result of our experience and of our study of the universe,
both material and mental; it is a result of the desire
for definite knowledge. As a re-action against
the excesses of idealism it is a powerful leaven,
and it brings into necessary prominence those facts
which are neglected by the opposite philosophy.
It takes account of facts, and scorns mysticism; and
it thus appeals to a deep-seated bias of the time.
George Eliot’s books have an
interest as an attempt at an interpretation of life
from its more practical and realistic side, and not
less as a re-action against the influences of very
nearly all the great literary minds of the earlier
half of the century in England. Under the lead
of Coleridge and Wordsworth, and influenced by German
thought and literature, a remarkable movement was
then developed in English literature. The outcome
of that movement has been surpassed only by that of
the age of Shakspere. Freshness of thought, love
of nature, profound humanitarian convictions, and
spontaneity wedded to great largeness of ideas, characterize
this period and its noble work. Such an age is
almost invariably followed by an age of re-action,
criticism, realism and analysis. An instinctive
demand for a portrayal of the more positive side of
life, and the influence of science, have developed
a new literary school. For doctrine it teaches
agnosticism, and in method it cares mainly for art
and beauty of form. Towards the development of
the new school George Eliot has been a leading influence,
though her sympathies have not gone with all its tendencies
and results.
If Wordsworth exaggerated the importance
of the intuitive and personal, George Eliot equally
exaggerated the value of the historic and hereditary.
It was desirable, however, that the relations of life
to the past should be brought out more distinctly
by a literary development of their relations to the
present, and that the influence of social heredity
should be seen as affecting life on all sides.
Tradition is a large and persistent element in the
better life of the race, while the past certainly has
a powerful influence over the present. This fact
was neglected by Wordsworth, and especially is it
neglected by the intuitive philosophies. They
ignore the lessons of the past, and assume that a
new and perfect world is to be evolved from the depths
of consciousness. That to think a better world
is to create a better world, they seem to take for
granted, while the fact is that the truer life is
the result of a painful and long-continued struggle
against adverse conditions. What has been, persists
in remaining, and the past, with all its narrowness
and prejudices, continues to influence men more powerfully
than does clear thought or regard for the truth.
Emotion and sentiment cling about what has become
sacred with age. Channels for thought and activity
having once been made, it is very difficult to abandon
them for untried paths approved even by reason.
The historic view is one of much importance,
and is likely to be overlooked by the poets and novelists.
It is also ignored by the radicals in morals and religion.
Much which George Eliot says on this subject is of
great value, and may be heeded with the utmost profit.
Her words of wisdom, however, lose much of their value
because they utterly ignore those spontaneous and
supernatural elements of man’s higher life which
lift it quite out of the region of dependence on history.
There is something to be said in behalf
of George Eliot’s attitude towards religion,
which caused her to hold it in reverence, even when
rejecting the objective validity of its dogmas.
Yet much more is to be said for that other attitude,
which is faithful to the law of reason, and believes
that reason is competent to say some truer and larger
word on a subject of such vital importance and such
constant interest to man. That both reason and
tradition are to be listened to reverently is true,
but George Eliot so zealously espoused the cause of
tradition as to give it an undue prominence.
Her lesson was needed, however, and we may be all the
better able to profit by it because she was so much
an enthusiast in proclaiming its value. The even
poise of perfect truth is no more to be had from her
pages than from those of others.
The emphasis she laid on feeling and
sentiment was a needed one, as a counterpoise to the
exaggerations of rationalism. Man does live in
his feelings more than in his reason. He is a
being of sentiment, a creature of impulse, his social
life is one of the affections. In all the ranges
of his moral, religious and social life he is guided
mainly by his emotions and sentiments. It cannot
be said, however, as George Eliot would have us say,
that these are human born and have no higher meaning.
They are the outgrowth of spiritual reality, as well
as of human experience; they repeat the foregleams
and foresights of a
“far-off
divine event,
To which the whole creation moves.”
Life is enriched and flooded with
light by the emotions, and feeling, true and tender
and pure, is as much the symbol of humanity as reason
itself. It was therefore well that some one should
attempt to justify the emotional life against the
aspersions of those who have done it grave injustice.
It is true that man is not a being who wholly arrives
at his method of life through reason, but feeling
lends quite as important aid. He does not only
think, but he has emotions as well; he not only weighs
evidence, but he acts by impulse. He is continually
led by the emotions, sentiments and impulses created
for him by the life of ages past. Without emotion
there could be no art, no poetry and no music.
Without emotion there would be no religion and no
spiritual life. Sentiment sweetens, beautifies
and endears all that is human and natural.
Emotion and the affections, however,
seem to be shorn of their highest beauty and glory
when they are restricted to a merely earthly origin
and compass of power. It is altogether impossible
to believe that their own impulse to look beyond the
human is a delusion, and that they really have nothing
to report that is valid from beyond the little round
which man treads. To believe in the human beauty
and glory of the feelings, and to rejoice in their
power to unite us to our kind, need imply no forgetfulness
of their demand for a wider expression and a higher
communion.
Her theory of the origin of feeling
is not to be accepted. It means something more
than an inheritance of ancestral experience. It
is the result rather than the cause of reason, for
reason has an influence she did not acknowledge, and
an original capacity which she never saw. Her
view of feeling was mainly theoretical, for she was
led in her attitude towards the facts of life, not
by sentiment, but by reason. Hers was a thoughtful
rather than an impulsive mind, and given to logic more
than to emotion.
Her enthusiasm for altruism, her zeal
for humanity, lends a delightful feature to her books.
It gives a glow and a consecration to her work, and
makes her as great a prophet as positivism is capable
of creating. And it is no idle power she awakens
in her positivist faith in man. She shames those
who claim a broader and better faith. Zeal for
man is no mean gospel, as she gives life and meaning
to it in her books. To live for others, too many
are not likely to do. She made altruism beautiful,
she made it a consecration and a religion. Those
who cannot accept her agnosticism and her positivism
may learn much from her faith in man and from her enthusiasm
for humanity. No faith is worth much which does
not lead to a truer and a more helpful love of man.
Any faith is good in so far as it makes us more humane
and sympathetic. In this regard, the radicalism
of George Eliot was a great advance on much of the
free-thinking of our century. She desired to
build, not to destroy. She was no iconoclast,
no hater of what other men love and venerate.
Her tendencies were all on the side of progress, good
order and social growth.
Her conception of the organic social
life of the race is one of great value. It led
her to believe in the possibility of a social organization
in the future based on science, and better capable
of meeting all the wants of mankind than the more
personal and competitive methods have done. This
belief in the organic unity of the race is not necessarily
positivist in its character, for Hegel entertained
it as fully as does Herbert Spencer. The larger
social life will come, however, as individuals are
moved to lead the way, and not alone as the result
of a general evolutionary process. On its mental
side, her social theory is to be regarded with grave
suspicions, for it brings all minds to the same level.
No mind of commanding influence is to be found in
her books. No powerful intellect gives greatness
to any of her plots. Her Felix Holt is not a
man of original and positive thought. We accept,
but do not enthusiastically admire him. Deronda
is a noble character, but he in no sense represents
the largest things of which a social leader is capable.
He disappoints and is weak, and he has no power to
create the highest kind of leadership. In other
words, he is not a great man. The world’s
reformers have been of another temper and mettle.
He is no Mazzini, no Luther. George Eliot’s
social theories loft no room for such men. They
were superfluous in her social system. The man
not to be explained by heredity and tradition had
no place in her books; and no genius, no great man,
can ever be explained by heredity and tradition alone.
George Eliot evidently desired to
destroy individualism as a social force. The
individual, according to her teaching, is to renounce
himself for the sake of the race. He is to live,
not as a personal being, but as a member of the social
organization; to develop his altruistic nature, not
to perfect his personal character. The finer
flavor of personality is brushed mercilessly away
by this method.
Reason needs to be justified in opposition
to her excessive praise of feeling. Meanwhile,
the capacity of man to live a life higher than that
of his social state is to be asserted. He is
indeed a member of humanity, but humanity does not
absorb him to the cost of his personality. Life
is strong in those ages in which the individual is
able to assert his own personality, in opposition
to what is imperfect and untrue in the life of his
time. This failure to recognize the worth and
capacity of the individual is a most serious defect
in George Eliot’s work, and mars it in many
directions. A very competent critic has shown
how serious is the limitation arising in this manner,
and permeating her books with a false conception of
life.
“So far as George Eliot’s
life is concerned,” says Mr. Stopford Brooke,
“she was eager in her self-development, and as
eager in her sympathies. But it was a different
matter in the main drift of her work. She lowered
the power of individualism. Nay, she did not believe
in its having any self-caused or God-caused existence.
Few have individualized their characters more than
she did, and of these characters we have many distinct
types. But she individualized them with, I may
say, almost the set purpose of showing that their
individualism was to be sacrificed to the general
welfare of the race. The more her characters cling
to their individuality the more they fail in reaching
happiness or peace. If they are noble characters,
they are finally obliged, through their very nobility,
to surrender all their ideals, all their personal
hopes, all the individual ends they hoped to develop;
and they reach peace finally only through utter surrender
of personality in humanity. The characters in
her books who do not do this, who cling to their individuality
and maintain it, succeed in life, for the most part,
if they are strong; are broken to pieces if they are
weak; but in all cases, save one, are not the noble
but the ignoble characters. The whole of her
books is a suppressed attack on individualism, and
an exaltation of self-renunciation as the only force
of progress, as the only ground of morality.
I leave aside here, as apart from the moral side of
the subject, the view that individual power or weakness
of any kind is the consequence of the past, of race,
of physical causes. What a man is found to do
is not affected by that, in her view.... No one
can deny that the morality is a lofty one, and, as
far as it asserts self-renunciation, entirely useful;
we have with all our hearts to thank George Eliot for
that part of her work. But when sacrifice of
self is made, in its last effort, equivalent to the
sacrifice of individuality, the doctrine of self-renunciation
is driven to a vicious extreme. It is not self-sacrifice
which is then demanded, it is suicide ... Fully
accepted, it would reduce the whole of the human race
to hopelessness. That, indeed, is the last result.
A sad and fatal hopelessness of life broods over all
the nobler characters. All their early ideals
are sacrificed, all their early joys depart, all the
pictures they formed are blotted out. They gain
peace through renunciation, after long failure; some
happiness in yielding to the inevitable, and harmonizing
life with it; and some blessedness in doing all they
can for the progress of those who follow them, for
the good of those that are with them. Their self
is conquered, not through ennoblement of personality,
but through annihilation of personality. And having
surrendered their separate personality, they then attain
the fitting end, silence forevermore. It is no
wonder that no characters are so sad, that none steep
the reader in such hopelessness of joy, as the noble
characters of the later works of George Eliot.
They want the mighty power, the enkindling hopes,
the resurrection of life, the joy and rapture which
deepens towards death and enables man to take up the
ideals of youth again.”
If too severe in some directions,
this criticism is substantially sound. It does
not matter what theory of personality we adopt, in
a philosophical sense, if that theory upholds personal
confidence and force of will. If it does not
do this, the whole result is evil. This lack of
faith in personality saddened all the work done by
George Eliot. In theory a believer in an ever-brightening
future, and no pessimist, yet the outcome of her work
is dark with despondency and grief.
Life is sad, hard and ascetic in her
treatment of it. An ascetic tone runs through
all her work, the result of her theories of renunciation.
The same sternness and cheerlessness is to be seen
in the poetry and painting of the pre-Raphaelites.
The joy, freshness and sunniness of Raphael is not
to be found in their work. Life is painful, puritanic
and depressing to them. Old age seems to be upon
them, or the decadence of a people that has once been
great. Human nature does not need that this strain
be put upon it. Life is stronger when more assertive
of itself. It has a right to assert itself in
defiance of mere rules, and only when it does so is
it true and great. The ascetic tone is one of
the worst results of a scientific view of the world
as applied to literature; for it is thoroughly false
both in fact and in sentiment. The strong, hopeful,
youthful look at life is the one which literature
demands, and because it is the nearest the heart and
spirit of life itself. The dead nation produces
a dead literature. The age made doubtful by an
excess of science produces a literature burdened with
sadness and pain. Great and truthful as it may
be, it lacks in power to conquer the world. It
shows, not the power of Homer, but the power of Lucretius.
Her altruism has its side of truth,
but not all of the truth is in it. Any system
of thought which sees nothing beyond man is not likely
to find that which is most characteristic in man himself.
He is to be fathomed, if fathomed at all, by some
other line than that of his own experience. If
he explains the universe, the universe is also necessary
to explain him. Man apart from the supersensuous
is as little to be understood as man apart from humanity.
He belongs to a Universal Order quite as much as he
belongs to the human order. Man may be explained
by evolution, but evolution is not to be explained
by anything in the nature of man. It requires
some larger field of vision to take note of that elemental
law. Not less true is it that mind does not come
obediently under this method of explanation, that
it demands account of how matter is transformed into
thought. The law of thought needs to be solved
after mind is evolved.
There is occasion for surprise that
a mind so acute and logical as George Eliot’s
did not perceive that the evolution philosophy has
failed to settle any of the greater problems suggested
by Kant. The studies of Darwin and Spencer have
certainly made it impossible longer to accept Locke’s
theory of the origin of all knowledge in individual
experience, but they have not in any degree explained
the process of thought or the origin of ideas.
The gulf between the physiological processes in the
brain and thought has not been bridged even by a rope
walk. The total disparity of mind and matter
resists all efforts to reduce them to one. The
utmost which the evolution philosophy has so far done,
is to attempt to prove that mind is a function of
matter or of the physiological process. This conclusion
is as far as possible from being that of the unity
of mind and matter.
That man is very ignorant, and that
this world ought to demand the greater share of his
attention and energies, are propositions every reasonable
person is ready to accept. Granted their truth,
all that is necessarily true in agnosticism has been
arrived at. It is a persistent refusal to see
what lies behind outward facts which gives agnosticism
all its practical justification. Art itself is
a sufficient refutation of the assertion that we know
nothing of what lies behind the apparent. That
we know something of causes, every person who uses
his own mind may be aware. At the same time,
the rejection of the doctrine of rights argues obedience
to a theory, rather than humble acceptance of the
facts of history. That doctrine of rights, so
scorned by George Eliot, has wrought most of the great
and wholesome social changes of modern times.
Her theory of duties can show no historic results
whatever.
To separate George Eliot’s theories
from her genius it seems impossible to do, but this
it is necessary to do in order to give both their proper
place. All praise, her work demands on its side
where genius is active. It is as a thinker, as
a theorizer, she is to be criticised and to be declared
wanting. Her work was crippled by her philosophy,
or if not crippled, then it was made less strong of
limb and vigorous of body by that same philosophy.
It is true of her as of Wordsworth, that she grew prosy
because she tried to be philosophical. It is true
of her as it is not true of him, that her work lacks
in the breadth which a large view of the world gives.
His was no provincial conception of nature or of man.
Hers was so in a most emphatic sense. The philosophy
she adopted is not and cannot become the philosophy
of more than a small number of persons. In the
nature of the case it is doomed to be the faith of
a few students and cultured people. It can stir
no common life, develop no historic movements, inaugurate
no reforms, nor give to life a diviner meaning.
Whether it be true or not, and this need
not here be asked, this social and moral
limitation of its power is enough to condemn it for
the purposes of literature. In so far as George
Eliot’s work is artistic, poetic, moral and human,
it is very great, and no word too strong can be said
in its praise. It is not too excessive enthusiasm
to call her, on the whole, the equal of any novelist.
Her genius is commanding and elemental. She has
originality, strength of purpose, and a profound insight
into character. Yet her work is weakened by its
attachment to a narrow theory of life. Her philosophy
is transitory in its nature. It cannot hold its
own, as developed by her, for any great length of
time. It has the elements of its own destruction
in itself. The curious may read her for her speculations;
the many will read her for her realism, her humanity
and her genius. In truth, then, it would have
been better if her work had been inspired by great
spiritual aims and convictions.