Thoroughly worldly people never
understand even the world; they rely altogether on
a few cynical maxims which are not true. Once
I remember walking with a prosperous publisher, who
made a remark which I had often heard before; it is,
indeed, almost a motto of the modern world.
Yet I had heard it once too often, and I saw suddenly
that there was nothing in it. The publisher
said of somebody, “That man will get on; he believes
in himself.” And I remember that as I lifted
my head to listen, my eye caught an omnibus on which
was written “Hanwell.” I said to
him, “Shall I tell you where the men are who
believe most in themselves? For I can tell you.
I know of men who believe in themselves more colossally
than Napoleon or Cæsar. I know where flames
the fixed star of certainty and success. I can
guide you to the thrones of the Super-men. The
men who really believe in themselves are all in lunatic
asylums.” He said mildly that there were
a good many men after all who believed in themselves
and who were not in lunatic asylums. “Yes,
there are,” I retorted, “and you of all
men ought to know them. That drunken poet from
whom you would not take a dreary tragedy, he believed
in himself. That elderly minister with an epic
from whom you were hiding in a back room, he believed
in himself. If you consulted your business experience
instead of your ugly individualistic philosophy, you
would know that believing in himself is one of the
commonest signs of a rotter. Actors who can’t
act believe in themselves; and debtors who won’t
pay. It would be much truer to say that a man
will certainly fail, because he believes in himself.
Complete self-confidence is not merely a sin; complete
self-confidence is a weakness. Believing utterly
in one’s self is a hysterical and superstitious
belief like believing in Joanna Southcote: the
man who has it has `Hanwell’ written on his
face as plain as it is written on that omnibus.”
And to all this my friend the publisher made this
very deep and effective reply, “Well, if a man
is not to believe in himself, in what is he to believe?”
After a long pause I replied, “I will go home
and write a book in answer to that question.”
This is the book that I have written in answer to
it.
But I think this book may well
start where our argument started- in the
neighbourhood of the mad-house. Modern masters
of science are much impressed with the need of beginning
all inquiry with a fact. The ancient masters
of religion were quite equally impressed with that
necessity. They began with the fact of sin-a
fact as practical as potatoes. Whether or no
man could be washed in miraculous waters, there was
no doubt at any rate that he wanted washing.
But certain religious leaders in London, not mere materialists,
have begun in our day not to deny the highly disputable
water, but to deny the indisputable dirt. Certain
new theologians dispute original sin, which is the
only part of Christian theology which can really be
proved. Some followers of the Reverend R.J.Campbell,
in their almost too fastidious spirituality, admit
divine sinlessness, which they cannot see even in
their dreams. But they essentially deny human
sin, which they can see in the street. The strongest
saints and the strongest sceptics alike took positive
evil as the starting-point of their argument.
If it be true (as it certainly is) that a man can
feel exquisite happiness in skinning a cat, then the
religious philosopher can only draw one of two deductions.
He must either deny the existence of God, as all atheists
do; or he must deny the present union between God
and man, as all Christians do. The new theologians
seem to think it a highly rationalistic solution to
deny the cat.
In this remarkable situation
it is plainly not now possible (with any hope of a
universal appeal) to start, as our fathers did, with
the fact of sin. This very fact which was to
them (and is to me) as plain as a pikestaff, is the
very fact that has been specially diluted or denied.
But though moderns deny the existence of sin, I do
not think that they have yet denied the existence of
a lunatic asylum. We all agree still that there
is a collapse of the intellect as unmistakable as
a falling house. Men deny hell, but not, as
yet, Hanwell. For the purpose of our primary
argument the one may very well stand where the other
stood. I mean that as all thoughts and theories
were once judged by whether they tended to make a
man lose his soul, so for our present purpose all modern
thoughts and theories may be judged by whether they
tend to make a man lose his wits.
It is true that some speak lightly
and loosely of insanity as in itself attractive.
But a moment’s thought will show that if disease
is beautiful, it is generally some one else’s
disease. A blind man may be picturesque; but
it requires two eyes to see the picture. And
similarly even the wildest poetry of insanity can
only be enjoyed by the sane. To the insane man
his insanity is quite prosaic, because it is quite
true. A man who thinks himself a chicken is
to himself as ordinary as a chicken. A man who
thinks he is a bit of glass is to himself as dull
as a bit of glass. It is the homogeneity of his
mind which makes him dull, and which makes him mad.
It is only because we see the irony of his idea that
we think him even amusing; it is only because he does
not see the irony of his idea that he is put in Hanwell
at all. In short, oddities only strike ordinary
people. Oddities do not strike odd people.
This is why ordinary people have a much more exciting
time; while odd people are always complaining of the
dulness of life. This is also why the new novels
die so quickly, and why the old fairy tales endure
for ever. The old fairy tale makes the hero
a normal human boy; it is his adventures that are startling;
they startle him because he is normal. But in
the modern psychological novel the hero is abnormal;
the centre is not central. Hence the fiercest
adventures fail to affect him adequately, and the
book is monotonous. You can make a story out
of a hero among dragons; but not out of a dragon among
dragons. The fairy tale discusses what a sane
man will do in a mad world. The sober realistic
novel of to-day discusses what an essential lunatic
will do in a dull world.
Let us begin, then, with the
mad-house; from this evil and fantastic inn let us
set forth on our intellectual journey. Now, if
we are to glance at the philosophy of sanity, the
first thing to do in the matter is to blot out one
big and common mistake. There is a notion adrift
everywhere that imagination, especially mystical imagination,
is dangerous to man’s mental balance. Poets
are commonly spoken of as psychologically unreliable;
and generally there is a vague association between
wreathing laurels in your hair and sticking straws
in it. Facts and history utterly contradict this
view. Most of the very great poets have been
not only sane, but extremely business-like; and if
Shakespeare ever really held horses, it was because
he was much the safest man to hold them. Imagination
does not breed insanity. Exactly what does breed
insanity is reason. Poets do not go mad; but
chess-players do. Mathematicians go mad, and
cashiers; but creative artists very seldom.
I am not, as will be seen, in any sense attacking
logic: I only say that this danger does lie
in logic, not in imagination. Artistic paternity
is as wholesome as physical paternity. Moreover,
it is worthy of remark that when a poet really was
morbid it was commonly because he had some weak spot
of rationality on his brain. Poe, for instance,
really was morbid; not because he was poetical, but
because he was specially analytical. Even chess
was too poetical for him; he disliked chess because
it was full of knights and castles, like a poem.
He avowedly preferred the black discs of draughts,
because they were more like the mere black dots on
a diagram. Perhaps the strongest case of all
is this: that only one great English poet went
mad, Cowper. And he was definitely driven mad
by logic, by the ugly and alien logic of predestination.
Poetry was not the disease, but the medicine; poetry
partly kept him in health. He could sometimes
forget the red and thirsty hell to which his hideous
necessitarianism dragged him among the wide waters
and the white flat lilies of the Ouse. He was
damned by John Calvin; he was almost saved by John
Gilpin. Everywhere we see that men do not go
mad by dreaming. Critics are much madder than
poets. Homer is complete and calm enough; it
is his critics who tear him into extravagant tatters.
Shakespeare is quite himself; it is only some of
his critics who have discovered that he was somebody
else. And though St. John the Evangelist saw
many strange monsters in his vision, he saw no creature
so wild as one of his own commentators. The general
fact is simple. Poetry is sane because it floats
easily in an infinite sea; reason seeks to cross the
infinite sea, and so make it finite. The result
is mental exhaustion, like the physical exhaustion
of Mr. Holbein. To accept everything is an exercise,
to understand everything a strain. The poet only
desires exaltation and expansion, a world to stretch
himself in. The poet only asks to get his head
into the heavens. It is the logician who seeks
to get the heavens into his head. And it is his
head that splits.
It is a small matter, but not
irrelevant, that this striking mistake is commonly
supported by a striking misquotation. We have
all heard people cite the celebrated line of Dryden
as “Great genius is to madness near allied.”
But Dryden did not say that great genius was to madness
near allied. Dryden was a great genius himself,
and knew better. It would have been hard to find
a man more romantic than he, or more sensible.
What Dryden said was this, “Great wits are
oft to madness near allied”; and that is true.
It is the pure promptitude of the intellect that
is in peril of a breakdown. Also people might
remember of what sort of man Dryden was talking.
He was not talking of any unworldly visionary like
Vaughan or George Herbert. He was talking of
a cynical man of the world, a sceptic, a diplomatist,
a great practical politician. Such men are indeed
to madness near allied. Their incessant calculation
of their own brains and other people’s brains
is a dangerous trade. It is always perilous to
the mind to reckon up the mind. A flippant person
has asked why we say, “As mad as a hatter.”
A more flippant person might answer that a hatter
is mad because he has to measure the human head.
And if great reasoners are often
maniacal, it is equally true that maniacs are commonly
great reasoners. When I was engaged in a controversy
with the Clarion on the matter of free will,
that able writer Mr. R.B.Suthers said that free will
was lunacy, because it meant causeless actions, and
the actions of a lunatic would be causeless.
I do not dwell here upon the disastrous lapse in
determinist logic. Obviously if any actions,
even a lunatic’s, can be causeless, determinism
is done for. If the chain of causation can be
broken for a madman, it can be broken for a man.
But my purpose is to point out something more practical.
It was natural, perhaps, that a modern Marxian Socialist
should not know anything about free will. But
it was certainly remarkable that a modern Marxian
Socialist should not know anything about lunatics.
Mr. Suthers evidently did not know anything about lunatics.
The last thing that can be said of a lunatic is that
his actions are causeless. If any human acts
may loosely be called causeless, they are the minor
acts of a healthy man; whistling as he walks; slashing
the grass with a stick; kicking his heels or rubbing
his hands. It is the happy man who does the useless
things; the sick man is not strong enough to be idle.
It is exactly such careless and causeless actions
that the madman could never understand; for the madman
(like the determinist) generally sees too much cause
in everything. The madman would read a conspiratorial
significance into those empty activities. He
would think that the lopping of the grass was an attack
on private property. He would think that the
kicking of the heels was a signal to an accomplice.
If the madman could for an instant become careless,
he would become sane. Every one who has had
the misfortune to talk with people in the heart or
on the edge of mental disorder, knows that their most
sinister quality is a horrible clarity of detail; a
connecting of one thing with another in a map more
elaborate than a maze. If you argue with a madman,
it is extremely probable that you will get the worst
of it; for in many ways his mind moves all the quicker
for not being delayed by the things that go with good
judgment. He is not hampered by a sense of humour
or by charity, or by the dumb certainties of experience.
He is the more logical for losing certain sane affections.
Indeed, the common phrase for insanity is in this
respect a misleading one. The madman is not the
man who has lost his reason. The madman is the
man who has lost everything except his reason.
The madman’s explanation
of a thing is always complete, and often in a purely
rational sense satisfactory. Or, to speak more
strictly, the insane explanation, if not conclusive,
is at least unanswerable; this may be observed specially
in the two or three commonest kinds of madness.
If a man says (for instance) that men have a conspiracy
against him, you cannot dispute it except by saying
that all the men deny that they are conspirators;
which is exactly what conspirators would do.
His explanation covers the facts as much as yours.
Or if a man says that he is the rightful King of England,
it is no complete answer to say that the existing
authorities call him mad; for if he were King of England
that might be the wisest thing for the existing authorities
to do. Or if a man says that he is Jesus Christ,
it is no answer to tell him that the world denies his
divinity; for the world denied Christ’s.
Nevertheless he is wrong.
But if we attempt to trace his error in exact terms,
we shall not find it quite so easy as we had supposed.
Perhaps the nearest we can get to expressing it is
to say this: that his mind moves in a perfect
but narrow circle. A small circle is quite as
infinite as a large circle; but, though it is quite
as infinite, it is not so large. In the same
way the insane explanation is quite as complete as
the sane one, but it is not so large. A bullet
is quite as round as the world, but it is not the world.
There is such a thing as a narrow universality; there
is such a thing as a small and cramped eternity; you
may see it in many modern religions. Now, speaking
quite externally and empirically, we may say that
the strongest and most unmistakable mark of madness
is this combination between a logical completeness
and a spiritual contraction. The lunatic’s
theory explains a large number of things, but it does
not explain them in a large way. I mean that
if you or I were dealing with a mind that was growing
morbid, we should be chiefly concerned not so much
to give it arguments as to give it air, to convince
it that there was something cleaner and cooler outside
the suffocation of a single argument. Suppose,
for instance, it were the first case that I took as
typical; suppose it were the case of a man who accused
everybody of conspiring against him. If we could
express our deepest feelings of protest and appeal
against this obsession, I suppose we should say something
like this: “Oh, I admit that you have your
case and have it by heart, and that many things do
fit into other things as you say. I admit that
your explanation explains a great deal; but what a
great deal it leaves out! Are there no other
stories in the world except yours; and are all men
busy with your business? Suppose we grant the
details; perhaps when the man in the street did not
seem to see you it was only his cunning; perhaps when
the policeman asked you your name it was only because
he knew it already. But how much happier you
would be if you only knew that these people cared
nothing about you! How much larger your life
would be if your self could become smaller in it;
if you could really look at other men with common curiosity
and pleasure; if you could see them walking as they
are in their sunny selfishness and their virile indifference!
You would begin to be interested in them, because
they were not interested in you. You would break
out of this tiny and tawdry theatre in which your
own little plot is always being played, and you would
find yourself under a freer sky, in a street full
of splendid strangers.” Or suppose it were
the second case of madness, that of a man who claims
the crown, your impulse would be to answer, “All
right! Perhaps you know that you are the King
of England; but why do you care? Make one magnificent
effort and you will be a human being and look down
on all the kings of the earth.” Or it might
be the third case, of the madman who called himself
Christ. If we said what we felt, we should say,
“So you are the Creator and Redeemer of the world:
but what a small world it must be! What a little
heaven you must inhabit, with angels no bigger than
butterflies! How sad it must be to be God; and
an inadequate God! Is there really no life fuller
and no love more marvellous than yours; and is it
really in your small and painful pity that all flesh
must put its faith? How much happier you would
be, how much more of you there would be, if the hammer
of a higher God could smash your small cosmos, scattering
the stars like spangles, and leave you in the open,
free like other men to look up as well as down!”
And it must be remembered that
the most purely practical science does take this view
of mental evil; it does not seek to argue with it
like a heresy but simply to snap it like a spell.
Neither modern science nor ancient religion believes
in complete free thought. Theology rebukes certain
thoughts by calling them blasphemous. Science
rebukes certain thoughts by calling them morbid.
For example, some religious societies discouraged
men more or less from thinking about sex. The
new scientific society definitely discourages men from
thinking about death; it is a fact, but it is considered
a morbid fact. And in dealing with those whose
morbidity has a touch of mania, modern science cares
far less for pure logic than a dancing Dervish.
In these cases it is not enough that the unhappy man
should desire truth; he must desire health.
Nothing can save him but a blind hunger for normality,
like that of a beast. A man cannot think himself
out of mental evil; for it is actually the organ of
thought that has become diseased, ungovernable, and,
as it were, independent. He can only be saved
by will or faith. The moment his mere reason
moves, it moves in the old circular rut; he will go
round and round his logical circle, just as a man
in a third-class carriage on the Inner Circle will
go round and round the Inner Circle unless he performs
the voluntary, vigorous, and mystical act of getting
out at Gower Street. Decision is the whole business
here; a door must be shut for ever. Every remedy
is a desperate remedy. Every cure is a miraculous
cure. Curing a madman is not arguing with a philosopher;
it is casting out a devil. And however quietly
doctors and psychologists may go to work in the matter,
their attitude is profoundly intolerant-
as intolerant as Bloody Mary. Their attitude
is really this: that the man must stop thinking,
if he is to go on living. Their counsel is one
of intellectual amputation. If thy head
offend thee, cut it off; for it is better, not merely
to enter the Kingdom of Heaven as a child, but to
enter it as an imbecile, rather than with your whole
intellect to be cast into hell- or into
Hanwell.
Such is the madman of experience;
he is commonly a reasoner, frequently a successful
reasoner. Doubtless he could be vanquished in
mere reason, and the case against him put logically.
But it can be put much more precisely in more general
and even aesthetic terms. He is in the clean
and well-lit prison of one idea: he is sharpened
to one painful point. He is without healthy hesitation
and healthy complexity. Now, as I explain in
the introduction, I have determined in these early
chapters to give not so much a diagram of a doctrine
as some pictures of a point of view. And I have
described at length my vision of the maniac for this
reason: that just as I am affected by the maniac,
so I am affected by most modern thinkers. That
unmistakable mood or note that I hear from Hanwell,
I hear also from half the chairs of science and seats
of learning to-day; and most of the mad doctors are
mad doctors in more senses than one. They all
have exactly that combination we have noted:
the combination of an expansive and exhaustive reason
with a contracted common sense. They are universal
only in the sense that they take one thin explanation
and carry it very far. But a pattern can stretch
for ever and still be a small pattern. They see
a chess-board white on black, and if the universe is
paved with it, it is still white on black. Like
the lunatic, they cannot alter their standpoint; they
cannot make a mental effort and suddenly see it black
on white.
Take first the more obvious case
of materialism. As an explanation of the world,
materialism has a sort of insane simplicity.
It has just the quality of the madman’s argument;
we have at once the sense of it covering everything
and the sense of it leaving everything out. Contemplate
some able and sincere materialist, as, for instance,
Mr. McCabe, and you will have exactly this unique sensation.
He understands everything, and everything does not
seem worth understanding. His cosmos may be
complete in every rivet and cog-wheel, but still his
cosmos is smaller than our world. Somehow his
scheme, like the lucid scheme of the madman, seems
unconscious of the alien energies and the large indifference
of the earth; it is not thinking of the real things
of the earth, of fighting peoples or proud mothers,
or first love or fear upon the sea. The earth
is so very large, and the cosmos is so very small.
The cosmos is about the smallest hole that a man can
hide his head in.
It must be understood that I
am not now discussing the relation of these creeds
to truth; but, for the present, solely their relation
to health. Later in the argument I hope to attack
the question of objective verity; here I speak only
of a phenomenon of psychology. I do not for the
present attempt to prove to Haeckel that materialism
is untrue, any more than I attempted to prove to the
man who thought he was Christ that he was labouring
under an error. I merely remark here on the
fact that both cases have the same kind of completeness
and the same kind of incompleteness. You can
explain a man’s detention at Hanwell by an indifferent
public by saying that it is the crucifixion of a god
of whom the world is not worthy. The explanation
does explain. Similarly you may explain the order
in the universe by saying that all things, even the
souls of men, are leaves inevitably unfolding on an
utterly unconscious tree- the blind destiny
of matter. The explanation does explain, though
not, of course, so completely as the madman’s.
But the point here is that the normal human mind not
only objects to both, but feels to both the same objection.
Its approximate statement is that if the man in Hanwell
is the real God, he is not much of a god. And,
similarly, if the cosmos of the materialist is the
real cosmos, it is not much of a cosmos. The
thing has shrunk. The deity is less divine than
many men; and (according to Haeckel) the whole of
life is something much more grey, narrow, and trivial
than many separate aspects of it. The parts seem
greater than the whole.
For we must remember that the
materialist philosophy (whether true or not) is certainly
much more limiting than any religion. In one
sense, of course, all intelligent ideas are narrow.
They cannot be broader than themselves. A Christian
is only restricted in the same sense that an atheist
is restricted. He cannot think Christianity false
and continue to be a Christian; and the atheist cannot
think atheism false and continue to be an atheist.
But as it happens, there is a very special sense
in which materialism has more restrictions than spiritualism.
Mr. McCabe thinks me a slave because I am not allowed
to believe in determinism. I think Mr. McCabe
a slave because he is not allowed to believe in fairies.
But if we examine the two vetoes we shall see that
his is really much more of a pure veto than mine.
The Christian is quite free to believe that there is
a considerable amount of settled order and inevitable
development in the universe. But the materialist
is not allowed to admit into his spotless machine
the slightest speck of spiritualism or miracle.
Poor Mr. McCabe is not allowed to retain even the
tiniest imp, though it might be hiding in a pimpernel.
The Christian admits that the universe is manifold
and even miscellaneous, just as a sane man knows that
he is complex. The sane man knows that he has
a touch of the beast, a touch of the devil, a touch
of the saint, a touch of the citizen. Nay, the
really sane man knows that he has a touch of the madman.
But the materialist’s world is quite simple and
solid, just as the madman is quite sure he is sane.
The materialist is sure that history has been simply
and solely a chain of causation, just as the interesting
person before mentioned is quite sure that he is simply
and solely a chicken. Materialists and madmen
never have doubts.
Spiritual doctrines do not actually
limit the mind as do materialistic denials.
Even if I believe in immortality I need not think
about it. But if I disbelieve in immortality
I must not think about it. In the first case
the road is open and I can go as far as I like; in
the second the road is shut. But the case is
even stronger, and the parallel with madness is yet
more strange. For it was our case against the
exhaustive and logical theory of the lunatic that,
right or wrong, it gradually destroyed his humanity.
Now it is the charge against the main deductions
of the materialist that, right or wrong, they gradually
destroy his humanity; I do not mean only kindness,
I mean hope, courage, poetry, initiative, all that
is human. For instance, when materialism leads
men to complete fatalism (as it generally does), it
is quite idle to pretend that it is in any sense a
liberating force. It is absurd to say that you
are especially advancing freedom when you only use
free thought to destroy free will. The determinists
come to bind, not to loose. They may well call
their law the “chain” of causation.
It is the worst chain that ever fettered a human
being. You may use the language of liberty,
if you like, about materialistic teaching, but it is
obvious that this is just as inapplicable to it as
a whole as the same language when applied to a man
locked up in a mad-house. You may say, if you
like, that the man is free to think himself a poached
egg. But it is surely a more massive and important
fact that if he is a poached egg he is not free to
eat, drink, sleep, walk, or smoke a cigarette.
Similarly you may say, if you like, that the bold determinist
speculator is free to disbelieve in the reality of
the will. But it is a much more massive and important
fact that he is not free to raise, to curse, to thank,
to justify, to urge, to punish, to resist temptations,
to incite mobs, to make New Year resolutions, to pardon
sinners, to rebuke tyrants, or even to say “thank
you” for the mustard.
In passing from this subject
I may note that there is a queer fallacy to the effect
that materialistic fatalism is in some way favourable
to mercy, to the abolition of cruel punishments or
punishments of any kind. This is startlingly
the reverse of the truth. It is quite tenable
that the doctrine of necessity makes no difference
at all; that it leaves the flogger flogging and the
kind friend exhorting as before. But obviously
if it stops either of them it stops the kind exhortation.
That the sins are inevitable does not prevent punishment;
if it prevents anything it prevents persuasion.
Determinism is quite as likely to lead to cruelty as
it is certain to lead to cowardice. Determinism
is not inconsistent with the cruel treatment of criminals.
What it is (perhaps) inconsistent with is the generous
treatment of criminals; with any appeal to their better
feelings or encouragement in their moral struggle.
The determinist does not believe in appealing to the
will, but he does believe in changing the environment.
He must not say to the sinner, “Go and sin
no more,” because the sinner cannot help it.
But he can put him in boiling oil; for boiling oil
is an environment. Considered as a figure, therefore,
the materialist has the fantastic outline of the figure
of the madman. Both take up a position at once
unanswerable and intolerable.
Of course it is not only of the
materialist that all this is true. The same would
apply to the other extreme of speculative logic.
There is a sceptic far more terrible than he who believes
that everything began in matter. It is possible
to meet the sceptic who believes that everything began
in himself. He doubts not the existence of angels
or devils, but the existence of men and cows.
For him his own friends are a mythology made up by
himself. He created his own father and his own
mother. This horrible fancy has in it something
decidedly attractive to the somewhat mystical egoism
of our day. That publisher who thought that men
would get on if they believed in themselves, those
seekers after the Superman who are always looking
for him in the looking-glass, those writers who talk
about impressing their personalities instead of creating
life for the world, all these people have really only
an inch between them and this awful emptiness.
Then when this kindly world all round the man has
been blackened out like a lie; when friends fade into
ghosts, and the foundations of the world fail; then
when the man, believing in nothing and in no man, is
alone in his own nightmare, then the great individualistic
motto shall be written over him in avenging irony.
The stars will be only dots in the blackness of his
own brain; his mother’s face will be only a
sketch from his own insane pencil on the walls of his
cell. But over his cell shall be written, with
dreadful truth, “He believes in himself.”
All that concerns us here, however,
is to note that this panegoistic extreme of thought
exhibits the same paradox as the other extreme of
materialism. It is equally complete in theory
and equally crippling in practice. For the sake
of simplicity, it is easier to state the notion by
saying that a man can believe that he is always in
a dream. Now, obviously there can be no positive
proof given to him that he is not in a dream, for the
simple reason that no proof can be offered that might
not be offered in a dream. But if the man began
to burn down London and say that his housekeeper would
soon call him to breakfast, we should take him and
put him with other logicians in a place which has
often been alluded to in the course of this chapter.
The man who cannot believe his senses, and the man
who cannot believe anything else, are both insane,
but their insanity is proved not by any error in their
argument, but by the manifest mistake of their whole
lives. They have both locked themselves up in
two boxes, painted inside with the sun and stars;
they are both unable to get out, the one into the
health and happiness of heaven, the other even into
the health and happiness of the earth. Their
position is quite reasonable; nay, in a sense it is
infinitely reasonable, just as a threepenny bit is
infinitely circular. But there is such a thing
as a mean infinity, a base and slavish eternity.
It is amusing to notice that many of the moderns,
whether sceptics or mystics, have taken as their sign
a certain eastern symbol, which is the very symbol
of this ultimate nullity. When they wish to represent
eternity, they represent it by a serpent with his
tail in his mouth. There is a startling sarcasm
in the image of that very unsatisfactory meal.
The eternity of the material fatalists, the eternity
of the eastern pessimists, the eternity of the supercilious
theosophists and higher scientists of to-day is, indeed,
very well presented by a serpent eating his tail,
a degraded animal who destroys even himself.
This chapter is purely practical
and is concerned with what actually is the chief mark
and element of insanity; we may say in summary that
it is reason used without root, reason in the void.
The man who begins to think without the proper first
principles goes mad; he begins to think at the wrong
end. And for the rest of these pages we have
to try and discover what is the right end. But
we may ask in conclusion, if this be what drives men
mad, what is it that keeps them sane? By the
end of this book I hope to give a definite, some will
think a far too definite, answer. But for the
moment it is possible in the same solely practical
manner to give a general answer touching what in actual
human history keeps men sane. Mysticism keeps
men sane. As long as you have mystery you have
health; when you destroy mystery you create morbidity.
The ordinary man has always been sane because the
ordinary man has always been a mystic. He has
permitted the twilight. He has always had one
foot in earth and the other in fairyland. He
has always left himself free to doubt his gods; but
(unlike the agnostic of to-day) free also to believe
in them. He has always cared more for truth than
for consistency. If he saw two truths that seemed
to contradict each other, he would take the two truths
and the contradiction along with them. His spiritual
sight is stereoscopic, like his physical sight:
he sees two different pictures at once and yet sees
all the better for that. Thus he has always
believed that there was such a thing as fate, but
such a thing as free will also. Thus he believed
that children were indeed the kingdom of heaven, but
nevertheless ought to be obedient to the kingdom of
earth. He admired youth because it was young
and age because it was not. It is exactly this
balance of apparent contradictions that has been the
whole buoyancy of the healthy man. The whole
secret of mysticism is this: that man can understand
everything by the help of what he does not understand.
The morbid logician seeks to make everything lucid,
and succeeds in making everything mysterious.
The mystic allows one thing to be mysterious, and
everything else becomes lucid. The determinist
makes the theory of causation quite clear, and then
finds that he cannot say “if you please”
to the housemaid. The Christian permits free
will to remain a sacred mystery; but because of this
his relations with the housemaid become of a sparkling
and crystal clearness. He puts the seed of dogma
in a central darkness; but it branches forth in all
directions with abounding natural health. As
we have taken the circle as the symbol of reason and
madness, we may very well take the cross as the symbol
at once of mystery and of health. Buddhism is
centripetal, but Christianity is centrifugal:
it breaks out. For the circle is perfect and
infinite in its nature; but it is fixed for ever in
its size; it can never be larger or smaller.
But the cross, though it has at its heart a collision
and a contradiction, can extend its four arms for ever
without altering its shape. Because it has a
paradox in its centre it can grow without changing.
The circle returns upon itself and is bound.
The cross opens its arms to the four winds; it is a
signpost for free travellers.
Symbols alone are of even a cloudy
value in speaking of this deep matter; and another
symbol from physical nature will express sufficiently
well the real place of mysticism before mankind.
The one created thing which we cannot look at is the
one thing in the light of which we look at everything.
Like the sun at noonday, mysticism explains everything
else by the blaze of its own victorious invisibility.
Detached intellectualism is (in the exact sense of
a popular phrase) all moonshine; for it is light without
heat, and it is secondary light, reflected from a dead
world. But the Greeks were right when they made
Apollo the god both of imagination and of sanity;
for he was both the patron of poetry and the patron
of healing. Of necessary dogmas and a special
creed I shall speak later. But that transcendentalism
by which all men live has primarily much the position
of the sun in the sky. We are conscious of it
as of a kind of splendid confusion; it is something
both shining and shapeless, at once a blaze and a
blur. But the circle of the moon is as clear
and unmistakable, as recurrent and inevitable, as
the circle of Euclid on a blackboard. For the
moon is utterly reasonable; and the moon is the mother
of lunatics and has given to them all her name.