When the business man rebukes
the idealism of his office-boy, it is commonly in
some such speech as this: “Ah, yes, when
one is young, one has these ideals in the abstract
and these castles in the air; but in middle age they
all break up like clouds, and one comes down to a
belief in practical politics, to using the machinery
one has and getting on with the world as it is.”
Thus, at least, venerable and philanthropic old men
now in their honoured graves used to talk to me when
I was a boy. But since then I have grown up and
have discovered that these philanthropic old men were
telling lies. What has really happened is exactly
the opposite of what they said would happen.
They said that I should lose my ideals and begin to
believe in the methods of practical politicians.
Now, I have not lost my ideals in the least; my faith
in fundamentals is exactly what it always was.
What I have lost is my old childlike faith in practical
politics. I am still as much concerned as ever
about the Battle of Armageddon; but I am not so much
concerned about the General Election. As a babe
I leapt up on my mother’s knee at the mere mention
of it. No; the vision is always solid and reliable.
The vision is always a fact. It is the reality
that is often a fraud. As much as I ever did,
more than I ever did, I believe in Liberalism.
But there was a rosy time of innocence when I believed
in Liberals.
I take this instance of one of
the enduring faiths because, having now to trace the
roots of my personal speculation, this may be counted,
I think, as the only positive bias. I was brought
up a Liberal, and have always believed in democracy,
in the elementary liberal doctrine of a self-governing
humanity. If any one finds the phrase vague or
threadbare, I can only pause for a moment to explain
that the principle of democracy, as I mean it, can
be stated in two propositions. The first is this:
that the things common to all men are more important
than the things peculiar to any men. Ordinary
things are more valuable than extraordinary things;
nay, they are more extraordinary. Man is something
more awful than men; something more strange.
The sense of the miracle of humanity itself should
be always more vivid to us than any marvels of power,
intellect, art, or civilization. The mere man
on two legs, as such, should be felt as something more
heartbreaking than any music and more startling than
any caricature. Death is more tragic even than
death by starvation. Having a nose is more comic
even than having a Norman nose.
This is the first principle of
democracy: that the essential things in men
are the things they hold in common, not the things
they hold separately. And the second principle
is merely this: that the political instinct or
desire is one of these things which they hold in common.
Falling in love is more poetical than dropping into
poetry. The democratic contention is that government
(helping to rule the tribe) is a thing like falling
in love, and not a thing like dropping into poetry.
It is not something analogous to playing the church
organ, painting on vellum, discovering the North Pole
(that insidious habit), looping the loop, being Astronomer
Royal, and so on. For these things we do not
wish a man to do at all unless he does them well.
It is, on the contrary, a thing analogous to writing
one’s own love-letters or blowing one’s
own nose. These things we want a man to do for
himself, even if he does them badly. I am not
here arguing the truth of any of these conceptions;
I know that some moderns are asking to have their
wives chosen by scientists, and they may soon be asking,
for all I know, to have their noses blown by nurses.
I merely say that mankind does recognize these universal
human functions, and that democracy classes government
among them. In short, the democratic faith is
this: that the most terribly important things
must be left to ordinary men themselves-the
mating of the sexes, the rearing of the young, the
laws of the state. This is democracy; and in
this I have always believed.
But there is one thing that I
have never from my youth up been able to understand.
I have never been able to understand where people
got the idea that democracy was in some way opposed
to tradition. It is obvious that tradition is
only democracy extended through time. It is trusting
to a consensus of common human voices rather than to
some isolated or arbitrary record. The man who
quotes some German historian against the tradition
of the Catholic Church, for instance, is strictly
appealing to aristocracy. He is appealing to
the superiority of one expert against the awful authority
of a mob. It is quite easy to see why a legend
is treated, and ought to be treated, more respectfully
than a book of history. The legend is generally
made by the majority of people in the village, who
are sane. The book is generally written by the
one man in the village who is mad. Those who
urge against tradition that men in the past were ignorant
may go and urge it at the Carlton Club, along with
the statement that voters in the slums are ignorant.
It will not do for us. If we attach great importance
to the opinion of ordinary men in great unanimity
when we are dealing with daily matters, there is no
reason why we should disregard it when we are dealing
with history or fable. Tradition may be defined
as an extension of the franchise. Tradition means
giving votes to the most obscure of all classes, our
ancestors. It is the democracy of the dead.
Tradition refuses to submit to the small and arrogant
oligarchy of those who merely happen to be walking
about. All democrats object to men being disqualified
by the accident of birth; tradition objects to their
being disqualified by the accident of death.
Democracy tells us not to neglect a good man’s
opinion, even if he is our groom; tradition asks us
not to neglect a good man’s opinion, even if
he is our father. I, at any rate, cannot separate
the two ideas of democracy and tradition; it seems
evident to me that they are the same idea. We
will have the dead at our councils. The ancient
Greeks voted by stones; these shall vote by tombstones.
It is all quite regular and official, for most tombstones,
like most ballot papers, are marked with a cross.
I have first to say, therefore,
that if I have had a bias, it was always a bias in
favour of democracy, and therefore of tradition.
Before we come to any theoretic or logical beginnings
I am content to allow for that personal equation;
I have always been more inclined to believe the ruck
of hard-working people than to believe that special
and troublesome literary class to which I belong.
I prefer even the fancies and prejudices of the people
who see life from the inside to the clearest demonstrations
of the people who see life from the outside.
I would always trust the old wives’ fables
against the old maids’ facts. As long as
wit is mother wit it can be as wild as it pleases.
Now, I have to put together a
general position, and I pretend to no training in
such things. I propose to do it, therefore,
by writing down one after another the three or four
fundamental ideas which I have found for myself, pretty
much in the way that I found them. Then I shall
roughly synthesise them, summing up my personal philosophy
or natural religion; then I shall describe my startling
discovery that the whole thing had been discovered
before. It had been discovered by Christianity.
But of these profound persuasions which I have to recount
in order, the earliest was concerned with this element
of popular tradition. And without the foregoing
explanation touching tradition and democracy I could
hardly make my mental experience clear. As it
is, I do not know whether I can make it clear, but
I now propose to try.
My first and last philosophy,
that which I believe in with unbroken certainty, I
learnt in the nursery. I generally learnt it
from a nurse; that is, from the solemn and star-appointed
priestess at once of democracy and tradition.
The things I believed most then, the things I believe
most now, are the things called fairy tales.
They seem to me to be the entirely reasonable things.
They are not fantasies: compared with them
other things are fantastic. Compared with them
religion and rationalism are both abnormal, though
religion is abnormally right and rationalism abnormally
wrong. Fairyland is nothing but the sunny country
of common sense. It is not earth that judges
heaven, but heaven that judges earth; so for me at
least it was not earth that criticised elfland, but
elfland that criticised the earth. I knew the
magic beanstalk before I had tasted beans; I was sure
of the Man in the Moon before I was certain of the
moon. This was at one with all popular tradition.
Modern minor poets are naturalists, and talk about
the bush or the brook; but the singers of the old
epics and fables were supernaturalists, and talked
about the gods of brook and bush. That is what
the moderns mean when they say that the ancients did
not “appreciate Nature,” because they
said that Nature was divine. Old nurses do not
tell children about the grass, but about the fairies
that dance on the grass; and the old Greeks could
not see the trees for the dryads.
But I deal here with what ethic
and philosophy come from being fed on fairy tales.
If I were describing them in detail I could note
many noble and healthy principles that arise from them.
There is the chivalrous lesson of “Jack the Giant
Killer”; that giants should be killed because
they are gigantic. It is a manly mutiny against
pride as such. For the rebel is older than all
the kingdoms, and the Jacobin has more tradition than
the Jacobite. There is the lesson of “Cinderella,”
which is the same as that of the Magnificat-
EXALTAVIT HUMILES. There is the great lesson
of “Beauty and the Beast”; that a thing
must be loved before it is loveable. There
is the terrible allegory of the “Sleeping Beauty,”
which tells how the human creature was blessed with
all birthday gifts, yet cursed with death; and how
death also may perhaps be softened to a sleep.
But I am not concerned with any of the separate statutes
of elfland, but with the whole spirit of its law,
which I learnt before I could speak, and shall retain
when I cannot write. I am concerned with a certain
way of looking at life, which was created in me by
the fairy tales, but has since been meekly ratified
by the mere facts.
It might be stated this way.
There are certain sequences or developments (cases
of one thing following another), which are, in the
true sense of the word, reasonable. They are,
in the true sense of the word, necessary. Such
are mathematical and merely logical sequences.
We in fairyland (who are the most reasonable of all
creatures) admit that reason and that necessity.
For instance, if the Ugly Sisters are older than Cinderella,
it is (in an iron and awful sense) necessary that
Cinderella is younger than the Ugly Sisters.
There is no getting out of it. Haeckel may talk
as much fatalism about that fact as he pleases:
it really must be. If Jack is the son of a miller,
a miller is the father of Jack. Cold reason
decrees it from her awful throne: and we in fairyland
submit. If the three brothers all ride horses,
there are six animals and eighteen legs involved:
that is true rationalism, and fairyland is full of
it. But as I put my head over the hedge of the
elves and began to take notice of the natural world,
I observed an extraordinary thing. I observed
that learned men in spectacles were talking of the
actual things that happened- dawn and death
and so on-as if they were rational
and inevitable. They talked as if the fact that
trees bear fruit were just as necessary as the
fact that two and one trees make three. But it
is not. There is an enormous difference by the
test of fairyland; which is the test of the imagination.
You cannot imagine two and one not making three.
But you can easily imagine trees not growing fruit;
you can imagine them growing golden candlesticks or
tigers hanging on by the tail. These men in
spectacles spoke much of a man named Newton, who was
hit by an apple, and who discovered a law. But
they could not be got to see the distinction between
a true law, a law of reason, and the mere fact of
apples falling. If the apple hit Newton’s
nose, Newton’s nose hit the apple. That
is a true necessity: because we cannot conceive
the one occurring without the other. But we can
quite well conceive the apple not falling on his nose;
we can fancy it flying ardently through the air to
hit some other nose, of which it had a more definite
dislike. We have always in our fairy tales kept
this sharp distinction between the science of mental
relations, in which there really are laws, and the
science of physical facts, in which there are no laws,
but only weird repetitions. We believe in bodily
miracles, but not in mental impossibilities.
We believe that a Bean-stalk climbed up to Heaven;
but that does not at all confuse our convictions on
the philosophical question of how many beans make
five.
Here is the peculiar perfection
of tone and truth in the nursery tales. The
man of science says, “Cut the stalk, and the
apple will fall”; but he says it calmly, as
if the one idea really led up to the other.
The witch in the fairy tale says, “Blow the horn,
and the ogre’s castle will fall”;
but she does not say it as if it were something in
which the effect obviously arose out of the cause.
Doubtless she has given the advice to many champions,
and has seen many castles fall, but she does not lose
either her wonder or her reason. She does not
muddle her head until it imagines a necessary mental
connection between a horn and a falling tower.
But the scientific men do muddle their heads, until
they imagine a necessary mental connection between
an apple leaving the tree and an apple reaching the
ground. They do really talk as if they had found
not only a set of marvellous facts, but a truth connecting
those facts. They do talk as if the connection
of two strange things physically connected them philosophically.
They feel that because one incomprehensible thing
constantly follows another incomprehensible thing
the two together somehow make up a comprehensible thing.
Two black riddles make a white answer.
In fairyland we avoid the word
“law”; but in the land of science they
are singularly fond of it. Thus they will call
some interesting conjecture about how forgotten folks
pronounced the alphabet, Grimm’s Law.
But Grimm’s Law is far less intellectual than
Grimm’s Fairy Tales. The tales are, at
any rate, certainly tales; while the law is not a
law. A law implies that we know the nature of
the generalisation and enactment; not merely that we
have noticed some of the effects. If there is
a law that pick-pockets shall go to prison, it implies
that there is an imaginable mental connection between
the idea of prison and the idea of picking pockets.
And we know what the idea is. We can say why
we take liberty from a man who takes liberties.
But we cannot say why an egg can turn into a chicken
any more than we can say why a bear could turn into
a fairy prince. As ideas, the egg and the
chicken are further off from each other than the bear
and the prince; for no egg in itself suggests a chicken,
whereas some princes do suggest bears. Granted,
then, that certain transformations do happen, it is
essential that we should regard them in the philosophic
manner of fairy tales, not in the unphilosophic manner
of science and the “Laws of Nature.”
When we are asked why eggs turn to birds or fruits
fall in autumn, we must answer exactly as the fairy
godmother would answer if Cinderella asked her why
mice turned to horses or her clothes fell from her
at twelve o’clock. We must answer that it
is magic. It is not a “law,”
for we do not understand its general formula.
It is not a necessity, for though we can count on it
happening practically, we have no right to say that
it must always happen. It is no argument for
unalterable law (as Huxley fancied) that we count
on the ordinary course of things. We do not count
on it; we bet on it. We risk the remote possibility
of a miracle as we do that of a poisoned pancake or
a world-destroying comet. We leave it out of
account, not because it is a miracle, and therefore
an impossibility, but because it is a miracle, and
therefore an exception. All the terms used in
the science books, “law,” “necessity,”
“order,” “tendency,” and so
on, are really unintellectual, because they assume
an inner synthesis, which we do not possess.
The only words that ever satisfied me as describing
Nature are the terms used in the fairy books, “charm,”
“spell,” “enchantment.”
They express the arbitrariness of the fact and its
mystery. A tree grows fruit because it is a magic
tree. Water runs downhill because it is bewitched.
The sun shines because it is bewitched.
I deny altogether that this is
fantastic or even mystical. We may have some
mysticism later on; but this fairy-tale language about
things is simply rational and agnostic. It is
the only way I can express in words my clear and definite
perception that one thing is quite distinct from another;
that there is no logical connection between flying
and laying eggs. It is the man who talks about
“a law” that he has never seen who is the
mystic. Nay, the ordinary scientific man is strictly
a sentimentalist. He is a sentimentalist in this
essential sense, that he is soaked and swept away
by mere associations. He has so often seen birds
fly and lay eggs that he feels as if there must be
some dreamy, tender connection between the two ideas,
whereas there is none. A forlorn lover might
be unable to dissociate the moon from lost love; so
the materialist is unable to dissociate the moon from
the tide. In both cases there is no connection,
except that one has seen them together. A sentimentalist
might shed tears at the smell of apple-blossom, because,
by a dark association of his own, it reminded him
of his boyhood. So the materialist professor
(though he conceals his tears) is yet a sentimentalist,
because, by a dark association of his own, apple-blossoms
remind him of apples. But the cool rationalist
from fairyland does not see why, in the abstract,
the apple tree should not grow crimson tulips; it sometimes
does in his country.
This elementary wonder, however,
is not a mere fancy derived from the fairy tales;
on the contrary, all the fire of the fairy tales is
derived from this. Just as we all like love tales
because there is an instinct of sex, we all like astonishing
tales because they touch the nerve of the ancient
instinct of astonishment. This is proved by the
fact that when we are very young children we do not
need fairy tales: we only need tales. Mere
life is interesting enough. A child of seven
is excited by being told that Tommy opened a door
and saw a dragon. But a child of three is excited
by being told that Tommy opened a door. Boys
like romantic tales; but babies like realistic tales-because
they find them romantic. In fact, a baby is about
the only person, I should think, to whom a modern
realistic novel could be read without boring him.
This proves that even nursery tales only echo an almost
pre-natal leap of interest and amazement. These
tales say that apples were golden only to refresh
the forgotten moment when we found that they were
green. They make rivers run with wine only to
make us remember, for one wild moment, that they run
with water. I have said that this is wholly
reasonable and even agnostic. And, indeed, on
this point I am all for the higher agnosticism; its
better name is Ignorance. We have all read in
scientific books, and, indeed, in all romances, the
story of the man who has forgotten his name.
This man walks about the streets and can see and appreciate
everything; only he cannot remember who he is.
Well, every man is that man in the story. Every
man has forgotten who he is. One may understand
the cosmos, but never the ego; the self is more distant
than any star. Thou shalt love the Lord thy God;
but thou shalt not know thyself. We are all under
the same mental calamity; we have all forgotten our
names. We have all forgotten what we really are.
All that we call common sense and rationality and
practicality and positivism only means that for certain
dead levels of our life we forget that we have forgotten.
All that we call spirit and art and ecstasy only
means that for one awful instant we remember that
we forget.
But though (like the man without
memory in the novel) we walk the streets with a sort
of half-witted admiration, still it is admiration.
It is admiration in English and not only admiration
in Latin. The wonder has a positive element of
praise. This is the next milestone to be definitely
marked on our road through fairyland. I shall
speak in the next chapter about optimists and pessimists
in their intellectual aspect, so far as they have one.
Here I am only trying to describe the enormous emotions
which cannot be described. And the strongest
emotion was that life was as precious as it was puzzling.
It was an ecstasy because it was an adventure; it
was an adventure because it was an opportunity.
The goodness of the fairy tale was not affected by
the fact that there might be more dragons than princesses;
it was good to be in a fairy tale. The test of
all happiness is gratitude; and I felt grateful, though
I hardly knew to whom. Children are grateful
when Santa Claus puts in their stockings gifts of
toys or sweets. Could I not be grateful to Santa
Claus when he put in my stockings the gift of two
miraculous legs? We thank people for birthday
presents of cigars and slippers. Can I thank
no one for the birthday present of birth?
There were, then, these two first
feelings, indefensible and indisputable. The
world was a shock, but it was not merely shocking;
existence was a surprise, but it was a pleasant surprise.
In fact, all my first views were exactly uttered
in a riddle that stuck in my brain from boyhood.
The question was, “What did the first frog
say?” And the answer was, “Lord, how you
made me jump!” That says succinctly all that
I am saying. God made the frog jump; but the
frog prefers jumping. But when these things are
settled there enters the second great principle of
the fairy philosophy.
Any one can see it who will simply
read “Grimm’s Fairy Tales” or the
fine collections of Mr. Andrew Lang. For the
pleasure of pedantry I will call it the Doctrine of
Conditional Joy. Touchstone talked of much virtue
in an “if”; according to elfin ethics
all virtue is in an “if.” The note
of the fairy utterance always is, “You may live
in a palace of gold and sapphire, if you do not say
the word `cow’”; or “You may live
happily with the King’s daughter, if you do
not show her an onion.” The vision always
hangs upon a veto. All the dizzy and colossal
things conceded depend upon one small thing withheld.
All the wild and whirling things that are let loose
depend upon one thing that is forbidden. Mr.
W.B.Yeats, in his exquisite and piercing elfin poetry,
describes the elves as lawless; they plunge in innocent
anarchy on the unbridled horses of the air-
“Ride on the crest of the
dishevelled tide, And dance upon the mountains
like a flame.”
It is a dreadful thing to say that
Mr. W.B.Yeats does not understand fairyland.
But I do say it. He is an ironical Irishman,
full of intellectual reactions. He is not stupid
enough to understand fairyland. Fairies prefer
people of the yokel type like myself; people who gape
and grin and do as they are told. Mr. Yeats reads
into elfland all the righteous insurrection of his
own race. But the lawlessness of Ireland is a
Christian lawlessness, founded on reason and justice.
The Fenian is rebelling against something he understands
only too well; but the true citizen of fairyland is
obeying something that he does not understand at all.
In the fairy tale an incomprehensible happiness rests
upon an incomprehensible condition. A box is
opened, and all evils fly out. A word is forgotten,
and cities perish. A lamp is lit, and love flies
away. A flower is plucked, and human lives are
forfeited. An apple is eaten, and the hope of
God is gone.
This is the tone of fairy tales,
and it is certainly not lawlessness or even liberty,
though men under a mean modern tyranny may think it
liberty by comparison. People out of Portland
Gaol might think Fleet Street free; but closer study
will prove that both fairies and journalists are the
slaves of duty. Fairy godmothers seem at least
as strict as other godmothers. Cinderella received
a coach out of Wonderland and a coachman out of nowhere,
but she received a command-which might have
come out of Brixton-that she should be
back by twelve. Also, she had a glass slipper;
and it cannot be a coincidence that glass is so common
a substance in folk-lore. This princess lives
in a glass castle, that princess on a glass hill;
this one sees all things in a mirror; they may all
live in glass houses if they will not throw stones.
For this thin glitter of glass everywhere is the expression
of the fact that the happiness is bright but brittle,
like the substance most easily smashed by a housemaid
or a cat. And this fairy-tale sentiment also
sank into me and became my sentiment towards the whole
world. I felt and feel that life itself is as
bright as the diamond, but as brittle as the window-pane;
and when the heavens were compared to the terrible
crystal I can remember a shudder. I was afraid
that God would drop the cosmos with a crash.
Remember, however, that to be
breakable is not the same as to be perishable.
Strike a glass, and it will not endure an instant;
simply do not strike it, and it will endure a thousand
years. Such, it seemed, was the joy of man, either
in elfland or on earth; the happiness depended on
not doing something which you could
at any moment do and which, very often, it was not
obvious why you should not do. Now, the point
here is that to me this did not seem unjust.
If the miller’s third son said to the fairy,
“Explain why I must not stand on my head in
the fairy palace,” the other might fairly reply,
“Well, if it comes to that, explain the fairy
palace.” If Cinderella says, “How
is it that I must leave the ball at twelve?”
her godmother might answer, “How is it that you
are going there till twelve?” If I leave a
man in my will ten talking elephants and a hundred
winged horses, he cannot complain if the conditions
partake of the slight eccentricity of the gift.
He must not look a winged horse in the mouth.
And it seemed to me that existence was itself so
very eccentric a legacy that I could not complain
of not understanding the limitations of the vision
when I did not understand the vision they limited.
The frame was no stranger than the picture.
The veto might well be as wild as the vision; it
might be as startling as the sun, as elusive as the
waters, as fantastic and terrible as the towering
trees.
For this reason (we may call
it the fairy godmother philosophy) I never could join
the young men of my time in feeling what they called
the general sentiment of revolt. I should
have resisted, let us hope, any rules that were evil,
and with these and their definition I shall deal in
another chapter. But I did not feel disposed
to resist any rule merely because it was mysterious.
Estates are sometimes held by foolish forms, the breaking
of a stick or the payment of a peppercorn: I
was willing to hold the huge estate of earth and heaven
by any such feudal fantasy. It could not well
be wilder than the fact that I was allowed to hold
it at all. At this stage I give only one ethical
instance to show my meaning. I could never mix
in the common murmur of that rising generation against
monogamy, because no restriction on sex seemed so odd
and unexpected as sex itself. To be allowed,
like Endymion, to make love to the moon and then to
complain that Jupiter kept his own moons in a harem
seemed to me (bred on fairy tales like Endymion’s)
a vulgar anti-climax. Keeping to one woman is
a small price for so much as seeing one woman.
To complain that I could only be married once was
like complaining that I had only been born once.
It was incommensurate with the terrible excitement
of which one was talking. It showed, not an
exaggerated sensibility to sex, but a curious insensibility
to it. A man is a fool who complains that he
cannot enter Eden by five gates at once. Polygamy
is a lack of the realization of sex; it is like a
man plucking five pears in mere absence of mind.
The aesthetes touched the last insane limits of language
in their eulogy on lovely things. The thistledown
made them weep; a burnished beetle brought them to
their knees. Yet their emotion never impressed
me for an instant, for this reason, that it never
occurred to them to pay for their pleasure in any
sort of symbolic sacrifice. Men (I felt) might
fast forty days for the sake of hearing a blackbird
sing. Men might go through fire to find a cowslip.
Yet these lovers of beauty could not even keep sober
for the blackbird. They would not go through
common Christian marriage by way of recompense to
the cowslip. Surely one might pay for extraordinary
joy in ordinary morals. Oscar Wilde said that
sunsets were not valued because we could not pay for
sunsets. But Oscar Wilde was wrong; we can pay
for sunsets. We can pay for them by not being
Oscar Wilde.
Well, I left the fairy tales
lying on the floor of the nursery, and I have not
found any books so sensible since. I left the
nurse guardian of tradition and democracy, and I have
not found any modern type so sanely radical or so
sanely conservative. But the matter for important
comment was here: that when I first went out
into the mental atmosphere of the modern world, I
found that the modern world was positively opposed
on two points to my nurse and to the nursery tales.
It has taken me a long time to find out that the
modern world is wrong and my nurse was right.
The really curious thing was this: that modern
thought contradicted this basic creed of my boyhood
on its two most essential doctrines. I have explained
that the fairy tales founded in me two convictions;
first, that this world is a wild and startling place,
which might have been quite different, but which is
quite delightful; second, that before this wildness
and delight one may well be modest and submit to the
queerest limitations of so queer a kindness.
But I found the whole modern world running like a
high tide against both my tendernesses; and the shock
of that collision created two sudden and spontaneous
sentiments, which I have had ever since and which,
crude as they were, have since hardened into convictions.
First, I found the whole modern
world talking scientific fatalism; saying that everything
is as it must always have been, being unfolded without
fault from the beginning. The leaf on the tree
is green because it could never have been anything
else. Now, the fairy-tale philosopher is glad
that the leaf is green precisely because it might
have been scarlet. He feels as if it had turned
green an instant before he looked at it. He
is pleased that snow is white on the strictly reasonable
ground that it might have been black. Every colour
has in it a bold quality as of choice; the red of garden
roses is not only decisive but dramatic, like suddenly
spilt blood. He feels that something has been
done. But the great determinists of the
nineteenth century were strongly against this native
feeling that something had happened an instant before.
In fact, according to them, nothing ever really had
happened since the beginning of the world. Nothing
ever had happened since existence had happened; and
even about the date of that they were not very sure.
The modern world as I found it
was solid for modern Calvinism, for the necessity
of things being as they are. But when I came
to ask them I found they had really no proof of this
unavoidable repetition in things except the fact that
the things were repeated. Now, the mere repetition
made the things to me rather more weird than more
rational. It was as if, having seen a curiously
shaped nose in the street and dismissed it as an accident,
I had then seen six other noses of the same astonishing
shape. I should have fancied for a moment that
it must be some local secret society. So one
elephant having a trunk was odd; but all elephants
having trunks looked like a plot. I speak here
only of an emotion, and of an emotion at once stubborn
and subtle. But the repetition in Nature seemed
sometimes to be an excited repetition, like that of
an angry schoolmaster saying the same thing over and
over again. The grass seemed signalling to me
with all its fingers at once; the crowded stars seemed
bent upon being understood. The sun would make
me see him if he rose a thousand times. The recurrences
of the universe rose to the maddening rhythm of an
incantation, and I began to see an idea.
All the towering materialism
which dominates the modern mind rests ultimately upon
one assumption; a false assumption. It is supposed
that if a thing goes on repeating itself it is probably
dead; a piece of clockwork. People feel that
if the universe was personal it would vary; if the
sun were alive it would dance. This is a fallacy
even in relation to known fact. For the variation
in human affairs is generally brought into them, not
by life, but by death; by the dying down or breaking
off of their strength or desire. A man varies
his movements because of some slight element of failure
or fatigue. He gets into an omnibus because he
is tired of walking; or he walks because he is tired
of sitting still. But if his life and joy were
so gigantic that he never tired of going to Islington,
he might go to Islington as regularly as the Thames
goes to Sheerness. The very speed and ecstasy
of his life would have the stillness of death.
The sun rises every morning. I do not rise every
morning; but the variation is due not to my activity,
but to my inaction. Now, to put the matter in
a popular phrase, it might be true that the sun rises
regularly because he never gets tired of rising.
His routine might be due, not to a lifelessness, but
to a rush of life. The thing I mean can be seen,
for instance, in children, when they find some game
or joke that they specially enjoy. A child kicks
his legs rhythmically through excess, not absence,
of life. Because children have abounding vitality,
because they are in spirit fierce and free, therefore
they want things repeated and unchanged. They
always say, “Do it again”; and the grown-up
person does it again until he is nearly dead.
For grown-up people are not strong enough to exult
in monotony. But perhaps God is strong enough
to exult in monotony. It is possible that God
says every morning, “Do it again” to the
sun; and every evening, “Do it again” to
the moon. It may not be automatic necessity that
makes all daisies alike; it may be that God makes
every daisy separately, but has never got tired of
making them. It may be that He has the eternal
appetite of infancy; for we have sinned and grown
old, and our Father is younger than we. The repetition
in Nature may not be a mere recurrence; it may be
a theatrical encore. Heaven may encore
the bird who laid an egg. If the human being
conceives and brings forth a human child instead of
bringing forth a fish, or a bat, or a griffin, the
reason may not be that we are fixed in an animal fate
without life or purpose. It may be that our little
tragedy has touched the gods, that they admire it
from their starry galleries, and that at the end of
every human drama man is called again and again before
the curtain. Repetition may go on for millions
of years, by mere choice, and at any instant it may
stop. Man may stand on the earth generation
after generation, and yet each birth be his positively
last appearance.
This was my first conviction;
made by the shock of my childish emotions meeting
the modern creed in mid-career. I had always vaguely
felt facts to be miracles in the sense that they are
wonderful: now I began to think them miracles
in the stricter sense that they were wilful.
I mean that they were, or might be, repeated exercises
of some will. In short, I had always believed
that the world involved magic: now I thought
that perhaps it involved a magician. And this
pointed a profound emotion always present and sub-conscious;
that this world of ours has some purpose; and if there
is a purpose, there is a person. I had always
felt life first as a story: and if there is a
story there is a story-teller.
But modern thought also hit my
second human tradition. It went against the fairy
feeling about strict limits and conditions. The
one thing it loved to talk about was expansion and
largeness. Herbert Spencer would have been greatly
annoyed if any one had called him an imperialist,
and therefore it is highly regrettable that nobody
did. But he was an imperialist of the lowest
type. He popularized this contemptible notion
that the size of the solar system ought to over-awe
the spiritual dogma of man. Why should a man
surrender his dignity to the solar system any more
than to a whale? If mere size proves that man
is not the image of God, then a whale may be the image
of God; a somewhat formless image; what one might
call an impressionist portrait. It is quite futile
to argue that man is small compared to the cosmos;
for man was always small compared to the nearest tree.
But Herbert Spencer, in his headlong imperialism,
would insist that we had in some way been conquered
and annexed by the astronomical universe. He
spoke about men and their ideals exactly as the most
insolent Unionist talks about the Irish and their
ideals. He turned mankind into a small nationality.
And his evil influence can be seen even in the most
spirited and honourable of later scientific authors;
notably in the early romances of Mr. H.G.Wells.
Many moralists have in an exaggerated way represented
the earth as wicked. But Mr. Wells and his school
made the heavens wicked. We should lift up our
eyes to the stars from whence would come our ruin.
But the expansion of which I
speak was much more evil than all this. I have
remarked that the materialist, like the madman, is
in prison; in the prison of one thought. These
people seemed to think it singularly inspiring to
keep on saying that the prison was very large.
The size of this scientific universe gave one no novelty,
no relief. The cosmos went on for ever, but not
in its wildest constellation could there be anything
really interesting; anything, for instance, such as
forgiveness or free will. The grandeur or infinity
of the secret of its cosmos added nothing to it.
It was like telling a prisoner in Reading gaol that
he would be glad to hear that the gaol now covered
half the county. The warder would have nothing
to show the man except more and more long corridors
of stone lit by ghastly lights and empty of all that
is human. So these expanders of the universe
had nothing to show us except more and more infinite
corridors of space lit by ghastly suns and empty of
all that is divine.
In fairyland there had been a
real law; a law that could be broken, for the definition
of a law is something that can be broken. But
the machinery of this cosmic prison was something that
could not be broken; for we ourselves were only a
part of its machinery. We were either unable
to do things or we were destined to do them.
The idea of the mystical condition quite disappeared;
one can neither have the firmness of keeping laws
nor the fun of breaking them. The largeness of
this universe had nothing of that freshness and airy
outbreak which we have praised in the universe of the
poet. This modern universe is literally an empire;
that is, it was vast, but it is not free. One
went into larger and larger windowless rooms, rooms
big with Babylonian perspective; but one never found
the smallest window or a whisper of outer air.
Their infernal parallels seemed
to expand with distance; but for me all good things
come to a point, swords for instance. So finding
the boast of the big cosmos so unsatisfactory to my
emotions I began to argue about it a little; and I
soon found that the whole attitude was even shallower
than could have been expected. According to these
people the cosmos was one thing since it had one unbroken
rule. Only (they would say) while it is one thing,
it is also the only thing there is. Why, then,
should one worry particularly to call it large?
There is nothing to compare it with. It would
be just as sensible to call it small. A man may
say, “I like this vast cosmos, with its throng
of stars and its crowd of varied creatures.”
But if it comes to that why should not a man say,
“I like this cosy little cosmos, with its decent
number of stars and as neat a provision of live stock
as I wish to see”? One is as good as the
other; they are both mere sentiments. It is mere
sentiment to rejoice that the sun is larger than the
earth; it is quite as sane a sentiment to rejoice
that the sun is no larger than it is. A man
chooses to have an emotion about the largeness of
the world; why should he not choose to have an emotion
about its smallness?
It happened that I had that emotion.
When one is fond of anything one addresses it by
diminutives, even if it is an elephant or a life-guardsman.
The reason is, that anything, however huge, that can
be conceived of as complete, can be conceived of as
small. If military moustaches did not suggest
a sword or tusks a tail, then the object would be
vast because it would be immeasurable. But the
moment you can imagine a guardsman you can imagine
a small guardsman. The moment you really see
an elephant you can call it “Tiny.”
If you can make a statue of a thing you can make a
statuette of it. These people professed that
the universe was one coherent thing; but they were
not fond of the universe. But I was frightfully
fond of the universe and wanted to address it by a
diminutive. I often did so; and it never seemed
to mind. Actually and in truth I did feel that
these dim dogmas of vitality were better expressed
by calling the world small than by calling it large.
For about infinity there was a sort of carelessness
which was the reverse of the fierce and pious care
which I felt touching the pricelessness and the peril
of life. They showed only a dreary waste; but
I felt a sort of sacred thrift. For economy is
far more romantic than extravagance. To them
stars were an unending income of halfpence; but I
felt about the golden sun and the silver moon as a
schoolboy feels if he has one sovereign and one shilling.
These subconscious convictions
are best hit off by the colour and tone of certain
tales. Thus I have said that stories of magic
alone can express my sense that life is not only a
pleasure but a kind of eccentric privilege.
I may express this other feeling of cosmic cosiness
by allusion to another book always read in boyhood,
“Robinson Crusoe,” which I read about this
time, and which owes its eternal vivacity to the fact
that it celebrates the poetry of limits, nay, even
the wild romance of prudence. Crusoe is a man
on a small rock with a few comforts just snatched from
the sea: the best thing in the book is simply
the list of things saved from the wreck. The
greatest of poems is an inventory. Every kitchen
tool becomes ideal because Crusoe might have dropped
it in the sea. It is a good exercise, in empty
or ugly hours of the day, to look at anything, the
coal-scuttle or the book-case, and think how happy
one could be to have brought it out of the sinking
ship on to the solitary island. But it is a
better exercise still to remember how all things have
had this hair-breadth escape: everything has
been saved from a wreck. Every man has had one
horrible adventure: as a hidden untimely birth
he had not been, as infants that never see the light.
Men spoke much in my boyhood of restricted or ruined
men of genius: and it was common to say that
many a man was a Great Might-Have-Been. To me
it is a more solid and startling fact that any man
in the street is a Great Might-Not-Have-Been.
But I really felt (the fancy
may seem foolish) as if all the order and number of
things were the romantic remnant of Crusoe’s
ship. That there are two sexes and one sun, was
like the fact that there were two guns and one axe.
It was poignantly urgent that none should be lost;
but somehow, it was rather fun that none could be added.
The trees and the planets seemed like things saved
from the wreck: and when I saw the Matterhorn
I was glad that it had not been overlooked in the
confusion. I felt economical about the stars
as if they were sapphires (they are called so in Milton’s
Eden): I hoarded the hills. For the universe
is a single jewel, and while it is a natural cant
to talk of a jewel as peerless and priceless, of this
jewel it is literally true. This cosmos is indeed
without peer and without price: for there cannot
be another one.
Thus ends, in unavoidable inadequacy,
the attempt to utter the unutterable things.
These are my ultimate attitudes towards life; the
soils for the seeds of doctrine. These in some
dark way I thought before I could write, and felt
before I could think: that we may proceed more
easily afterwards, I will roughly recapitulate them
now. I felt in my bones; first, that this world
does not explain itself. It may be a miracle
with a supernatural explanation; it may be a conjuring
trick, with a natural explanation. But the explanation
of the conjuring trick, if it is to satisfy me, will
have to be better than the natural explanations I have
heard. The thing is magic, true or false.
Second, I came to feel as if magic must have a meaning,
and meaning must have some one to mean it. There
was something personal in the world, as in a work of
art; whatever it meant it meant violently. Third,
I thought this purpose beautiful in its old design,
in spite of its defects, such as dragons. Fourth,
that the proper form of thanks to it is some form
of humility and restraint: we should thank God
for beer and Burgundy by not drinking too much of them.
We owed, also, an obedience to whatever made us.
And last, and strangest, there had come into my mind
a vague and vast impression that in some way all good
was a remnant to be stored and held sacred out of some
primordial ruin. Man had saved his good as Crusoe
saved his goods: he had saved them from a wreck.
All this I felt and the age gave me no encouragement
to feel it. And all this time I had not even
thought of Christian theology.