The history of the French Revolution
in England begins with a sermon and ends with a poem.
Between that famous discourse by Dr. Richard Price
on the love of our country, delivered in the first
excitement that followed the fall of the Bastille,
and the publication of Shelley’s Hellas
there stretched a period of thirty-two years.
It covered the dawn, the clouding and the unearthly
sunset of a hope. It begins with the grave but
enthusiastic prose of a divine justly respected by
earnest men, who with a limited horizon fulfilled
their daily duties in the city. It ends in the
rapt vision, the magical music of a singer, who seemed
as he sang to soar beyond the range of human ears.
The hope passes from the confident expectation of
instant change, through the sobrieties of disillusionment
and the recantations of despair, to the iridescent
dreams of a future which has taken wing and made its
home in a fairy world.
In 1789 when Dr. Price preached to
his ardent congregation of Nonconformist Radicals
in the meeting-house at the Old Jewry, the prospect
was definite and the place of the millennium was merely
the England over which George III. ruled. The
hope was a robust but pedestrian “mental traveller,”
and its limbs wore the precise garments of political
formulae. It looked for honest Parliaments and
manhood suffrage, for the triumph of democracy and
the abolition of war. Its scene as Wordsworth
put it, was
Not
in Utopia, subterraneous fields,
Or some secreted island, Heaven knows
where,
But in the very world which is the world
Of all of us, the place where in the end
We find our happiness, or not at all.
The impetus of its own aspiration
carried it swiftly beyond the prosaic demand for Parliamentary
Reform. It evolved its programme for the reconstruction
of all human institutions, and projected the amendment
of human nature itself. America had made an end
of kings and France was in the full tide of revolution.
Nothing was too mighty for this new-begotten hope,
and the path to human perfectibility stretched as
plain as the narrow road to Bunyan’s Heavenly
City.
There followed the phase when persecution
from alarmed defenders of things as they are, disgust
at the failures of the revolution in France, and contempt
for the futilities of the revolution at home, drove
the new movement into as many refuges as its votaries
had temperaments. For some there was cynicism,
for others recantation. “The French Revolution”
as Hazlitt put it, “was the only match that
ever took place between philosophy and experience;
and waking from the trance of theory we hear the words
Truth, Reason, Virtue, Liberty, with the same indifference
or contempt that a cynic who has married a jilt or
a termagant listens to the rhapsodies of lovers.”
Godwin found his own alluring by-way, and turning
away at once from political repression and political
agitation, became the pioneer of philosophic anarchism.
To Shelley at the end of this marvellous thirty years
of ardour, speculation, and despair, the hope became
winged. She had her place no longer in “the
very world which is the world of all of us.”
She had moved to
Kingless continents, sinless
as Eden
Around mountains and islands inviolably
Prankt on the sapphire sea.
It requires no inordinate effort for
us who live in an equable political climate to realise
the atmosphere of Dr. Price’s Old Jewry sermon.
The lapse of a century indeed has made him a more
intelligible figure than he could have seemed to the
generation which immediately followed him. He
was temperate in his rationalism and thrifty in his
philanthropy. He tended to Unitarianism in his
theology, but was a sturdy defender of Free Will.
He had written a widely-read apology for the Colonial
side in the American Civil War. A stout individualist
in his political theory, inspired, as were nearly
all the English progressive thinkers of his day, by
an extreme jealousy of State action, he yet guarded
himself carefully against anarchical conclusions,
and followed Saint Paul in teaching obedience to magistrates.
He had written a treatise on ethics which on some
points anticipated Kant. But his most characteristic
pre-occupation was a study of finance in the interests
of national thrift and social benevolence. This
cold moralist, who despised the emotional aspects
of human nature and found no place for the affections
in his scheme of the virtues, lapsed into passion when
he attacked the National Debt, and developed an arithmetical
enthusiasm when he explained his plan for providing
through voluntary insurance for the old age of the
worthy poor. He was not quite the first of the
philosophers to dream of the abolition of war, and
to plan an international tribunal for the settlement
of disputes between nations. In that he followed
Leibnitz, as he anticipated Kant.
It was such an essentially cold and
calculating intellect as this which in that age of
ferment could launch the new doctrine of the infinite
perfectibility of mankind. Modern readers know
the Rev. Dr. Price only from the fulminations of Burke,
in whose pages he figures now as an incendiary and
again as a fool. He was in point of fact the soul
of sobriety and the mirror of all the respectabilities
in his serious dissenting world. It is worth
while to note that he was also, with his friend Priestley,
perhaps the only English Nonconformist preacher who
has ever enjoyed a European reputation. No less
a man than Condorcet refers to him as one of the formative
minds of the century.
Dr. Price’s sermon is worth
a glance, not merely because it was the goad which
provoked Burke to eloquent fury, but still more because
it is a document which records for us the mood in
which even the older and graver progressives of his
generation greeted the French Revolution. It
was an official discourse delivered before the Society
for Commemorating the Revolution in Great Britain.
This typically English club claimed to have met annually
since 1688 for a dinner and a sermon. The centenary
of our own Revolution and the events in France gave
it for a moment a central place on the political stage.
It was an eminently respectable society, mainly composed
of middle-class Nonconformists, with four Doctors
of Divinity on its Committee, an entrance fee of half-a-guinea,
and a radical peer, Earl Stanhope, for its Chairman.
At its annual meeting in November, 1789, Dr. Price
“disdaining national partialities and rejoicing
in every triumph of liberty and justice over arbitrary
power,” had moved an address congratulating the
French National Assembly on “the Revolution
in that country and on the prospect it gives to the
two first kingdoms in the world of a common participation
in the blessings of civil and religious liberty.”
The sermon was an eloquent expansion of this address.
It opens with a defence of the cosmopolitan
attitude which could rejoice at an improvement in
the prospects of our hereditary rival. Christ
taught not patriotism, but universal benevolence, as
the parable of the Good Samaritan shows. “My
neighbour” is he to whom I can do most good,
whether foreigner or fellow-citizen. We should
love our country “ardently but not exclusively,”
considering ourselves “citizens of the world,”
and taking care “to maintain a just regard to
the rights of other countries.” Patriotism
had been in history a scourge of mankind. It
was among the Romans no better than “a principle
holding together a band of robbers in their attempts
to crush all liberty but their own.” The
aim of those who love their kind can be only to spread
Truth, Virtue and Liberty. To make mankind happy
and free, it should suffice to instruct them.
“Ignorance is the parent of bigotry, intolerance,
persecution and slavery. Inform and instruct mankind
and these evils will be excluded.” There
follow some rambling remarks on the need for a revisal
of the Liturgy and the Articles, a complaint of the
servility shown in a recent address to King George,
who ought to consider himself rather the servant than
the sovereign of his people, and a prediction that
France and England, each delivered from despotism by
a happy revolution, will now “not merely refrain
from engaging in wars with one another, but unite
in preventing wars everywhere.” As for our
own Revolution of 1688, it was a great but not a perfect
work. It had left religious toleration incomplete
and the Parliamentary franchise unequal. We must
continue to enforce its principles, especially in the
matter of removing the disabilities that still weigh
upon dissenters. Those principles are briefly
(1) Liberty of Conscience, (2) The right to resist
power when it is abused, and (3) The right to choose
our own governors, to cashier them for misconduct
and to frame a government for ourselves. There
follows a curious little moral exhortation which shows
how far the good Dr. Price was from forgetting his
duties as a preacher. He had been distressed
by the lax morals of some of his colleagues in the
agitation for Reform, and he pauses to deplore that
“not all who are zealous in this cause are as
conspicuous for purity of morals as for ability.”
He cannot reconcile himself to the idea of an immoral
patriot, and begs that they will at least hide their
vices. The old man finds his peroration in Simeon’s
prayer. He had seen the great salvation.
“I have lived to see thirty millions of people
indignant and resolute, spurning at slavery and demanding
liberty with an irresistible voice, their king led
in triumph and an arbitrary monarch surrendering himself
to his subjects. And now methinks I see the ardour
for liberty catching and spreading, a general amendment
beginning in human affairs; the dominion of kings
changed for the dominion of laws, and the dominion
of priests giving way to the dominion of reason and
conscience.”
The world remembers the scholar Salmasius
only because he provoked Milton to a learned outbreak
of bad manners. There is something immortal even
in the ill-temper of great men, and Dr. Price lives
in modern memory chiefly because he moved Burke to
declamatory rage. His Reflections on the French
Revolution was an answer to the Old Jewry sermon,
which, eloquent itself, was to beget much eloquence
in others. For four years the mighty debate went
on, and it became as the disputants conversed across
the echoes of the Terror, rather a dialogue between
the past and the future, than a discussion between
human voices. Burke answered Dr. Price, and to
Burke in turn replied Tom Paine with the brilliant,
confident, hard-hitting logic of a pamphlet (The
Rights of Man) which for all the efforts of Pitt
to suppress it, is still read and circulated to-day.
Two notable answers were ephemeral, one from Mary
Wollstonecraft, and another (Vindiciae Gallicae)
from Mackintosh, who afterwards recanted his own opinions
and lived to be known as Sir James.
To lift the discussion to the height
of a philosophical argument was reserved for William
Godwin, a mind steeped in the French and English speculation
of his century, gifted with rare powers of analysis,
and inspired with a faith in human reason in general
and his own logical capacity in particular, which
no English mind before him or after him has approached.
In spite of a lucid style and a certain cold eloquence
which illumines if it does not warm, Godwin’s
Political Justice was dead before its author,
while Burke lives and was never more widely read than
to-day.
The ghosts of great men have an erratic
habit in walking. It is passion rather than any
mere intellectual momentum which drives them from the
tomb. There is, moreover, in Burke a variety and
a humanity which appeals in some one of its phases
and moods to all of us in turn. The great store-house
of his emotions and his phrases has the catholicity
of the Bible. Each man can find in it what he
seeks. He is like the luminous phantom which
walked in Faust through the witcheries of the
Brocken. Each man saw in her his own first love.
He has been hero and prophet to Whigs and Tories,
and in our own generation we have seen him bequeath
an equal inspiration to a Cecil and a Morley.
It is no part of our task to attempt even the briefest
exposition of his philosophy; we are concerned with
him here chiefly as an influence which helped by its
vehemence and its superb rhetorical exaggerations to
drive the revolutionary thinkers who answered him
to parallel exaggerations and opposite extremes.
Inspired himself with a distrust of generalisation,
and a hatred of philosophers, he none the less evolved
a philosophy as he talked. Against his will he
was forced into the upper air in his furious pursuit
of the “political aeronauts.” His
was a volcanic intellect which flung up principles
in its moments of eruption, and poured them forth
pell-mell with the vitupérations and the exaltations.
No logical dissection can reach the
inner truth of Burke. Every statement of a principle
in an orator or a pamphleteer is coloured by the occasion,
the emotion, and the mood of an audience to whom it
is addressed. Burke spoke amid the angers and
alarms inspired first by the subversive energy, and
then by the doctrinaire cruelty of the French Revolution.
It was in the process of “diffusing the Terror”
that most of his philosophical obiter dicta
were uttered. The real nerve of the thinking
of a mind so vehement, so passionate, so essentially
dramatic is to be sought not in some principle which
was the major premise of his syllogisms, but in some
pervading emotion. Fanny Burney said of him that
when he spoke of the Revolution his face immediately
assumed “the expression of a man who is going
to defend himself against murderers.” That
is exactly the tone of all his later utterances.
His mission was to spread panic because he felt it.
By no other reading can one explain or excuse the
rage of his denunciation of the excellent Dr. Price.
If his was philosophy it was philosophy
seeing red. He predicted the Terror before it
occurred, and by his work in stirring Europe to the
coalition against France, he did much to realise his
own forebodings. But, to do Burke justice, his
was a disinterested fear, and it would be fairer to
call it a hatred of cruelty. Burke was not a man
to take fire because he thought a principle false.
His was rather the practical logic which found a principle
false because it led to evil; and the evil which caused
his mind to blaze was nearly always cruelty. He
hated the French philosophers because in the groves
of their Academy “at the end of every vista
you see nothing but the gallows.” He pursued
Rousseau and Dr. Price because their teaching, on
his reading of cause and effect, had set the tumbrils
rolling and weighted the guillotine for Marie Antoinette.
It was precisely the same impulse which had caused
him to pursue Warren Hastings for his cruelties towards
the Bégums of Oude. The spring of all this
speculation was a nerve which twitched with a maddening
sensitiveness at the sight of suffering.
To rouse Burke’s genius to its
noblest utterance, there must needs be a suffering
which he could personify and dramatise. He saw
nothing of the dull peasant misery which in truth
explained the Revolution. He ignored those catalogues
of injustice and wrong that composed the mandates (the
cahiers) which the Deputies carried with them
to the National Assembly. He forgot the famines,
the exactions, the oppressive privileges which made
revolt, and saw only the pathos of the Queen’s
helplessness before it. In Paine’s immortal
epigram, he “pitied the plumage and forgot the
dying bird.” But it is paradoxically true
that while he pursued the friends of humanity, his
real impulse was the hatred of cruelty which modern
men call humanitarian. To that hatred he was
always true. No abstract principle, but always
this dominating passion, covers his inconsistencies,
and bridges the gulf between his earlier Whiggery
and his later Toryism. In the French Revolution
he saw only cruelty, and he opposed it as he had opposed
Indian Imperialism, negro slavery, the savage criminal
justice of his day, and the penal laws against the
Irish Catholics. Of Burke one must ask not so
much What did he believe? as Whom did he pity?
It was the contrast of temperament
and attitude which made the cleavage between Burke
and the friends of the French Revolution deep and
irreconcilable. In the fundamentals of political
theory he often seems to agree with some of them,
and they differ as often among themselves. Burke
seems often to retain the typical eighteenth century
fiction that the State is based on some original pact
or social contract. That was Rousseau’s
starting point, and it was Godwin’s work (after
Hume) to shatter this heritage which French and English
speculation had been content to accept from Locke.
There are passages in which Burke appears to accept
the notion, unintelligible to modern minds, of the
natural, or as he put it, “primitive,”
rights of man. He reserved his contempt for those
who sought to tabulate or codify these rights, and
he would always brush aside any argument based upon
them, by asking the prior question, what in the given
emergency was best for the good of society, or the
happiness of men. Paine, when he was in his more
a priori moods, was capable of deducing his
whole practical system from the abstract rights of
man; Godwin was a modern in virtually dismissing the
whole notion. While Burke was belabouring Dr.
Price, he whittled away the whole theoretic significance
of the English Revolution of 1688, but he remained
its partisan. He tried to deny Dr. Price’s
claim to “choose our governors,” but he
could not relapse into the seventeenth-century Tory
doctrine of non-resistance, and would always allow
in extreme cases the right of rebellion. Here
again there was no final opposition, for there are
passages in Godwin against rash rebellion and the anarchy
of revolution more impressive, if less emotional,
than anything in Burke.
Modern criticism is disposed to base
the greatness of Burke on his inspired anticipation
of the historical view of politics. Quotation
has made classical those noble passages which glorify
the continuous life of mankind, link the present by
a chain of pieties to the past, conjure up a glowing
vision of the social organism, and celebrate the wisdom
of our ancestors and the infallibility of the race.
There was, indeed, a real opposition of temperament
here; but Burke had no monopoly of the historical
vision. It is a travesty to suggest that the revolutionary
school despised history. Paine, indeed, was a
self-taught man, who knew nothing of history and cared
less. But Godwin wrote history with success and
even penned a remarkable essay (On Sepulchres)
in which he anticipated the Comtist veneration for
the great dead, and proposed a national scheme for
covering the country with monuments to their memory.
Condorcet, perhaps the greatest intellect and certainly
the noblest character among them, wrote the first
attempt at a systematic evolutionary interpretation
of history.
But it makes some difference whether
a man sees history from above or from below.
Burke saw it from the comfortable altitude of the Whig
aristocracy to which he had allied himself. The
revolutionary school saw its inverse, from the standpoint
of the “swinish multitude” (an angry indiscretion
of Burke’s) for whom it had worked to less advantage.
Paine was a man of the people, and Godwin belonged
by birth to the dissenting community for whom history
had been chiefly a record of persecution, illuminated
by rebellion. For Burke the product of history
was the sacred constitution in which he saw an “entailed
heritage,” the social fabric “well cramped
and bolted together in all its parts.” For
Godwin it was mainly a chronicle of criminal wars,
savage oppressions, and social misery. Burke,
in a moment of paradoxical exaltation, was capable
of singing the praises of “prejudice,”
which “renders a man’s virtue his habit.”
For Condorcet, on the other hand, history was the orderly
procession of the human mind, advancing through a series
of well-marked epochs (he enumerated nine) from the
pastoral state to the French Revolution, each epoch
marked primarily by the shedding of some moral, social,
or theological “prejudice,” which had hampered
its advance.
It is easy to criticise the naïve
intellectualism of such a view as this, which ignores
or thrusts into the background the economic causes
of advance and retrogression. But it is certainly
not an unhistorical view. Burke dreaded fundamental
discussions which “turn men’s duties into
doubts.” The revolutionary school believed
that all progress depended on the daring and thoroughness
of these discussions. History for them was a
continuous Socratic dialogue, in which the philosophers
of innovation were always arrayed against the sophists
of authority. They hoped everything from the
leadership of the illuminated few who gradually permeate
the mass and raise it with them. Burke held that
“the individual is foolish, but the species
is wise,” and the “natural aristocracy”
in whom he trusted was to keep the inert mass in a
condition of stable equilibrium.
We retain from Burke to-day the sonorous
generalisations, the epigrammatic maxims, which each
of us applies in his own way. But to Burke’s
contemporaries they meant only one thing a
defence of the unreformed franchise. All his
reverence for the pre-ordained order of providence,
the “divine tactic” which had made society
what it was, meant for them in bald prose that Old
Sarum should have two members. Burke had not
“a doubt that the House of Commons represents
perfectly the whole commons of Great Britain.”
They, with no mystical view of history to guide them,
pointed out that its electors were a mere handful
of 12,000 in the whole population, and that Birmingham,
Manchester, Leeds, Sheffield and Bradford had not
a Member among them. While Burke perorated about
the ways of providence, they pointed to that auctioneer
who put up for sale to the highest bidder the fee simple
of the Borough of Gatton with the power of nominating
two members for ever. That auctioneer is worth
quoting: “Need I tell you, gentlemen, that
this elegant contingency is the only infallible source
of fortune, titles, and honours in this happy country?
That it leads to the highest situations in the State?
And that, meandering through the tempting sinuosities
of ambition, the purchaser will find the margin strewed
with roses, and his head quickly crowned with those
precious garlands that flourish in full vigour round
the fountain of honour? On this halcyon sea,
if any gentleman who has made his fortune in either
of the Indies chooses once more to embark, he may
repose in perfect quiet. No hurricanes to dread;
no tormenting claims of insolent electors to evade;
no tinkers’ wives to kiss.... With this
elegant contingency in his pocket, the honours of
the State await his plucking, and with its emoluments
his purse will overflow.”
A reference to the elegant contingency
of Gatton sufficed to deflate a good deal of eloquence.
Burke, indeed, believed in the pre-ordained
order of the world, but he somehow omitted the rebels.
When in his sublimest periods, he appealed to “the
known march of the ordinary providence of God,”
and saw in revolution and change an assault on the
divine order, one sees, rigid and forbidding, the
limitations of his thinking. The man who sees
in history a divine tactic must salute the regiment
in its headlong charge no less than the regiment which
stands with fixed bayonets around the ark of the covenant.
Said the Hindoo saint, who saw all things in God and
God in all things, to the soldier who was slaying him,
“And Thou also art He.” The march
of providence embraced 1789 as well as 1688.
Paine and Godwin, Danton and Robespierre might have
answered Burke with a reminder that they also were
His children.
The key to any understanding of the
dialogue between Burke and the Revolutionists is that
each side was moved by a passion which meant nothing
to the other. Burke was hoarse with anger and
fear at the excesses in France. They were afire
with an almost religious faith in human perfectibility.
Burke’s is a great record of detailed reforms
achieved or advocated, but for organic change there
was no place in his system, and he indulged in no
vision of human progress. “The only moral
trust with any certainty in our hands,” he wrote,
“is the care of our own time.” It
was of to-morrow that the Revolution thought, and even
of the day after to-morrow. Nothing could shake
its faith. Proscribed amid the Terror for his
moderation and independence, learning daily in the
garret where he hid of the violent deaths of friends
and comrades, witnessing, as it must have seemed to
him, the ruin of his work and the frustration of his
brightest hopes, Condorcet, solitary and disguised,
sat down to write that sketch of human destinies which
is, perhaps, the most confident statement of a reasoned
optimism in European literature. He finished
his Sketch for an Historical Picture of the Progress
of the Human Mind, left his garret, and went out
to meet his death. A year later, as if to show
that the great prodigal hope could survive the brain
that conceived it, the representatives of the French
people had it circulated as a national document.
Its thesis is that no limit can be
set to the perfection of human faculties, that the
progress and perfectibility of man are independent
of any power which can arrest them, and have no term
unless it be the duration of the globe itself.
The progress might be swift or slow, but the ultimate
end was sure. Twenty years before, Turgot projecting
a system of universal education in France, had promised
to transform the nation in ten years. Condorcet
was less sanguine, but his perspective was short.
The indefinite advance of mankind presupposed, he argued,
the elimination of inequality (1) among peoples, and
(2) among classes, and lastly the perfection of the
individual. For all this he believed that the
Revolution had already laid the foundation. Negro
slavery, for example, would end; Africa would enter
on a phase of culture dependent on settled agriculture,
and the East adopt free institutions. The time
was at hand when the sun would rise only on free men,
and tyrants, slaves, and priests would live only in
history. The Revolution had proclaimed the equality
of men, and the future would proceed to realise it.
Monopolies abolished, fortunes would tend to a level
of equality, and a system of insurance (Dr. Price’s
specific) would mitigate or abolish poverty.
Universal education would reduce the natural inequality
of talents, and break down the barriers of class, so
that men, retaining still the desire to be instructed
by others, would no longer need to be controlled by
their superiors. Science had made a dizzy progress
in the past generation, but its advance must be still
more rapid when general education enables it to be
cultivated by still greater numbers, and by women
as well as men. To the fear which Malthus afterwards
used as the most formidable argument against revolutionary
optimism, that a denser population would leave the
means of subsistence inadequate, he opposed intensive
cultivation, synthetic chemistry, and the progress
of mankind in self-control and virtue. Human
character itself will change with the amendment of
human institutions. Passion can be dominated by
reflection, and by the deliberate encouragement of
gentle and altruistic sentiments. The business
of politics is to destroy the opposition between self-interest
and altruism, and to make a world in which when a man
seeks his own good, he need no longer infringe the
good of others. A great share in this moral elevation
would come from the destruction of the inequality
of the sexes, which Condorcet preached in France while
Mary Wollstonecraft was its pioneer in England.
That inequality has been ruinous even to the sex which
it favoured, and rests in nothing but an abuse of
force. To remove it is not merely to raise the
status of women but to increase family happiness,
and to reform morals. Wars too will end, and
with them a constant menace to liberty. The ultimate
dream is a perpetual confederation of mankind.
It would be a fascinating but too
protracted study to follow this faith in the perfectibility
of mankind to its final enthusiasms of prophecy, and
to trace it to its origins in the speculations of Helvetius
and Holbach, of Priestley and Price. It was a
creative impulse which made for itself a psychology
and a sociology; it rather led the thinking of men
than followed from their reasonings. They seem
at every turn to choose of two alternative views the
one which would favour this sovereign hope. Is
it reason and opinion, or some innate character which
governs the actions of men? The philosophers of
hope answer “opinion,” for opinion can
be indefinitely changed and led from prejudice to
science. Is it climate (as Montesquieu had urged)
or political institutions which differentiate the
races of men? Clearly it is institutions, for
if it were climate there would be nothing to hope from
reform. Burke opposed to all their schemes of
construction and destruction, to their generalisations
and philosophisings, the unchangeable fact of human
nature. They answered (diving into Helvetius)
that human nature is itself the product of “education”
or, as we should call it, “environment.”
Circumstances and above all political institutions
have made man what he is. Princes, as Holbach
puts it, are gardeners who can by varying systems
of cultivation alter the character of men as they
would alter the form of trees. Change the institutions
and you will change human nature itself. There
seemed no limit to the improvement which would follow
if we could but discard the fetters of prejudice and
despotism.
Wordsworth’s “shades of
the prison-house” which close upon the growing
boy, were an echo of this thought. Godwin’s
friend, Holcroft, embodied it in a striking metaphor:
“Men do not become what by nature they are meant
to be, but what society makes them. The generous
feelings and higher propensities of the soul are,
as it were shrunk up, scared, violently wrenched,
and amputated, to fit us for our intercourse in the
world, something in the manner that beggars maim and
mutilate their children to make them fit for their
future situation in life.”
The men of the Revolution phrased
that idea each in his own way, according as they had
been influenced, primarily, by Rousseau, Helvetius,
or Condorcet. It gave to their controversy with
Burke the appearance, not so much of a dispute between
rival schools, as of a dialogue between men who spoke
to each other in unknown tongues.
Burke condescended to reason with
Dr. Price. But the main answer of authority to
the friends of the French Revolution, was the answer
which Burke prescribed for “infidels” “a
refutation by criminal justice.” A curious
parallel movement towards extremes went on simultaneously
in the two camps. While Burke separated himself
from Fox, split the Whig party, and devoted his genius
to the task of fanning the general English dislike
of the Revolution into a panic rage of anger and fear,
the progressive camp in its turn was gradually captured
by the “intellectuals,” and passed from
a humdrum demand for political reform into a ferment
of moral and social speculation. Societies grew
up in all the chief centres of population, always
with the same programme. “An honest Parliament.
An annual Parliament. A Parliament wherein each
individual will have his representative.”
Of these the most active, the most extreme, and the
best organised was undoubtedly the London Corresponding
Society.
It was founded by a Scottish boot-maker
named Thomas Hardy. The sober, limited character
of the man is plain to read in his records and pamphlets.
The son of a sea-captain, who had had his education
in a village school in Perthshire where the scholars
paid a penny a week, he was a leading member of the
Scots’ Kirk in Covent Garden, and had drawn
his political education not at all from godless French
philosophers, but from the Protestant fanatic, Lord
George Gordon, and from Dr. Price’s book on
the American War. He gathered his own friends
together to found his society, and nine of them met
for the first time in the “Bell” tavern
in Exeter Street in January, 1792. “They
had finished their daily labour and met there by appointment.
After having their bread and cheese and porter for
supper, as usual, and their pipes afterwards, with
some conversation, on the hardness of the times and
the dearness of all the necessaries of life, which
they in common with their fellow-citizens felt to
their sorrow, the business for which they had met was
brought forward Parliamentary Reform.”
The Corresponding Society drew the
bulk of its members from tradesmen, mechanics and
shopkeepers, who contributed their penny a week, and
organised itself under Hardy’s methodical guidance
into numerous branches each with twenty members.
It is said to have counted in the end some 30,000
members in London alone. It was a focus of discontent
and hope which soon attracted men of more conspicuous
talents and wider experience. Horne Tooke, man
about town, ex-clergyman, and philologist, who had
been at first the friend and lieutenant and then the
rival and enemy of Wilkes, was there to bridge the
years between the last great popular agitation and
the new hopes of reform. He was a man cautious
and even timid in action, but there was a vanity in
him which led him to say “hanging matters”
when he had an inflammable audience in front of him
within the four walls of a room. There was Tom
Paine, the man who had first dared to propose the
independence of the United States, a veteran of revolution
who had served on Washington’s staff, penned
those brilliant exhortations which led the American
rebels to victory, and acted as Foreign Secretary
to the insurgent Congress. On the fringes of
the little inner circle of intellectuals one catches
a glimpse of William Blake the poet, and Ritson, the
first teacher and theorist of vegetarianism.
Not the least interesting member of the group was Thomas
Holcroft, the inseparable friend and ally of William
Godwin. Holcroft’s vivid and masterful
personality stands out indeed as the most attractive
among the abler members of the circle. The son
of a boot-maker, he had earned his bread as cobbler,
ostler, village schoolmaster, strolling player and
reporter. His insatiable passion for knowledge
had given him a mastery of French and German.
He went in 1783 to Paris as correspondent of the Morning
Herald, on the modest salary of a guinea-and-a-half
a week. It was there that he acquired his familiarity
with the writings of the French political philosophers,
and performed the quaint achievement of pirating Figaro
for the English stage. No printed copy was obtainable,
and Holcroft contrived to commit the whole play to
memory by attending ten performances, much as Mozart
had pirated the ancient exclusive music of St. Peter’s
in Rome. He was at this period a thriving literary
craftsman, and the author of a series of popular plays
in which the critics of the time had just begun to
note and resent an obtrusive democratic tendency.
Under the influence of these eager
speculative spirits, the Corresponding Society must
have travelled far from its original business of Parliamentary
Reform. Here is an extract from evidence given
before the Privy Council, which relates the proceedings
at one of its later meetings:
“The most gentlemanlike person
took the chair and talked about an equal representation
of the people, and of putting an end to war. Holcroft
talked about the Powers of the Human Mind....
Mr. Holcroft talked a great deal about Peace, of his
being against any violent or coercive means, that
were usually resorted to against our fellow-creatures,
urged the more powerful operation of Philosophy and
Reason to convince man of his errors; that he would
disarm his greatest enemy by these means and oppose
his Fury. He spoke also about Truth being powerful,
and gave advice to the above effect to the delegates
present who all seemed to agree, as no person opposed
his arguments.”
One may doubt, however, whether the
whole society was composed of “natural Quakers,”
who, like Holcroft and Godwin, preached non-resistance
before Tolstoy. The dour commonsense of Hardy
maintained the theory he vowed that it
was only theory that every citizen should
possess arms and know their use. As the Revolution
went forward in France, the agitation in England became
increasingly reckless. When the society held
its anniversary dinner after the Terror, in May, 1794,
at the “Crown and Anchor” Tavern, the
band played “Ca ira,” the “Carmagnole”
and the “Marseillaise.” The chief
toasts were “the Rights of Man,” and “the
Armies contending for Liberty,” which was a
sufficiently clear phrase for describing the Republican
armies that were at war with England. There followed
an ode composed by Sir William Jones, a translation
of the Athenian song which celebrated the deeds of
the tyrannicides, Harmodius and Aristogeiton;
Verdant myrtle’s branchy pride
Shall my thirsty blade entwine.
One may doubt whether Sir William
Jones ever felt the smallest inclination to satisfy
the thirst of his blade, but there was provision enough
for more commonplace appetites. Two years before,
Hardy’s worthy mechanics had supped on porter
and cheese and talked of the hardness of the times.
Their movement had been captured by a group of eager,
sophisticated, literary persons, who went much farther
than Parliamentary Reform, and with the aid of claret
and the subtler French intoxicants, “turned
indignant” as another Ode puts it:
From Kings who seek in Gothic night
To hide the blaze of moral light.
Fill high the animating glass
And let the electric ruby pass.
It was a cheerful indignation, a festive rage.
That dinner must have marked the height
of the revolutionary tide in England. The reaction
was already rampant and vindictive, and before the
year 1794 was out it had crushed the progressive movement
and postponed for thirty-eight years the triumph of
Parliamentary Reform. It requires a strenuous
exercise of the imagination to conceive the panic which
swept over England as the news of the French Terror
circulated. It fastened impartially on every
class of the community, and destroyed the emotional
balance no less of Pitt and his colleagues than of
the working men who formed the Church and King mobs.
Proclamations were issued to quell insurrections which
never had been planned, and the militia called out
when not a hand had been raised against the King throughout
Great Britain. So great was the fear, so deep
the moral indignation that “even respectable
and honest men,” (the phrase is Holcroft’s)
“turned spies and informers on their friends
from a sense of public duty.” A mob burned
Dr. Priestley’s house near Birmingham for no
better reason than because he was supposed to have
attended a Reform dinner, which in fact, he did not
attend. Hardy’s bookshop in Piccadilly was
rushed by a mob, and his wife, about to be confined,
was injured in her efforts to escape, and died a few
hours afterwards. A hunt went on all over the
kingdom for booksellers and printers to prosecute,
and when Thomas Paine was prosecuted in his absence
for publishing The Rights of Man, the jury
was so determined to find him guilty that they would
not trouble to hear the case for the Crown.
Twenty years before, the French philosopher
Helvetius, after an experience of Jesuit persecution
and Court disfavour in France, made a quaint proposal
for re-organising the whole discussion of moral and
political questions. The first step, he thought,
was to compile a dictionary in which all the terms
required in such debates would receive an authoritative
definition. But this dictionary, he urged, must
be composed in the English language, and published
first in England, for only there was discussion free,
and the press unfettered. In the reaction over
which Pitt and Dundas presided, that envied liberty
was totally eclipsed. The Habeas Corpus
Act was suspended; the Privy Council sat as a sort
of Star Chamber to question political suspects, and
there was even talk of importing Hessian and Hanoverian
mercenaries to check an insurrection which nowhere
showed its head. The frailest of all human endowments
is the sense of humour. The sense of proportion
had been eclipsed in the panic, and most of the cases
which may be studied to-day in the State trials impress
the modern reader as tasteless and cruel farces.
Men were tried and sentenced never for deeds, but always
for words. For a sermon closely resembling Dr.
Price’s, a dissenting minister named Winterbotham
was tried at Exeter, and sentenced to four years’
imprisonment and a fine of L200. The attorney,
John Frost, returning from France, admitted in a chance
conversation in a coffee-house that he thought society
could manage very well without kings; he was imprisoned,
set in the pillory and struck off the rolls.
One favourite expedient was to produce a spy who would
swear that he had heard some suspect Radical declare
in a coach or a coffee-house, that he would “as
soon have the King’s head off as he would tear
a bit of paper” (evidence against a group of
Manchester prisoners), or that he “would cut
off the King’s head as easily as he would shave
himself” (case against Thomas Hardy). The
climax of really entertaining absurdity was reached
when two debtors imprisoned in the Fleet were tried
and sentenced for nailing a seditious libel to its
doors. The libel was a notice that “This
house is to let,” that “infamous bastilles
are no longer necessary in Europe,” and that
“peaceable possession” would be secured
“on or before the first day of January, 1793,
being the commencement of the first year of liberty
in Great Britain.”
The farce of this panic became a tragedy
when the reformers of Scotland ventured to summon
a Convention at Edinburgh to voice the demand for
shorter Parliaments and universal male suffrage.
It met in October, 1793, and was attended by delegates
from the London Corresponding Society as well as from
Scottish branches. Nothing was intended beyond
the holding of what we should call to-day a conference
or congress. But the word “Convention”
with its reminiscence of the French revolutionary
assembly seems to have caused the Government some particular
alarm. The Convention, after some days of orderly
debate, was invaded by the magistrates and broken
up. Margarot and Sinclair (the English delegates),
Skirving, Palmer and Thomas Muir, were tried before
that notorious hanging judge, whom Stevenson portrayed
as Weir of Hermiston, and sentenced to fourteen years’
deportation at Botany Bay.
Of these five, all of them young men
of brilliant promise and high courage, only one, Margarot,
lived to return to England. Muir, daring, romantic
and headstrong, contributed to the history of the movement
a page of adventure which might invite the attention
of a novelist. He escaped from Botany Bay on
a whaler, was wrecked on the coast of South America,
contrived to wander to the West Indies, there shipped
on a Spanish vessel for Europe, fell in with an English
frigate, was wounded in the fight that followed, and
had the good fortune to find among the officers who
took him prisoner an old friend, who recognised him,
and assisted him to conceal his identity. He
was landed in Spain, invited to Paris and pensioned
by the Convention, but died shortly after his arrival.
Less romantic but even finer is Sinclair’s story.
He obtained bail while his comrades were tried and
sentenced. He might have broken his bail, and
his friends urged him to do so, but with the certainty
that Botany Bay lay before him he none the less returned
to Edinburgh, as Horne Tooke puts it “in discharge
of his faith as a private man towards his bail, and
in discharge of his duty towards an oppressed and
insulted public; he has returned not to take a fair
trial, but, as he is well persuaded, to a settled
conviction and sentence.” Joseph Gerrald,
another member of the same group gave the same fine
example of courage, surrendered to his bail, and was
sent for fifteen years to Botany Bay.
The ferment was more than an intellectual
stirring. It brought with it a moral elevation
and a great courage that did not shrink from venturing
life and fortune for a disinterested end. The
modern reader is apt to indulge a smile when he reads
in the ardent declamation of this time professions
of a love of Virtue and praises of Universal Benevolence.
We are impatient of abstractions and shy of capital
letters. But it was no abstraction which carried
a man with honour to the fevers and privations of
Botany Bay, when he might have sought safety and fame
in Paris. The English reformers were resolved
to brave the worst that Pitt could do to them, and
challenged the fate of their Scottish comrades.
They prepared in their turn to hold a “Convention”
for Parliamentary Reform, and showed a doubtful prudence
in keeping its details secret while the intention
was boldly avowed. The counter-stroke came promptly.
Twelve of the leading members of the Corresponding
Society, including Hardy, Horne Tooke and Holcroft
were arrested and sent, for the most part to the Tower,
on a charge of high treason. The records of their
preliminary examination before the Privy Council go
to show that Pitt and Dundas had allowed themselves
to be persuaded by their spies that every species
of treason and folly was in preparation, from an armed
insurrection down to a plan to murder the King by blowing
a poisoned arrow from an air-gun. The Government
had said that there was a treasonable conspiracy;
it had to produce the traitors.
There was some delay in arresting
Holcroft. His conduct is worth recording because
it is so typical of the naïve courage, the doctrinaire
hardihood of the group. These men whom the reaction
accused of subverting morality, were in fact dervishes
of principle, who rushed on the bayonets in the name
of manhood and truth and sincerity. Godwin when
he came in his systematic treatise to describe how
a free people would conduct a defensive war, declared
that it would scorn to resort to a stratagem or an
ambuscade. In the same spirit Holcroft hearing
that a warrant was out against him for high treason,
walked boldly into the Chief Justice’s court,
and announced that he came to be put upon his trial
“that if I am a guilty man, the whole extent
of my guilt may become notorious, and if innocent
that the rectitude of my principles and conduct may
be no less public.” When a messenger did,
in fact, go to Holcroft’s house about the same
hour to arrest him, his daughters, obedient to the
same ideal of sincerity, actually invited him to take
their father’s papers.
One may doubt whether English liberties
have ever run a graver danger in modern times than
at the trial of the twelve reformers. The Government
sought to overwhelm them with a mass of evidence which
they lacked the means to sift and confute. But
no definite act was charged against them, and the
whole case turned on a monstrous attempt to give a
wide constructive interpretation to the law of high
treason. High treason in English law has the
perfectly definite meaning of an attempt on the King’s
life, or the levying of war against him. Chief
Justice Eyre, in his charge to the Grand Jury, sought
to stretch it until it assumed a Russian latitude,
and would include any effort by agitation to alter
the form of government or the constitution of Parliament.
The issue, before a jury which probably had not escaped
the general panic, seemed very doubtful, and it was
the general opinion that the decisive blow for liberty
was struck by William Godwin. Long years afterwards
Horne Tooke, in a dramatic scene, called Godwin to
him in public, and kissed the hand which had saved
his life.
Godwin contributed to the Morning
Chronicle a long letter, or more properly, a pamphlet,
in which he analysed the Chief Justice’s charge
and brought to the light what really was latent in
it, a claim to treat as high treason any effort, however
peaceful and orderly, to bring about a fundamental
change in our institutions. The letter shows none
of Godwin’s speculative daring, and his gift
of cold and dignified eloquence is severely repressed.
He wrote to attain his immediate end, and from that
standpoint his pleading was a masterpiece. A certain
deadly courtesy, a tone of quiet reasonableness made
it possible for the most prejudiced reader to follow
it with assent. The argument was irresistible,
and the single touch of emotion at the end was worthy
of a great orator. A few lines depicted these
men who, moved by public spirit, had acted in good
faith within the law, as it had been universally understood
in England, overwhelmed by a sudden extension of its
most terrible articles, applied to them without precedent
or warning. Should the awful sentence be read
over these men, that they should be hanged (but not
until they were dead), and then, still living, suffer
the loss of their members and see their bowels torn
out? The ghastly barbarity of the whole procedure
could not have been more effectively exposed.
Looking back upon this trial there is no reason to
think that the reformers exaggerated its importance.
Had the Government won its case, it must have succeeded
in destroying the very possibility of opposition or
agitation in England. It was believed that no
less than three hundred signed warrants lay ready
for issue on the day that Hardy and his friends were
convicted. But the stroke was too daring, the
threat too impudent. When the trial began, the
prosecution lightened its own task by dropping the
charge against Holcroft and three of his comrades.
But for nine days the charge was pressed against Thomas
Hardy, and when he was acquitted a further six days
was spent in the effort to convict Horne Tooke, and
four in a last vain attempt to succeed against Thelwall.
The popular victory checked the excesses
of the reaction. As Holcroft wrote: “The
whole power of Government was directed against Thomas
Hardy: in his fate seemed involved the fate of
the nation, and the verdict of Not Guilty appeared
to burst its bonds, and to have released it from inconceivable
miseries and ages of impending slavery.”
The reaction, indeed, was restrained; but so also
was the movement of reform. The subsequent history
of its leaders is one of unheroic failure, and of an
unpopularity which was harder to endure than danger.
Windham referred to the twelve in debate as “acquitted
felons,” and Holcroft was constrained first
to produce his plays under a borrowed name, and then
to seek a refuge in voluntary exile on the continent.
The passions roused by the Terror arrested the progress
of the revolutionary movement in England. The
alarms and glories of the struggle with Napoleon buried
it in oblivion.
It is this complex experience which
lies behind Godwin’s political writings.
The French Revolution produced its simple effects in
Burke and Tom Paine revolt and disgust
in the one, enthusiasm and hope in the other.
In Godwin the reaction is more complicated. He
retained to the last his ardent faith in progress,
and the perfectibility of mankind. No events
could shake that, but it was the work of experience
to reinforce all the native individualism of his confident
and self-reliant temper, to harden into an extreme
dogma that general belief in laissez faire
which was the common property of most of the English
progressives of his day, and to beget in him not merely
a doubt in the efficacy of violent revolutions, but
a dislike of all concerted political effort and the
whole collective work of political associations.
He had felt the lash of repression, saved one friend
from the hangman, and seen others depart for Botany
Bay: he remained to the end, the uncompromising
foe of every species of governmental coercion.
He had listened to Horne Tooke perorating “hanging
matters” at the Corresponding Society; he had
seen the “electric ruby” circulating at
its dinners; he had witnessed the collapse of Thomas
Hardy’s painstaking and methodical organisation.
The fruit of all these experiences was the first statement
in European literature of philosophic anarchism a
statement which hardly yields to Tolstoy’s in
its trenchant and unflinching logic.
“Logic” is more often
a habit of consecutive and reasoned writing than the
source of a thinker’s opinion. The logical
writer is the man who can succeed in displaying plausible
reasons for what he believes by instinct, or knows
by experience. There is history and temperament
behind the coldest logic. The history which set
Godwin against all State action, whether undertaken
in defence of order or privilege, or on behalf of
reform, is to be read in the excesses of Pitt and the
futilities of the Corresponding Society. The question
of temperament involves a subtler psychological judgment.
If you feel in yourself something less than the heroic
temper which will make a militant agitation or a violent
revolution against the monstrous ascendency of privilege
and ordered force, you are lucky if you can convince
yourself that agitation is commonly mischievous, and
association but a means of combating one evil by creating
another. Godwin was certainly no coward.
But he was fortunate in evolving a theory which excused
him from attempting the more dangerous exploits of
civic courage. His ideal was the Stoic virtue,
the isolated strength, which can stand firm in passive
protest against oppression and wrong. He stood
firm, and Pitt was content to leave him standing.
We have seen the first bold statement
of the hope which the French Revolution kindled in
Dr. Price’s Old Jewry sermon. We have watched
the brave incautious effort to realise it in the plans
of the Corresponding Society. In these crowded
years that began with the fall of the Bastille and
closed with the Terror, it was to enter on yet another
phase, and in this last incarnation the hope was very
near despair. To men in the early prime of life,
aware of their powers and their gift of influence,
the Revolution came as a call to action. To a
group of still younger men, poets and thinkers, forming
their first eager views of life in the leisure of
the Universities, it was above all a stimulus to fancy.
Godwin was their prophet, but they built upon his speculations
the superstructure of a dream that was all their own.
For some years, Coleridge, Southey, and Wordsworth
were caught and held in the close web of logic which
Godwin gave to the world in 1793 in the first edition
of Political Justice. Wordsworth read
and studied and continually discussed it. Southey
confessed that he “read and studied and all but
worshipped Godwin.” Coleridge wrote a sonnet
which he afterwards suppressed in which he blesses
his “holy guidance” and hymns Godwin “with
an ardent lay.”
For that thy voice in passion’s
stormy day
When wild I roamed the bleak heath of
distress
Bade the bright form of Justice meet my
way,
And told me that her name was Happiness.
To us who read Godwin with many a
later Utopia in our memories, his most valuable chapters
are those which give his penetrating criticisms of
existing society. To these young men the excitement
was in his picture of a free community from which
laws and coercion had been eliminated, and in which
property was in a continual flux actuated by the stream
of universal benevolence. They resolved to found
a community based on Godwinian principles, and to
free themselves from the cramping and dwarfing influences
of a society ruined by laws and superstitions, they
lit on the simple expedient of removing themselves
beyond its reach. They lacked the manhood and
the simplicity which had turned more prosaic natures
into agitators and reformers. It is a tale which
every student of literature has delighted to read,
how Coleridge and Southey, bent on founding their
Pantisocracy, on the banks of the Susquehana, came
to Bristol to charter a ship, and while they waited,
dimly aware that they lacked funds for the adventure,
anchored themselves in English homes by marrying the
Fricker sisters.
As one of the comrades, Robert Lovell,
quaintly puts it in a letter to Holcroft, “Principle,
not plan, is our object.” Lovell had visited
Holcroft in gaol, and one can well understand how that
near view of the fate which awaited the reformer under
Pitt, confirmed them in their idea of crossing the
Atlantic. “From the writings of William
Godwin and yourself,” Lovell went on, “our
minds have been illuminated; we wish our actions to
be guided by the same superior abilities.”
Holcroft, older and more combative than his poet-disciples,
advised the founding of a model colony in this country.
But the lure of a distant scene was too attractive.
Cottle, the friend and publisher of the Pantisocrats,
has left his account of their aims. Theirs was
to be “a social colony in which there was to
be a community of property and where all that was
selfish was to be proscribed.” It would
realise “a state of society free from the evils
and turmoils that then agitated the world, and present
an example of the eminence to which men might arrive
under the unrestrained influence of sound principles.”
It would “regenerate the whole complexion of
society, and that not by establishing formal laws,
but by excluding all the little deteriorating passions,
injustice, wrath, anger, clamor, and evil speaking,
and thereby setting an example of human perfectibility.”
What is left of the dream to-day?
Some verses in Coleridge’s earlier poems, the
address to Chatterton for instance
O Chatterton! that thou wert yet alive,
Sure thou wouldst spread the canvas to
the gale;
And love with us the tinkling team to
drive
O’er peaceful Freedom’s undivided
dale.
and those lines, half comical, half
pathetic, in which the “sweet harper”
is assured as some requital for a hard life and a cruel
death, that the Pantisocrats will raise a “solemn
cenotaph” to his memory “Where Susquehana
pours his untamed stream.” Long afterwards,
Coleridge described Pantisocracy in The Friend
as “a plan as harmless as it was extravagant,”
which had served a purpose by saving him from more
dangerous courses. “It was serviceable in
securing myself and perhaps some others from the paths
of sedition. We were kept free from the stains
and impurities which might have remained upon us had
we been travelling with the crowd of less imaginative
malcontents through the dark lanes and foul by-roads
of ordinary fanaticism.”
Pantisocracy was indeed a happy episode
for English literature. One may doubt whether
the “Ancient Mariner” would have been written,
had Coleridge travelled with Gerrald and Sinclair
along the “dark lane” that led to Botany
Bay. Nature can work strange miracles with the
instinct of self-preservation, and even for poets
she has a care. The prudence which teaches one
man to be a Whig, will make of another a Utopian.