“Where Liberty is, there is
my country.” The sentiment has a Latin ring;
one can imagine an early Stoic as its author.
It was spoken by Benjamin Franklin, and no saying
better expresses the spirit of eighteenth century
humanity. “Where is not Liberty, there is
mine.” The answer is Thomas Paine’s.
It is the watchword of the knight errant, the marching
music that sent Lafayette to America, and Byron to
Greece, the motto of every man who prizes striving
above enjoyment, honours comradeship above patriotism,
and follows an idea that no frontier can arrest.
Paine was indeed of no century, and no formula of
classification can confine him. His writing is
of the age of enlightenment; his actions belong to
romance. His clear, manly style, his sturdy commonsense,
the rapier play of his epigrams, the formal, logical
architecture of his thoughts, his complacent limitations,
his horror of mystery and Gothic half-lights, his
harsh contempt for all the sacred muddle of priestly
traditions and aristocratic politics, his assurance,
his intellectual courage, his humanity all
that, in its best and its worst, belongs to the century
of Voltaire and the Revolution. In his spirit
of adventure, in his passion for movement and combat,
there Paine is romantic. Paine thought in prose
and acted epics. He drew horizons on paper and
pursued the infinite in deeds.
Tom Paine was born, the son of a Quaker
stay-maker, in 1737, at Thetford, in the county of
Norfolk. His parents were poor, but he owed much,
he tells us, to a good moral education and picked up
“a tolerable stock of useful learning,”
though he knew no language but his own. A “Friend”
he was to the end in his independence, his rationalism,
and his humanity, though he laughed when he thought
of what a sad-coloured world the Quakers would have
made of the creation, if they had been consulted.
The boy craved adventure, and was prevented at seventeen
from enlisting in the crew of the privateer Terrible,
Captain Death, only to sail somewhat later in the
King of Prussia, Captain Mendez. One cruise
under a licensed pirate was enough for him, and he
soon settled in London, making stays for a living
and spending his leisure in the study of astronomy.
He qualified as an exciseman, acquiring in this employment
a grasp of finance and an interest in budgets of which
he afterwards made good use in his writings.
Cashiered for negligence, he turned schoolmaster,
and even aspired to ordination in the Church of England.
Reinstated as a “gauger,” he was eventually
dismissed for writing a pamphlet in defence of the
excisemen’s agitation for higher wages.
He was twice married, but his first wife died within
a year of marriage, and the second, with whom he had
started a “tobacco-mill,” agreed on its
failure, apparently for no definite fault on either
side, to a mutual separation. At thirty-seven,
penniless, lonely, and stamped with failure, yet conscious
of powers which had found no scope in the Old World,
he emigrated in 1774 to America with a letter from
Benjamin Franklin as his passport to fortune.
Opportunity came promptly, and Paine
was presently settled in Philadelphia as the editor
of the Pennsylvania Magazine. From the
pages of this periodical, his admirable biographer,
Mr. Moncure D. Conway, has unearthed a series of articles
which show that Paine had somehow brought with him
from England a mental equipment which ranked him already
among the moral pioneers of his generation. He
advocates international arbitration; he attacks duelling;
he suggests more rational ideas of marriage and divorce;
he pleads for mercy to animals; he demands justice
for women. Above all, he assails negro slavery,
and with such mastery and fervour, that five weeks
after the appearance of his article, the first American
Anti-Slavery Society was founded at Philadelphia.
The abolition of slavery was a cause for which he never
ceased to struggle, and when in later life he became
the target of religious persecutors, it was in their
dual capacity of Christians and slave-owners that
men stoned him. The American colonies were now
at the parting of the ways in the struggle with the
Mother Country. The revolt had begun with a limited
object, and few if any of its leaders realised whither
they were tending. Paine it was, who after the
slaughter at Lexington, abandoned all thoughts of
reconciliation and was the first to preach independence
and republicanism.
His pamphlet, Common-Sense
(1776), achieved a circulation which was an event
in the history of printing, and fixed in men’s
minds as firm resolves what were, before he wrote,
no more than fluid ideas. It spoke to rebels
and made a nation. Poor though Paine was, he poured
the whole of the immense profits which he received
from the sale of his little book into the colonial
war-chest, shouldered a musket, joined Washington’s
army as a private, and was soon promoted to be aide-de-camp
to General Greene. Paine’s most valuable
weapon, however, was still his pen. Writing at
night, after endless marches, by the light of camp
fires at a moment of general depression, when even
Washington thought that the game was “pretty
well up,” Paine began to write the series of
pamphlets afterwards collected under the title of
The American Crisis. They did for the
American volunteers what Rouget de Lisle’s immortal
song did for the French levies in the revolutionary
wars, what Koerner’s martial ballads did for
the German patriots in the Napoleonic wars. These
superb pages of exhortation were read in every camp
to the disheartened men; their courage commanded victory.
Burke himself wrote nothing finer than the opening
sentences of the first “crisis,” a trumpet
call indeed, but phrased by an artist who knew the
science of compelling music from brass:
“These are the times that try
men’s souls. The summer soldier and the
sunshine patriot will, in this crisis, shrink from
the service of his country; but he that stands it
now, deserves the thanks of man and woman. Tyranny,
like Hell, is not easily conquered; yet we have this
consolation with us, that the harder the conflict the
more glorious the triumph. What we obtain too
cheap we esteem too lightly; it is dearness only that
gives everything its value. Heaven knows how to
put a proper price upon its goods; and it would be
strange indeed if so celestial an article as freedom
should not be highly rated.”
“Common-sense” Paine was
now the chief of the moral forces behind the fighting
Republic, and his power of thinking boldly and stating
clearly drove it forward to its destiny under the
leadership of men whom Nature had gifted with less
trenchant minds. He was in succession Foreign
Secretary to Congress and clerk to the Pennsylvania
Assembly, and we find him converting despair into
triumph by the magic of self-sacrifice. He it
was who in 1780 saved the finances of the war in a
moment of despair, by starting the patriotic subscription
with the gift of his own salary, and in 1781 proved
his diplomatic gift in a journey to Paris by obtaining
money-aid from the French Court.
Paine might have settled down to enjoy
his fame, after the war, on the little property which
the State of New York gave him. He loathed inaction
and escaped middle age. In 1787 he returned to
England, partly to carry his pen where the work of
liberation called for it, partly to forward his mechanical
inventions. Paine, self-educated though he was,
was a capable mathematician, and he followed the progress
of the applied sciences with passion. His inventions
include a long list of things partly useful, partly
whimsical, a planing machine, a crane, a smokeless
candle and a gunpowder motor. But his fame as
an inventor rests on his construction of the first
iron bridge, made after his models and plans at Wearmouth.
He was received as a leader and teacher in the ardent
circle of reformers grouped round the Revolution Society
and the Corresponding Society. Others were the
dreamers and theorists of liberty. He had been
at the making of a Republic, and his American experience
gave the stimulus to English Radicalism which events
in France were presently to repeat. His fame
was already European, and at the fall of the Bastille,
it was to Paine that Lafayette confided its key, when
a free France sent that symbol of defeated despotism
as a present to a free America. He seemed the
natural link between three revolutions, the one which
had succeeded in the New World, the other which was
transforming France, and the third which was yet to
come in England.
Burke’s Reflections rang
in his ears like a challenge, and he sat promptly
down in his inn to write his reply. The Rights of
Man is an answer to Burke, but it is much more.
The vivid pages of history in which he explains and
defends the French Revolution which Burke had attacked
and misunderstood, are only an illustration to his
main argument. He expounds the right of revolution,
and blows away the cobweb argument of legality by
which his antagonist had sought to confine posterity
within the settlement of 1688. Every age and generation
must be free to act for itself. Man has no property
in man, and the claim of one generation to govern
beyond the grave is of all tyrannies the most
insolent. Burke had contended for the right of
the dead to govern the living, but that which a whole
nation chooses to do, it has a right to do. The
men of 1688, who surrendered their own rights and bound
themselves to obey King William and his heirs, might
indeed choose to be slaves; but that could not lessen
the right of their children to be free. Wrongs
cannot have a legal descent. Here was a bold and
triumphant answer to a sophistical argument; but it
served Paine only as a preface to his exposition of
the American constitution, which was “to Liberty
what a grammar is to language,” and to his plea
for the adoption in England of the French charter
of the Rights of Man.
Paine felt that he had made one Republic
with a pamphlet, why not another? He had the
unlimited faith of his generation in the efficacy of
argument, and experience had proved his power.
As Carlyle, in his whimsical dramatic fashion, said
of him, “He can and will free all this world;
perhaps even the other.” Godwin, as became
the philosopher of the movement, set his hopes on
the slower working of education: to make men
wise was to make them free. Paine was the pamphleteer
of the human camp. He saw mankind as an embattled
legion and believed, true man of action that he was,
that freedom could be won like victory by the impetus
of a resolute charge. He quotes the epigram of
his fellow-soldier, Lafayette, “For a nation
to love liberty, it is sufficient that she knows it;
and to be free it is sufficient that she wills it.”
Godwin would have sent men to school to liberty; Paine
called them to her unfurled standard. It is easy
to understand the success of Paine’s book, which
appeared in March, 1791. It was theory and practice
in one; it was the armed logic which had driven King
George’s regiments from America, the edged argument
which had razed the Bastille. It was bold reasoning,
and it was also inspired writing. Holcroft and
Godwin helped to bring out The Rights of Man,
threatened with suppression or mutilation by the publishers,
and a panting incoherent shout of joy in a note from
Holcroft to Godwin is typical of the excitement which
it caused:
“I have got it if
this do not cure my cough it is a damned perverse
mule of a cough. The pamphlet from
the row But mum we don’t
sell it oh, no ears and eggs verbatim,
except the addition of a short preface, which as you
have not seen, I send you my copy. Not a
single castration (Laud be unto God and J. S. Jordan!)
can I discover Hey, for the new Jerusalem!
The Millennium! And peace and eternal beatitude
be unto the soul of Thomas Paine.”
The usual prosecutions of booksellers
followed; but everywhere the new societies of reform
were circulating the book, and if it helped to send
some good men to Botany Bay, copies enough were sold
to earn a sum of a thousand pounds for the author,
which, with his usual disinterestedness, he promptly
gave to the Corresponding Society. A second part
appeared in 1792; and at length Pitt adopted Burke’s
opinion that criminal justice was the proper argument
with which to refute Tom Paine. Acting on a hint
from William Blake, who, in a vision more prosaic and
veridical than was usual with him, had seen the constables
searching for his friend, Paine escaped to France,
and was convicted in his absence of high treason.
Paine landed at Calais an outlaw,
to find himself already elected its deputy to the
Convention. As in America, so in France, his was
the first voice to urge the uncompromising solution.
He advocated the abolition of the monarchy; but his
was a courage that always served humanity. The
work which he did as a member, with Sieyes, Danton,
Condorcet, and five others, of the little committee
named to draft the constitution, was ephemeral.
His brave pleading for the King’s life was a
deed that deserves to live. He loved to think
of himself as a woodman swinging an axe against rotten
institutions and dying beliefs; but he weighted no
guillotines. Paine argued against the command
that we should “love our enemies,” but
he would not persecute them. This knight-errant
would fling his shield over the very spies who tracked
his steps. In Paris he saved the life of one
of Pitt’s agents who had vilified him, and procured
the liberation of a bullying English officer who had
struck him in public. The Terror made mercy a
traitor, and Paine found himself overwhelmed in the
vengeance which overtook all that was noblest in the
Revolution. He spent ten months in prison, racked
with fever, and an anecdote which seems to be authentic,
tells how he escaped death by the negligence of a
jailor. This overworked official hastily chalked
the sign which meant that a prisoner was marked for
next batch of the guillotine’s victims, on the
inside instead of the outside of Paine’s cell-door.
Condorcet, in hiding and awaiting
death, wrote in these months his Sketch of
human progress. Paine, meditating on the end that
seemed near, composed the first part of his Age
of Reason. Paine was, like Franklin, Jefferson
and Washington, a deist; and he differed from them
only in the courage which prompted him to declare his
belief. He came from gaol a broken man, hardly
able to stand, while the Convention, returned to its
sound senses, welcomed him back to his place of honour
on its benches. The record of his last years in
America, whither he returned in 1802, belongs rather
to the history of persecution than to the biography
of a soldier of liberty. His work was done; and,
though his pen was still active and influential, slave-owners,
ex-royalists, and the fanatics of orthodoxy combined
to embitter the end of the man who had dared to deny
the inspiration of the Bible. His book was burned
in England by the hangman. Bishops in their answers
mingled grudging concessions with personal abuse.
An agent of Pitt’s was hired to write a scurrilous
biography of the Government’s most dreaded foe.
In America, the grandsons of the Puritan colonists
who had flogged Quaker women as witches, denied him
a place on the stage-coach, lest an offended God should
strike it with lightning.
Paine died, a lonely old man, in 1809.
His personal character stands written in his career;
and it is unnecessary to-day even to mention the libels
which his biographer has finally refuted. In a
generation of brave men he was the boldest. He
could rouse the passions of men, and he could brave
them. If the Royalist Burke was eloquent for a
Queen, Republican Paine risked his life for a King.
No wrong found him indifferent; and he used his pen
not only for the democracy which might reward him,
but for animals, slaves and women. Poverty never
left him, yet he made fortunes with his pen, and gave
them to the cause he served. A naïve vanity was
his only fault as a man. It was his fate to escape
the gallows in England and the guillotine in France.
He deserved them both; in that age there was no higher
praise. A better democrat never wore the armour
of the knight-errant; a better Christian never assailed
Orthodoxy.
Neither by training nor by temperament
was Paine a speculative thinker; but his political
writing has none the less an immense significance.
Godwin was a writer removed by his profoundly individual
genius from the average thought of his day. Paine
agreed more nearly with the advanced minds of his
generation, and he taught the rest to agree with him.
No one since him or before him has stated the plain
democratic case against monarchy and aristocracy with
half his spirit and force. Earlier writers on
these themes were timid; the moderns are bored.
Paine is writing of what he understands, and feels
to be of the first importance. He cares as much
about abolishing titles as a modern reformer may feel
about nationalising land. His main theory in
politics has a lucid simplicity. Men are born
as God created them, free and equal; that is the assumption
alike of natural and revealed religion. Burke,
who “fears God,” looks with “awe
to kings,” with “duty to magistrates,”
and with “respect to nobility,” is but
erecting a wilderness of turnpike gates between man
and his Maker. Natural rights inhere in man by
reason of his existence; civil rights are founded
in natural rights and are designed to secure and guarantee
them. He gives an individual twist to the doctrine
of the social compact. Some governments arise
out of the people, others over the people. The
latter are based on conquest or priestcraft, and the
former on reason. Government will be firmly based
on the social compact only when nations deliberately
sit down as the Americans have done, and the French
are doing, to frame a constitution on the basis of
the Rights of Man.
As for the English Government, it
clearly arose in conquest; and to speak of a British
Constitution is playing with words. Parliament,
imperfectly and capriciously elected, is supposed to
hold the common purse in trust; but the men who vote
the supplies are also those who receive them.
The national purse is the common hack on which each
party mounts in turn, in the countryman’s fashion
of “ride and tie.” They order these
things better in France. As for our system of
conducting wars, it is all done over the heads of
the people. War is with us the art of conquering
at home. Taxes are not raised to carry on wars,
but wars raised to carry on taxes. The shrewd
hard-hitting blows range over the whole surface of
existing institutions. Godwin from his intellectual
eminence saw in all the follies and crimes of mankind
nothing worse than the effects of “prejudice”
and the consequences of fallacious reasoning.
Paine saw more self-interest in the world than prejudice.
When he came to preach the abolition of war, first
through an alliance of Britain, America and France,
and then through “a confederation of nations”
and a European Congress, he saw the obstacle in the
egoism of courts and courtiers which appear to quarrel
but agree to plunder. Another seven years, he
wrote in 1792, would see the end of monarchy and aristocracy
in Europe. While they continue, with war as their
trade, peace has not the security of a day.
Paine’s writing gains rather
than loses in theoretic interest, because the warmth
of his sympathies melts, as he proceeds, the icy logic
of his eighteenth century individualism. He starts
where all his school started, with a sharp antithesis
between society and government.
“Society is produced by our
wants and government by our wickedness; the former
promotes our happiness positively by uniting our affections;
the latter negatively by restraining our vices.
The one encourages intercourse, the other creates
distinctions. The first is a patron, the last
a punisher. Society in every state is a blessing;
but government even in its best state is a necessary
evil.... Government, like dress, is the badge
of our lost innocence; the palaces of kings are built
on the ruins of the bowers of paradise.”
That was the familiar pessimism which
led in practical politics to laissez faire,
and in speculation to Godwin’s philosophic anarchism.
Paine himself seems for a moment to take that road.
He enjoys telling us how well the American colonies
managed in the early stages of the war without any
regular form of government. He assures us that
“the more perfect civilisation is, the less
occasion has it for government.” But he
had served an apprenticeship to life; looking around
him at the streets filled with beggars and the jails
crowded with poor men, he suddenly forgets that the
whole purpose of government is to secure the individual
against the invasion of his rights, and straightway
bursts into a new definition: “Civil
government does not consist in executions; but in
making such provision for the instruction of youth
and the support of age as to exclude as much as possible
profligacy from the one and despair from the other.
Instead of this the resources of a country are lavished
upon kings ... and the poor themselves are compelled
to support the fraud that oppresses them.”
It is amazing how much good Paine
can extract from a necessary evil. He has suddenly
conceived of government as the instrument of the social
conscience. He means to use it as a means of securing
a better organisation of society. Paine was a
man of action, and no mere logic could hold him.
He proceeds in a breathless chapter to evolve a programme
of social reform which, after the slumbers of a century,
his Radical successors have just begun to realise.
Some hints came to him from Condorcet, but most of
these daringly novel ideas sprang from Paine’s
own inventive brain, and all of them are presented
by the whilom exciseman, with a wealth of financial
detail, as if he were a Chancellor of the Exchequer
addressing the first Republican Parliament in the
year One of Liberty. He would break up the poor
laws, “these instruments of civil torture.”
He has saved the major part of the cost of defence
by a naval alliance with the other Sea Powers, and
the abolition of capture at sea. Instead of poor
relief he would give a subsidy to the children of
the very poor, and pensions to the aged. Four
pounds a year for every child under fourteen in every
necessitous family will ensure the health and instruction
of the next generation. It will cost two millions
and a half, but it will banish ignorance. He would
pay the costs of compulsory education. Pensions
are to be granted not of grace but of right, as an
aid to the infirm after fifty years, and a subsidy
to the aged after sixty. Maternity benefit is
anticipated in a donation of twenty shillings to every
poor mother at the birth of a child. Casual labour
is to be cared for in some sort of workhouse-factories
in London. These reforms are to be financed partly
by economies and partly by a graduated income-tax,
for which Paine presents an elaborate schedule.
When the poor are happy and the jails empty, then
at last may a nation boast of its constitution.
In this pregnant chapter Paine not only sketched the
work of the future; he exploded his own premises.
The odium that still clings to Paine’s
theological writings comes mainly from those who have
not read them. When Mr. Roosevelt the other day
called him “a dirty little Atheist,” he
exposed nothing but his own ignorance. Paine
was a deist, and he wrote The Age of Reason
on the threshold of a French prison, primarily to
counteract the atheism which he thought he saw at
work among the Jacobins an odd diagnosis,
for Robespierre was at least as ardent in his deism
as Paine himself. He believed in a God, Whose
bounty he saw in nature; he taught the doctrine of
conditional immortality, and his quarrel with revealed
religion was chiefly that it set up for worship a
God of cruelty and injustice. From the stories
of the Jewish massacres ordained by divine command,
down to the orthodox doctrine of the scheme of redemption,
he saw nothing but a history derogatory to the wisdom
and goodness of the Almighty. To believe the
Old Testament we must unbelieve our faith in the moral
justice of God. It might “hurt the stubbornness
of a priest” to destroy this fiction, but it
would tranquilise the consciences of millions.
From this starting-point he proceeds in the later
second and third parts to a detailed criticism designed
to show that the books of the Bible were not written
by their reputed authors, that the miracles are incredible,
that the passages claimed as prophecy have been wrested
from their contexts, and that many inconsistencies
are to be found in the narrative portions of the Gospels.
Acute and fearless though it is, this
detailed argument has only an historical interest
to-day. When the violence of his persecutors had
goaded Paine into anger, he lost all sense of tact
in controversy, and lapsed occasionally into harsh
vulgarities. But the anger was just, and the
zeal for mental honesty has had its reward. Paine
had no sense for the mystery and poetry of traditional
religion. But what he attacked was not presented
to him as poetry. He was assailing a dogmatic
orthodoxy which had itself converted poetry into literal
fact. As literal fact it was incredible; and
Paine, taking it all at the valuation of its own professors,
assailed it with a disbelief as prosaic as their belief,
but intellectually more honest. His interpretation
of the Bible is unscientific, if you will, but it
is nearer to the truth of history than the conventional
belief of his day. If his polemics seem rough
and superfluous to us, it is only because his direct
frontal attacks forced on the work of Biblical criticism,
and long ago compelled the abandonment of most of
the positions which he assailed. In spite of its
grave faults of taste and temper and manner, The
Age of Reason performed an indispensable service
to honesty and morals. It was the bravest thing
he did, for it threatened his name with an immortality
of libel. His place in history is secure at last.
The neglected pioneer of one revolution, the honoured
victim of another, brave to the point of folly, and
as humane as he was brave, no man in his generation
preached republican virtue in better English, nor
lived it with a finer disregard of self.