The controversy which produced Political
Justice was a dialogue between the future and
the past. The task of speculation in England had
been, through a stagnant century, to define the conditions
of political stability, and to admire the elaborate
checks and balances of the British Constitution as
though change were the only evil that threatened mankind.
For Burke, change itself was but an incident in the
triumph of continuity and conservation. For Godwin
the whole life of mankind is a race through innovation
to perfection, and his main concern is to exhort the
athlete to fling aside the garments of prejudice, tradition,
and constraint, until one asks at the end how much
of flesh and blood has been torn away with the garments.
If one were to attempt in a phrase to sum up his work,
the best title which one could invent for it would
be Prolegomena to all Future Progress. What in
a word are the conditions of progress?
His attitude to mankind is by turns
a pedagogue’s disapprobation and a patron’s
encouragement. The worst enemy of progress was
the systematic optimism of Leibnitz and Pope, which
Voltaire had overthrown. There is indeed enough
of progress in the past to fire our courage and our
hopes. In moments of depression, he would admire
the beautiful invention of writing and the power of
mind displayed in human speech. But the general
panorama of history exhorts us to fundamental change.
In bold sweeping rhetoric he assures us that history
is little else than the record of crime. War
has diminished neither its horror nor its frequency,
and man is still the most formidable enemy to man.
Despotism is still the fate of the greatest part of
mankind. Penal laws by the terror of punishment
hold a numerous class in abject penury. Robbery
and fraud are none the less continual, and the poor
are tempted for ever to violence against the more
fortunate. One person in seven comes in England
on the poor rates. Can the poor conceive of society
as a combination to protect every man in his rights
and secure him the means of existence? Is it not
rather for them a conspiracy to engross its advantages
for the favoured few? Luxury insults them; admiration
is the exclusive property of the rich, and contempt
the constant lacquey of poverty. Nowhere is a
man valued for what he is. Legislation aggravates
the natural inequality of man. A house of landlords
sets to work to deprive the poor of the little commonage
of nature which remained to them, and its bias stands
revealed when we recollect that in England (as Paine
had pointed out) while taxes on land produce half
a million less than they did a century ago, taxes
on articles of general consumption produce thirteen
millions more. Robbery is a capital offence because
the poor alone are tempted to it. Among the poor
alone is all combination forbidden. Godwin was
often an incautious rhetorician. He painted the
present in colours of such unrelieved gloom, that
it is hard to see in it the possibility of a brighter
future. Mankind seems hopeless, and he has to
prove it perfectible.
Are these evils then the necessary
condition of society? Godwin answers that question
as the French school, and in particular Helvetius,
had done, by a preliminary assault on the assumptions
of a reactionary philosophy. He proposes to exhort
the human will to embark with a conscious and social
resolve on the adventure of perfection. He must
first demonstrate that the will is sovereign.
Man is the creature of necessity, and the nexus of
cause and effect governs the moral world like the
physical. We are the product of our conditions.
But among conditions some are within the power of
the will to change and others are not. Montesquieu
had insisted that it is climate which ultimately differentiates
the races of mankind. Climate is clearly a despotism
which we can never hope to reform away. Another
school has taught that men come into the world with
innate ideas and a predetermined character. Others
again would dispute that man is in his actions a reasonable
being, and would represent him as the toy of passion,
a creature to whom it is useless to present an argument
drawn from his own advantage. The first task
of the progressive philosopher is to clear away these
preliminary obstacles. Man is the creature of
conditions, but primarily of those conditions which
he may hope to modify education, religion,
social prejudice and above all government. He
is also in the last resort a being whose conduct is
governed by his opinions. Admit these premises
and the way is clear towards perfection. It is
a problem which in some form and in some dialect confronts
every generation of reformers. We are the creatures
of our own environment, but in some degree we are
ourselves a force which can modify that environment.
We inherit a past which weighs upon us and obsesses
us, but in some degree each generation is born anew.
Godwin used the new psychology against the old superstition
of innate ideas. A modern thinker in his place
would advance Weissmann’s biological theory
that the acquired modifications of an organism are
not inherited, as an answer to the pessimism which
bases itself upon heredity.
Godwin starts boldly with the thesis
that “the characters of men originate in their
external circumstances.” He brushes aside
innate ideas or instincts or even ante-natal impressions.
Accidents in the womb may have a certain effect, and
every man has a certain disposition at birth.
But the multiplicity of later experiences wears out
these early impressions. Godwin, in all this,
reproduces the current fallacy of his generation.
Impressions and experiences were for them something
external, flung upon the surface of the mind.
They were just beginning to realise that the mind
works when it perceives. Change a nobleman’s
child at birth with a ploughman’s, and each will
grow up quite naturally in his new circumstances.
Exercise makes the muscles; education, argument, and
the exchange of opinion the mind. “It is
impression that makes the man, and compared with the
empire of impression, the mere differences of animal
structure are inexpressibly unimportant and powerless.”
Change continues through life; everything mental and
physical is in flux; why suppose that only in the propensities
of the new-born infant is there something permanent
and inflexible? Helvetius had been Godwin’s
chief precursor in this opinion. He had gone so
far as to declare that men are at birth equal, some
raw human stuff which “education,” in
the broad sense of the word, proceeds to modify in
the long schooling from the cradle to the grave.
Men differ in genius, he would assert, by education
and experience, not by natural organisation.
The original acuteness of the senses has little to
do with the development of talent. The new psychology
had swept “faculties” away. Interest
is the main factor in the development of perception
and attention. The scarcity of attention is the
true cause of the scarcity of genius, and the chief
means of promoting it are emulation and the love of
glory.
Godwin is too cautious to accept this
ultra-revolutionary statement of the potential equality
of men without some reserves. But the idea inspires
him as it inspired all the vital thought of his day.
It set humane physicians at the height of the Terror
to work on discovering a method by which even defective
and idiot children might be raised by “education”
to the normal stature of the human mind. It fired
Godwin himself with a zeal for education. “Folly,”
said Helvetius, “is factitious.”
“Nature,” said Godwin, “never made
a dunce.” The failures of education are
due primarily to the teacher’s error in substituting
compulsion for persuasion and despotism for encouragement.
The excellences and defects of the human character
are not due to occult causes beyond the reach of ingenuity
to modify or correct, nor are false views the offspring
of an irresistible destiny. Our conventional schools
are the slaughterhouses of mind; but of all the external
influences which build up character and opinion, the
chief are political. It is Godwin’s favourite
theme, and he carries it even further than Holbach
and Helvetius had done. From this influence there
is no escape, for it infects the teacher no less than
the taught. Equality will make men frank, ingenuous
and intrepid, but a great disparity of ranks renders
men cold, irresolute, timid and cautious. However
lofty the morality of the teacher, the mind of the
child is continually corrupted by seeing, in the society
around him, wealth honoured, poverty contemned, intrepid
virtue proscribed and servility encouraged. From
the influence of social and political institutions
there is no escape: “They poison our minds
before we can resist or so much as suspect their malignity.
Like the barbarous directors of Eastern seraglios
they deprive us of our virility, and fit us for their
despicable employment from the cradle. So false
is the opinion that has too generally prevailed that
politics is an affair with which ordinary men have
little concern.”
Here Godwin is introducing into English
thinking an idea originally French. English writers
from Locke to Paine had spoken of government as something
purely negative, so little important that only when
a man saw his property threatened or his shores invaded,
was he forced to recollect that he had a country.
Godwin saw its influence everywhere, insinuating itself
into our personal dispositions and insensibly communicating
its spirit to our private transactions. The idea
in his hands made for hope. Reform, or better
still, abolish governments, and to what heights of
virtue might not men aspire? We need not say with
Rousseau that men are naturally virtuous. The
child, as Helvetius delighted to point out, will do
that for a coral or a doll which he will do at a mature
age for a title or a sceptre. Men are rather the
infinitely malleable, variable stuff on which education
and persuasion can play.
The first essential dogma of perfectibility,
the first presupposition of progress is, then, that
men’s characters depend on external circumstances.
The second dogma, the second condition of hope is that
the voluntary actions of men originate in their opinions.
It is an orthodox Socratic position, but Godwin was
not a student of Plato. He laid down this dogma
as the necessary basis of any reform by persuasion.
There is much virtue in the word “voluntary.”
In so far as actions are voluntary, the doctrine is
self-evident. A voluntary action is accompanied
by foresight, and the idea of certain consequences
is its motive. A judgment “this is good”
or “this is desirable,” has preceded the
action, and it originates therefore in an opinion however
fugitive. In moments of passion my attention
is so engrossed by a particular view of the subject
that I forget considerations by which I am commonly
guided. Even in battles between reason and sense,
he holds, the contending forces assume a rational
form. It is opinion contending with opinion and
judgment with judgment. At this point the modern
reader will become sceptical. These internal
struggles assume a rational form only when self-consciousness
reviews them that is to say when they are
over. In point of fact, Godwin argues, sheer
sensuality has a smaller empire over us than we commonly
suppose. Strip the feast of its social pleasures,
and the commerce of the sexes of all its intellectual
and emotional allurements, and who would be overcome?
One need not follow Godwin minutely
in his handling of what is after all a commonplace
of academic philosophy. He was concerned to insist
that men’s voluntary actions originate in opinion,
that he might secure a fulcrum for the leverage of
argument and persuasion. Vice is error, and error
can always be corrected. “Show me in the
clearest and most unambiguous manner that a certain
mode of proceeding is most reasonable in itself, or
most conducive to my interest, and I shall infallibly
pursue that mode, so long as the views you suggested
to me continue present to my mind.” The
practical problem is therefore to make ourselves and
our fellows perfectly conscious of our motives, and
always prepared to render a reason for our actions.
The perfection of human character is to approach as
nearly as possible to the absolutely voluntary state,
to act always, in other words, from a clear and comprehensive
survey of the consequences which we desire to produce.
The incautious reader may be invited
to pause at this point, for in this premise lies already
the whole of philosophic anarchism. You have
admitted that voluntary action is rational. You
have conceded that all action ought to be voluntary.
The silent assumption is that by education and effort
it can be made so. One may doubt whether
in the sense required by Godwin’s argument any
human action ever is or can be absolutely “voluntary,”
rational or self-conscious. To attain it, we
should have to reason naked in a desert with algebraic
symbols. To use words is to think in step, and
to beg our question. But Godwin is well aware
that most men rarely reason. He is here framing
an ideal, without realising its remoteness. The
mischief of his faith in logic as a force, was that
it led him to ignore the aesthetic and emotional influences,
by which the mass of men can best be led to a virtuous
ideal. Shelley, who was a thorough Platonist,
supplements, as we shall see , this characteristic
defect in his master’s teaching. The main
conclusions follow rapidly. Sound reasoning and
truth when adequately communicated must always be
victorious over error. Truth, then, is omnipotent,
and the vices and moral weaknesses of man are not
invincible. Man, in short, is perfectible, or
in other words, susceptible of perpetual improvement.
These sentiments have to the modern ear a platitudinous
ring. So far from being platitudes, they are
explosives capable of destroying the whole fabric
of government. For if truth is omnipotent, why
trust to laws? If men will obey argument, why
use constraint?
But let us move slowly towards this
extreme conclusion. If reason appears to-day
to play but a feeble part in society, and exerts only
a limited empire over the actions of men, it is because
unlettered ignorance, social habits and the positive
institutions of government stand in the way.
Where the masses of mankind are sunk in brutal ignorance,
one need not wonder that argument and persuasion have
but a small influence with them. Truth indeed
is rarely recondite or difficult to communicate.
Godwin might have quoted Helvetius: “It
is with genius as with an astronomer; he sees a new
star and forthwith all can see it.” Nor
need we fear the objection that by introducing an intellectual
element into virtue, we have removed it beyond the
reach of simple men. A virtuous action, indeed,
must be good both in intention and in tendency.
Godwin was like Helvetius and Priestley, a Utilitarian
in ethics, and defined duty as that mode of action
on the part of the individual which constitutes the
best possible application of his capacity to the general
benefit, in every situation that presents itself.
One may be mistaken as to what will contribute to the
general benefit, as Sir Everard Digby was, for example,
when he thought it his duty to blow up King James
and the Parliament. But the simple man need be
at no loss. An earnest desire will in some degree
generate capacity. There Godwin opened a profoundly
interesting and stimulating line of thought.
The mind is formed not by its innate powers, but by
its governing desires. As love brings eloquence
to the suitor, so if I do but ardently desire to serve
my kind, I shall find out a way, and while I study
a plan shall find that my faculties have been exercised
and increased. Moreover, in the struggle after
virtue I am not alone.
Burke made the first of the virtues
prudence. Godwin would have given sincerity that
place. To him and his circle the chief business
of social converse was by argument and exhortation
to strengthen the habit of virtue. There was
something to be said for the practice of auricular
confession; but how much better would it be if every
man were to make the world his confessional and the
human species the keeper of his conscience. The
practice of sincerity would give to our conversation
a Roman boldness and fervour. The frank distribution
of praise and blame is the most potent incentive to
virtue. Were we but bold and impartial in our
judgments, vice would be universally deserted and virtue
everywhere practised. Our cowardice in censure
and correction is the chief reason of the perpetuation
of abuses. If every man would tell all the truth
he knew, it is impossible to predict how short would
be the reign of usurpation and folly. Let our
motive be philanthropy, and we need not fear ruggedness
or brutality, disdain or superiority, since we aim
at the interest of him we correct, and not at the triumph
of the corrector. In an aside Godwin demands
the abolition of social conventions which offend sincerity.
If I must deny myself to a visitor, I should scorn
the polite lie that I am “not at home.”
It is a consequence also of this doctrine,
that there should be no prosecutions for libel, even
in private matters. Truth depends on the free
shock of opinions, and the unrestrained discussion
of private character is almost as important as freedom
in speculative enquiry. “If the truth were
universally told of men’s dispositions and actions,
gibbets and wheels might be dismissed from the face
of the earth. The knave unmasked would be obliged
to turn honest in his own defence. Nay, no man
would have time to turn a knave. Truth would follow
him in his first irresolute essays, and public disapprobation
arrest him in the commencement of his career.”
It is shameful for a good man to retort on a slander,
“I will have recourse to the only means that
are congenial to guilt: I will compel you to
be silent.” Freedom in this matter, as in
all others, will engender activity and fortitude; positive
institution (Godwin’s term for law and constraint)
makes the mind torpid and lethargic. It is hardly
necessary to reproduce Godwin’s vigorous arguments
for unfettered freedom in political and speculative
discussion, against censorships and prosecutions for
religious and political opinions. Even were we
secure from the possibility of mistake, mischief and
not good would accrue from the attempt to impose our
infallible opinions upon our neighbours. Men deserve
approbation only in so far as they are independent
in their opinions and free in their actions.
Equally clear is it that the establishment
of religion and all systems of tests must be abolished.
They make for hypocrisy, check advance in speculation,
and teach us to estimate a disinterested sincerity
at a cheap rate. We need not fear disorder as
a consequence of complete liberty of speech.
“Arguments alone will not have the power, unassisted
by the sense or the recollection of oppression or treachery
to hurry the people into excesses. Excesses are
never the offspring of speculative reason, are never
the offspring of misrepresentation only, but of power
endeavouring to stifle reason, and to traverse the
commonsense of mankind.”
A more original deduction from Godwin’s
demand for the unlimited freedom of opinion, was that
he objected vehemently to any system of national education.
Condorcet had drawn up a marvellously complete project
for universal compulsory education, with full liberty
indeed for the teachers, whose technical competence
alone the State would guarantee, and with a scheme
of free scholarships, an educational “ladder”
more generous than anything which has yet been realised
in fact. Godwin objects that State-regulated
institutions will stereotype knowledge and make for
an undesirable permanence and uniformity in opinion.
They diffuse what is known and forget what remains
to be known. They erect a system of authority
and separate a tenet from the evidence on which it
rests, so that beliefs cease to be perceptions and
become prejudices. No Government is to be trusted
with the dangerous power to create and regulate opinions
through its schools. Such a power is, indeed,
more dangerous than that of an Established Church,
and would be used to strengthen tyranny and perpetuate
faulty institutions.
Godwin, needless to say, takes, as
did Condorcet, the side of frankness in the controversy
which was a test of democratic faith in this generation whether
“political imposture” is allowable, and
whether a statesman should encourage the diffusion
of “salutary prejudices” among the unlearned,
the poor and women. This was indeed the main eighteenth
century defence for monarchy and aristocracy.
Kings and governors are not wiser than other men,
but it is useful that they should be thought so.
Such imposture, Godwin argued, is as futile as the
parallel use by religion of the pains and penalties
of the afterworld. It is the sober who are demoralised
by it, and not the lawless who are deterred. To
terrify men is a strange way of rendering them judicious,
fearless and happy. It is to leave men indolent
and unbraced by truth. He objects even to the
trappings and ceremonies which are used to render
magistrates outwardly venerable and awe-inspiring,
so that they may impress the irrational imagination.
These means may be used as easily to support injustice
as to render justice acceptable. They divide men
into two classes; those who may reason, and those
who must take everything on trust. This is to
degrade them both. The masses are kept in perpetual
vibration between rebellious discontent and infatuated
credulity. And can we suppose that the practice
of concealment and hypocrisy will make no breaches
in the character of the governing class?
The general effect of any meddling
of authority with opinion is that the mind is robbed
of its genuine employment. Such a system produces
beings wanting in independence, and in that intrepid
perseverance and calm self-approbation which grow
from independence. Such beings are the mere dwarfs
and mockeries of men.
Godwin was at issue here as much with
Rousseau as with Burke, but his trust in the people,
it should be explained, was based rather on faith
in what they might become, than on admiration for what
they were.
That all government is an evil, though
doubtless a necessary evil, was the typical opinion
of the individualistic eighteenth century. It
would not long have survived such proposals as Paine’s
scheme of old age pensions and Condorcet’s project
of national education. When men have perceived
that an evil can be turned to good account, they are
already on the road which will lead them to discard
their premises. But Godwin was quite unaffected
by this new Liberalism. No positive good was to
be hoped from government, and much positive evil would
flow from it at the best. In his absolute individualism
he went further. The whole idea of government
was radically wrong. For him the individual was
tightly enclosed in his own skin, and any constraint
was an infringement of his personality. He would
have poured scorn on the half-mystical conception
of a social organism. Nor did it occur to him
that a man might voluntarily subject himself to government,
losing none of his own autonomy in the act, from a
persuasion that government is on the whole a benefit,
and that submission, even when his own views are thwarted,
is a free man’s duty within certain limits,
accepted gladly for the sake of preserving an institution
which commonly works well. He did not see the
institution working well; he did not believe in the
benefits; he was convinced that more than all the
advantages of the best of governments could be obtained
from the free operation of opinion in an unorganised
community.
His main point is lucidly simple.
It was an application of the Whig and Protestant doctrine
of the right of private judgment. “If in
any instance I am made the mechanical instrument of
absolute violence, in that instance I fall under a
pure state of external slavery.” Nor is
the case much better, if instead of waiting for the
actual application of coercion, I act in obedience
to authority from the hope and fear of the State’s
rewards and punishments. For virtue has ceased,
and I am acting from self-interest. It is a triviality
to distinguish, as Whig thinkers do, between matters
of conscience (in which the State should not meddle)
and my conduct in the civil concerns of daily life
(which the State should regulate). What sort
of moralist can he be, who makes no conscience of
what he does in his daily intercourse with other men?
“I have deeply reflected upon the nature of
virtue, and am convinced that a certain proceeding
is incumbent on me. But the hangman supported
by an Act of Parliament assures me that I am mistaken.
If I yield my opinion to his dictum, my action becomes
modified, and my character also.... Countries
exposed to the perpetual interference of decrees instead
of arguments, exhibit within their boundaries the
mere phantoms of men.”
The root of the whole matter is that
brute force is an offence against reason, and an unnecessary
offence, if in fact men are guided by opinion and
will yield to argument. “The case of punishment
is the case of you and me differing in opinion, and
your telling me that you must be right since you have
a more brawny arm.”
If I must obey, it is better and less
demoralising to yield an external submission so as
to escape penalty or constraint, than to yield to
authority from a general confidence which enslaves
the mind. Comply but criticise. Obey but
beware of reverence. If I surrender my conscience
to another man’s keeping, I annihilate my individuality
as a man, and become the ready tool of him among my
neighbours who shall excel in imposture and artifice.
I put an end moreover to the happy collision of understandings
upon which the hopes of human improvement depend.
Governments depend upon the unlimited confidence of
their subjects, and confidence rests upon ignorance.
Government (has not Burke said so?)
is the perpetual enemy of change, and prompts us to
seek the public welfare not in alteration and improvement,
but in a timid reverence for the decisions of our
ancestors, as if it were the nature of the human mind
always to degenerate and never to advance. Godwin
thought with John Bright, “We stand on the shoulders
of our forefathers and see further.”
In proportion as weakness and ignorance
shall diminish, the basis of government will also
decay. That will be its true euthanasia.
There is indeed nothing to be said
for government save that for a time, and within jealously
drawn limits, it may be a fatal and indispensable
necessity. A just government cannot be founded
on force: for force has no affinity with justice.
It cannot be based upon the will of God; we have no
revelation that recommends one form of government rather
than another. As little can it be based upon
contract. Who were the parties to the pretended
social contract? For whom did they consent, for
themselves or for their descendants, and to how great
a variety of propositions? Have I assented or
my ancestors for me, to the laws of England in fifty
volumes folio, and to all that shall hereafter be added
to them? In a few contemptuous pages Godwin buries
the social contract. Men when they digest the
articles of a contract are not empowered to create
rights, but only to declare what was previously right.
But the doctrine of the natural rights of man fares
no better at his hands. There is no such thing
as a positive right to do as we list. One way
of acting in every emergency is reasonable, and the
other is not. One way will benefit mankind, and
the other will not. It is a pestilent doctrine
and a denial of all virtue, to say that we have a right
to do what we will with our own. Everything we
possess has a destination prescribed to it by the
immutable voice of reason and justice.
Duties and rights are correlative.
As it cannot be the duty of men or societies to do
anything to the detriment of human happiness, so it
appears with equal evidence that they cannot have the
right to do so. There cannot be a more absurd
proposition than that which affirms the right of doing
wrong. The voice of the people is not the voice
of God, nor does universal consent or a majority vote
convert wrong into right. It is absurd to say
that any set of people has a right to set up any form
of government it chooses, or any sect to establish
any superstition however detestable. All this
would have delighted Burke, but Godwin stands firmly
in his path by asserting what he calls the one negative
right of man. It is in a word, the right to exercise
virtue, the right to a region of choice, a sphere
of discretion, which his neighbours must not infringe
save by censure and remonstrance. When I am constrained,
I cease to be a person, and become a thing. “I
ought to exercise my talents for the benefit of others,
but the exercise must be the fruit of my own conviction;
no man must attempt to press me into the service.”
Government is an evil, and the business
of human advancement is to dispense with it as rapidly
as may be. In the period of transition Godwin
had but a secondary interest, and his sketch of it
is slight. He dismisses in turn despotism, aristocracy,
the “mixed monarchy” of the Whigs, and
the president with kingly powers of some American thinkers.
His pages on these subjects are vigorous, well-reasoned,
and pointed in their satire. It required much
courage to write them, but they do not contain his
original contribution to political theory. What
is most characteristic in his line of argument is
his insistence on the moral corruption that monarchy
and aristocracy involve. The whole standard of
moral values is subverted. To achieve ostentation
becomes the first object of desire. Disinterested
virtue is first suspected and then viewed with incredulity.
Luxury meanwhile distorts our whole attitude to our
fellows, and in every effort to excel and shine we
wrong the labouring millions. Aristocracy involves
general degradation, and can survive only amid general
ignorance. “To make men serfs and villeins
it is indispensably necessary to make them brutes....
A servant who has been taught to write and read, ceases
to be any longer a passive machine.”
From the abolition of monarchy and
aristocracy Godwin, and indeed the whole revolutionary
school, expected the cessation of war. War and
conquest elevate the few at the expense of the rest,
and cannot benefit the whole community. Democracies
have no business with war save to repel an invasion
of their territory. He thought of patriotism and
love of country much as did Dr. Price. They are
(as Hervé has argued in our own day) specious illusions
invented to render the multitude the blind instruments
of crooked designs. We must not be lured into
pursuing the general wealth, prosperity or glory of
the society to which we belong. Society is an
abstraction, an “ideal existence,” and
is not on its own account entitled to the smallest
regard. Let us not be led away into rendering
services to society for which no individual man is
the better. Godwin is scornful of wars to maintain
the balance of power, or to protect our fellow-countrymen
abroad. Some proportion must be observed between
the evil of which we complain and the evil which the
proposed remedy inevitably includes. War may
be defensible in support of the liberty of an oppressed
people, but let us wait (here he is clearly censuring
the practice of the French Republic) until the oppressed
people rises. Do not interfere to force it to
be free, and do not forget the resources of pacific
persuasion. As to foreign possessions there is
little to be said. Do without them. Let colonies
attend to their own defence; no State would wish to
have colonies if free trade were universal. Liberty
is equally good for every race of men, and democracy,
since it is founded on reason, a universal form of
government. There follow some naïve prescriptions
for conducting democratic wars. Sincerity forbids
ambuscades and secresy. Never invade, nor assume
the offensive. A citizen militia must replace
standing armies. Training and discipline are
of little value; the ardour of a free people will supply
their place.
Godwin’s leading idea when he
comes to sketch a shadowy constitution is an extreme
dislike of overgrown national States. Political
speculation in his day idealised the city republic
of antiquity. Helvetius, hoping to get rid as
far as possible of government, had advocated a system
of federated commonwealths, each so small that public
opinion and the fear of shame would act powerfully
within it. He would have divided France into
thirty republics, each returning four deputies to a
federal council. The Girondins cherished the
same idea, and lost their heads for it. Tolstoy,
going back to the village community as the only possible
scene of a natural and virtuous life, exhibits the
same tendency.
For Godwin the true unit of society
is the parish. Neighbours best understand each
others’ concerns, and in a limited area there
is no room for ambition to unfold itself. Great
talents will have their sphere outside this little
circle in the work of moulding opinion. Within
the parish public opinion is supreme, and acts through
juries, which may at first be obliged to exert some
degree of violence in dealing with offenders: “But
this necessity does not arise out of the nature of
man, but out of the institutions by which he has already
been corrupted. Man is not originally vicious.
He would not ... refuse to be convinced by the expostulations
that are addressed to him, had he not been accustomed
to regard them as hypocritical, and to conceive that
while his neighbour, his parent and his political
governor pretended to be actuated by a pure regard
to his interest or pleasure, they were in reality,
at the expense of his, promoting their own....
Render the plain dictates of justice level to every
capacity ... and the whole species will become reasonable
and virtuous. It will then be sufficient for
juries to recommend a certain mode of adjusting controversies,
without assuming the prerogative of dictating that
adjustment. It will then be sufficient for them
to invite offenders to forsake their errors....
Where the empire of reason was so universally acknowledged,
the offender would either readily yield to the expostulations
of authority, or if he resisted, though suffering
no personal molestation, he would feel so weary under
the unequivocal disapprobation and the observant eye
of public judgment as willingly to remove to a society
more congenial to his errors.” The picture
is not so Utopian as it sounds. It is a very
fair sketch of the social structure of a Macedonian
village community under Turkish rule, with the massacres
left out.
For the rest Godwin was reluctantly
prepared to admit the wisdom of instituting a single
chamber National Assembly, to manage the common affairs
of the parishes, to arrange their disputes and to provide
for national defence. But it should suffice for
it to meet for one day annually or thereabouts.
Like the juries it would at first issue commands,
but would in time find it sufficient to publish invitations
backed by arguments. Godwin, who is quite prepared
to idealise his district juries, pours forth an unstinted
contempt upon Parliaments and their procedure.
They make a show of unanimity where none exists.
The prospect of a vote destroys the intellectual value
of debate; the will of one man really dominates, and
the existence of party frustrates persuasion.
The whole is based upon “that intolerable insult
upon all reason and justice, the deciding upon truth
by the casting up of numbers.” He omits
to tell us whether he would allow his juries to vote.
Fortunately legislation is unnecessary: “The
inhabitants of a small parish living with some degree
of that simplicity which best corresponds with the
real nature and wants of a human being, would soon
be led to suspect that general laws were unnecessary
and would adjudge the causes that came before them
not according to certain axioms previously written,
but according to the circumstances and demand of each
particular cause.”
Godwin had a clear mental picture
of the gradual decay of authority towards the close
of the period of transition; his vision of the earlier
stages is less definite. He set his faith on the
rapid working of enquiry and persuasion, but he does
not explain in detail how, for example, we are to
rid ourselves of kings. He once met the Prince
Regent, but it is not recorded that he talked to him
of virtue and equality, as the early Quakers talked
to the man Charles Stuart. He is chiefly concerned
to warn his revolutionary friends against abrupt changes.
There must be a general desire for change, a conviction
of the understanding among the masses, before any
change is wise. When a whole nation, or even
an unquestionable majority of a nation, is resolved
on change, no government, even with a standing army
behind it, can stand against it. Every reformer
imagines that the country is with him. What folly!
Even when the majority seems resolved, what is the
quality of their resolution? They do, perhaps,
sincerely dislike some specific tax. But do they
dislike the vice and meanness that grow out of tyranny,
and pant for the liberal and ingenuous virtue that
would be fostered in their own minds by better conditions?
It is a disaster when the unillumined masses are instigated
to violent revolution. Revolutions are always
crude, bloody, uncertain and inimical to tolerance,
independence, and intellectual inquiry. They
are a detestable persecution when a minority promotes
them. If they must occur, at least postpone them
as long as possible. External freedom is worthless
without the magnanimity, firmness and energy that
should attend it. But if a man have these things,
there is little left for him to desire. He cannot
be degraded, nor become useless and unhappy.
Let us not be in haste to overthrow the usurped powers
of the world. Make men wise, and by that very
operation you make them free. It is unfortunate
that men are so eager to strike and have so little
constancy to reason. We should desire neither
violent change nor the stagnation that inflames and
produces revolutions. Our prayer to governments
should be, “Do not give us too soon; do not give
us too much; but act under the incessant influence
of a disposition to give us something.”
These are the reflections of a man
who wrote amid the Terror. He had seen the Corresponding
Society at work, and the experience made him more
than sceptical of any form of association in politics,
and led him into a curiously biassed argument, rhetorical
in form, forensic in substance. Temporary combinations
may be necessary in a time of turmoil, or to secure
some single limited end, such as the redress of a wrong
done to an individual. Where their scope is general
and their duration long continued, they foster declamation,
cabal, party spirit and tumult. They are frequented
by the artful, the intemperate, the acrimonious, and
avoided by the sober, the sceptical, the contemplative
citizen. They foster a fallacious uniformity
of opinion and render the mind quiescent and stationary.
Truth disclaims the alliance of marshalled numbers.
The conditions most favourable to reasoned enquiry
and calm persuasion are to be found in small and friendly
circles. The moral beauty of the spectacle offered
by these groups of friends united to pursue truth and
foster virtue, will render it contagious. So the
craggy steep of science will be levelled and knowledge
rendered accessible to all.
The conception of the State which
Godwin sought to supplant was itself limited and negative.
Government was little else in his day than a means
for internal defence against criminals and for external
defence against aggression. For the rest, it
helped landlords to enclose commons, kept down wages
by poor relief and in a muddle-headed way interfered
with the freedom of trade. But its central activity
was the repression of crime, and for Godwin’s
system the test question was his handling of the problem
of crime and punishment. He was no Platonist,
but not for the first time we discover him in a familiar
Socratic position. “Do you punish a man,”
asked Socrates, “to make him better or to make
him worse?” Godwin starts by rejecting the traditional
conception of punishment. The word means the
infliction of evil upon a vicious being, not merely
because the public advantage demands it, but because
there is a certain fitness and propriety in making
suffering the accompaniment of vice, quite apart from
any benefit that may be in the result. No adherent
of the doctrine of necessity in morals can justify
that attitude. The assassin could no more avoid
the murder he committed than could the dagger.
Justice opposes any suffering, which is not attended
by benefit. Resentment against vice will not excuse
useless torture. We must banish the conception
of desert. To punish for what is past and irrecoverable
must be ranked among the most baleful conceptions of
barbarism. Xerxes was not more unreasonable when
he lashed the waves of the sea, than that man would
be who inflicted suffering on his fellow from a view
to the past and not from a view to the future.
Excluding all idea of punishment in
the proper sense of the word, it remains only to consider
such coercion as is used against persons convicted
of injurious action in the past, for the purpose of
preventing future mischief. Godwin now invites
us to consider the futility of coercion as a means
of reforming, or as he would say, “enlightening
the understanding” of a man who has erred.
Our aim is to bring him to the acceptance of our conception
of duty. Assuming that we possess more of eternal
justice than he, do we shrink from setting our wit
against his? Instead of acting as his preceptor
we become his tyrant. Coercion first annihilates
the understanding of its victim, and then of him who
adopts it. Dressed in the supine prerogatives
of a master, he is excused from cultivating the faculties
of a man. Coercion begins by producing pain,
by violently alienating the mind from the truth with
which we wish it to be impressed. It includes
a tacit confession of imbecility.
With some hesitation Godwin allows
the use of force to restrain a man found in actual
violence. We may not have time to reason with
him. But even for self-defence there are other
resources. “The powers of the mind are
yet unfathomed.” He tells the story of Marius,
who overawed the soldier sent into his cell to execute
him, with the words, “Wretch, have you the temerity
to kill Marius?” Were we all accustomed to place
an intrepid confidence in the unaided energy of the
intellect, to despise force in others and to refuse
to employ it ourselves, who shall say how far the
species might be improved? But punitive coercion
deals only with a man whose violence is over.
The only rational excuse for it is to restrain a man
from further violence which he will presumably commit.
Godwin condemns capital punishment as excessive, since
restraint can be attained without it, and corporal
chastisement as an offence against the dignity of
the human mind. Let there be nothing in the state
of transition worse than simple imprisonment.
Godwin, however, dissents vehemently from Howard’s
invention of solitary confinement, designed to shield
the prisoner from the contamination of his fellow criminals.
Man is a social animal and virtue depends on social
relations. As a preliminary to acquiring it is
he to be shut out from the society of his fellows?
How shall he exercise benevolence or justice in his
cell? Will his heart become softened or expand
who breathes the atmosphere of a dungeon? Solitary
confinement is the bitterest torment that human ingenuity
can inflict. The least objectionable method of
depriving a criminal of the power to harm society
is banishment or transportation. Expose him to
the stimulus of necessity in an unsettled country.
New conditions make new minds. But the whole
attempt to apply law breaks down. You must heap
edict on edict, and to make your laws fit your cases,
must either for ever wrest them or make new ones.
Law does not end uncertainty, and it debilitates the
mind. So long as men are habituated to look to
foreign guidance and external rules for direction,
so long the vigour of their minds will sleep.
If Fenelon, saint and philosopher,
with an incompleted masterpiece in his pocket, and
Fenelon’s chambermaid, were both in danger of
burning to death in the archiepiscopal palace at Cambrai,
and if I could save only one of them, which ought
I to save? It is a fascinating problem in casuistry,
and Godwin with his usual decision of mind, has no
doubt about the solution. He would save Fenelon
as the more valuable life, and above all Fenelon’s
manuscript, and the maid, he is quite sure, would
wish to give her life for his. Something (the
modern reader will object) might be urged on the other
side. Just because he was a saint, it might be
argued that he was the fitter of the two to face the
great adventure, and one may be sure that he himself
would have thought so. A philosopher who gives
his life for a kitten will have advanced the Kingdom
of Heaven. The chambermaid, moreover, may have
in her a potentiality of love and happiness which
are worth many a masterpiece of French prose.
But Godwin has not yet exhausted his moral problem.
How, if the maid were my mother, wife or benefactress?
Once more he gives his unflinching answer. Justice
still requires of me in the interests of mankind to
save the more valuable life. “What magic
is there in the pronoun ‘my’ to overturn
the decisions of everlasting truth?” My mother
may be a fool, a liar, or a thief. Of what consequence
then, is it that she is “mine”? Gratitude
ought not to blind me to my duty, though she have suckled
me and nursed me. The benevolence of a benefactor
ought indeed to be esteemed, but not because it benefited
me. A benefactor ought to be esteemed as much
by another as by me, solely because he benefited a
human being. Gratitude, in short, has no place
in justice or virtue, and reason declines to recognise
the private affections.
Such, crudely stated, is Godwin’s
famous doctrine of “universal benevolence.”
The virtuous man is like Swift’s Houyhnhnms,
noble quadrupeds, wholly governed by reason, who cared
for strangers as well as for the nearest neighbour,
and showed the same affection for their neighbour’s
offspring as for their own. The centre of Godwin’s
moral teaching was yet another Socratic thought.
Politics are “the proper vehicle of a liberal
morality,” and morals concern our relation to
the whole body of mankind. To realise justice
is our prime concern as rational beings, and society
is nothing but embodied justice. Justice deals
with beings capable of pleasure and pain. Here
we are partakers of a common nature with like faculties
for suffering or enjoyment. “Justice,”
then, “is that impartial treatment of every man
in matters that relate to his happiness, which is
measured solely by a consideration of the properties
of the receiver and the capacity of him who gives.”
Every man with whom I am in contact is a sentient being,
and one should be as much to me as another, save indeed
where equity corrects equality, by suggesting to me
that one individual may be of more value than another,
because of his greater power to benefit mankind.
Justice exacts from us the application of our talents,
time, and resources with the single object of producing
the greatest sum of benefit to sentient beings.
There is no limit to what I am bound to do for the
general weal. I hold my person and property both
in trust on behalf of mankind. A man who needs
L10 has an absolute claim on me, if I have it, unless
it can be shown that the money could be more beneficially
applied. Every shilling I possess is irrevocably
assigned by some claim of eternal justice. Every
article of property, it follows, should belong to
him in whose hands it will be of most benefit, and
the instrument of the greatest happiness.
It is the love of distinction which
attends wealth in corrupt societies that explains
the desire for luxury. We desire not the direct
pleasure to be derived from excessive possessions,
but the consideration which is attached to it.
Our very clothes are an appeal to the goodwill of our
neighbours, and a refuge from their contempt.
Society would be transformed if the distinction were
reversed, if admiration were no longer rendered to
the luxurious and avaricious and were accorded only
to talent and virtue. Let not the necessity of
rewarding virtue be suggested as a justification for
the inequalities of fortune. Shall we say, to
a virtuous man: “If you show yourself deserving,
you shall have the essence of a hundred times more
food than you can eat, and a hundred times more clothes
than you can wear. You shall have a patent for
taking away from others the means of a happy and respectable
existence, and for consuming them in riotous and unmeaning
extravagance.” Is this the reward that
ought to be offered to virtue, or that virtue should
stoop to take? Godwin is at his best on this
theme of luxury: “Every man may calculate
in every glass of wine he drinks, and every ornament
he annexes to his person, how many individuals have
been condemned to slavery and sweat, incessant drudgery,
unwholesome food, continual hardships, deplorable
ignorance and brutal insensibility, that he may be
supplied with these luxuries. It is a gross imposition
that men are accustomed to put upon themselves, when
they talk of the property bequeathed to them by their
ancestors. The property is produced by the daily
labour of men who are now in existence. All that
the ancestors bequeathed to them was a mouldy patent
which they show as a title to extort from their neighbours
what the labour of those neighbours has produced.”
It is a flagrant immorality that one
man should have the power to dispose of the produce
of another man’s toil, yet to maintain this power
is the main concern of police and legislation.
Morality recognises two degrees of property, (1) things
which will produce the greatest benefit, if attributed
to me, in brief the necessities of life, my food, clothes,
furniture and apartment; (2) the empire which every
man may claim over the produce of his own industry,
even over that part of it which ought not to be used
and appropriated by himself. Every man is a steward.
But subject to censure and remonstrance, he must be
free to dispose of his property as his own understanding
shall dictate. The ideal is equality, and all
society should be what Coleridge called a Pantisocracy.
It is wrong for any one to enjoy anything, unless
something similar is accessible to all, and wrong
to produce luxuries until the elementary wants of
all are satisfied. But it would be futile and
wrong to attempt to equalise property by positive
enactment. It would be useless until men are
virtuous, and unnecessary when they are so. The
moment accumulation and monopoly are regarded by any
society as dishonourable and mischievous, the revolution
in opinion will ensure that comforts shall tend to
a level.
Godwin objects to the plans put forward
in France during the Revolution for interfering with
bequests and inheritance. He would, however, check
the incentives to accumulation by abolishing the feudal
system, primogeniture, titles and entail. Property
is sacred that good men may be free to
give it away. Reform public opinion, and a man
engaged in amassing wealth would soon hide his treasures
as carefully as he now displays them. The first
step is to rob wealth of its distinction. Wealth
is acquired to-day in over-reaching our neighbours,
and spent in insulting them. Establish equality
on a firm basis of rational opinion, and you cut off
for ever the great occasion of crime, remove the constant
spectacle of injustice with all its attendant demoralisation,
and liberate genius now immersed in sordid cares.
“In a state of society where
men lived in the midst of plenty, and where all shared
alike the bounties of nature, the sentiments of oppression,
servility and fraud would inevitably expire. The
narrow principle of selfishness would vanish.
No man being obliged to guard his little store, or
provide with anxiety and pain for his restless wants,
each would lose his individual existence in the thought
of the general good. No man would be an enemy
to his neighbour, for they would have no subject of
contention, and of consequence philanthropy would resume
the empire which reason assigns her. Mind would
be delivered from her perpetual anxiety about corporal
support, and freed to expatiate in the field of thought,
which is congenial to her. Each would assist the
enquiries of all.”
Unnecessary tasks absorb most of our
labour to-day. In the ideal community, Godwin
reckons that half an hour’s toil from every man
daily will suffice to produce the necessities of life.
He modified this sanguine estimate in a later essay
(The Enquirer) to two hours. He dismisses
all objections based on the sloth or selfishness of
human nature, by the simple answer that this happy
state of things will not be realised until human nature
has been reformed. Need individuality suffer?
It need fear only the restraint imposed by candid public
opinion. That will not be irksome, because it
will be frank. We shrink from it to-day, only
because it takes the form of clandestine scandal and
backbiting. Godwin contemplates no Spartan plan
of common labour or common meals. “Everything
understood by the term co-operation is in some sense
an evil.” To be sure, it may be indispensable
in order to cut a canal or navigate a ship. But
mechanical invention will gradually make it unnecessary.
The Spartans used slaves. We shall make machines
our helots. Indeed, so odious is co-operation
to a free mind, that Godwin marvels that men can consent
to play music in concert, or can demean themselves
to execute another man’s compositions, while
to act a part in a play amounts almost to an offence
against sincerity. Such extravagances as
this passage are amongst the most precious things in
Political Justice. Godwin was a fanatic
of logic who warns us against his individualist premises
by pressing them to a fantastic conclusion.
The sketch of the ideal community
concludes with a demolition of the family. Cohabitation,
he argued, is in itself an evil. It melts opinions
to a common mould, and destroys the fortitude of the
individual. The wishes of two people who live
together can never wholly coincide. Hence follow
thwartings of the will, bickering and misery.
No man is always cheerful and kind. We manage
to correct a stranger with urbanity and good humour.
Only when the intercourse is too close and unremitted
do we degenerate into surliness and invective.
In an earlier chapter Godwin had formulated a general
objection to all promises, which reminds us of Tolstoy’s
sermons from the same individualistic standpoint on
the text, “Swear not at all.” Every
conceivable mode of action has its tendency to benefit
or injure mankind. I am bound in duty to one course
of action in every emergency the course
most conducive to the general welfare. Why, then,
should I bind myself by a promise? If my promise
contradicts my duty it is immoral, if it agrees with
it, it teaches me to do that from a precarious and
temporary motive which ought to be done from its intrinsic
recommendations. By promising we bind ourselves
to learn nothing from time, to make no use of knowledge
to be acquired. Promises depose us from a full
use of our understanding, and are to be tolerated
only in the trivial engagements of our day-to-day existence.
It follows that marriage is an evil, for it is at
once the closest form of cohabitation, and the rashest
of all promises. Two thoughtless and romantic
people, met in youth under circumstances full of delusion,
have bound themselves, not by reason but by contract,
to make the best, when they discover their deception,
of an irretrievable mistake. Its maxim is, “If
you have made a mistake, cherish it.” So
long as this institution survives, “philanthropy
will be crossed in a thousand ways, and the still
augmenting stream of abuse continue to flow.”
Godwin has little fear of lust or
license. Men will, on the whole, continue to
prefer one partner, and friendship will refine the
grossness of sense. There are worse evils than
open and avowed inconstancy the loathsome
combination of deceitful intrigue with the selfish
monopoly of property. That a child should know
its father is no great matter, for I ought not in
reason to prefer one human being to another because
he is “mine.” The mother will care
for the child with the spontaneous help of her neighbours.
As to the business of supplying children with food
and clothing, “these would easily find their
true level and spontaneously flow from the quarter
in which they abounded to the quarter that was deficient.”
There must be no barter or exchange, but only giving
from pure benevolence without the prospect of reciprocal
advantage.
The picture of this easy-going Utopia,
in which something will always turn up for nobody’s
child, concludes with two sections which exhibit in
nice juxtaposition the extravagance and the prudence
of Godwin. We may look forward to great physical
changes. We shall acquire an empire over our
bodies, and may succeed in making even our reflex notions
conscious. We must get rid of sleep, one of the
most conspicuous infirmities of the human frame.
Life can be prolonged by intellect. We are sick
and we die because in a certain sense we consent to
suffer these accidents. When the limit of population
is reached, men will refuse to propagate themselves
further. Society will be a people of men, and
not of children, adult, veteran, experienced; and
truth will no longer have to recommence her career
at the end of thirty years. Meanwhile let the
friends of justice avoid violence, eschew massacres,
and remember that prudent handling will win even rich
men for the cause of human perfection.
So ends Political Justice,
the strangest amalgam in our literature of caution
with enthusiasm, of visions with experience, of French
logic with English tactlessness, a book which only
genius could have made so foolish and so wise.