I have been invited to speak to you
about the relations between Religion and Philosophy.
To do that in a logical and thoroughgoing way it
would be necessary to discuss elaborately the meaning
first of Religion and then of Philosophy. Such
a discussion would occupy at least a lecture, and
I am unwilling to spend one out of six scanty hours
in formal preliminaries. I shall assume, therefore,
that we all know in some general way the meaning of
Religion. It is not necessary for our present
purpose to discuss such questions as the definition
of Religion for purposes of sociological investigation,
or the possibility of a Religion without a belief
in God, or the like. I shall assume that, whatever
else may be included in the term Religion, Christianity
may at least be included in it; and that what you are
practically most interested in is the bearing of Philosophy
upon the Christian ideas concerning the being
and nature of God, the hope of Immortality, the meaning
and possibility of Revelation. When we turn to
Philosophy, I cannot perhaps assume with equal confidence
that all of you know what it is. But then learning
what Philosophy is especially that most
fundamental part of Philosophy which is called Metaphysics is
like learning to swim: you never discover how
to do it until you find yourself considerably out
of your depth. You must strike out boldly, and
at last you discover what you are after. I shall
presuppose that in a general way you do all know that
Philosophy is an enquiry into the ultimate nature
of the Universe at large, as opposed to the discussion
of those particular aspects or departments of it which
are dealt with by the special Sciences. What
you want to know, I take it, is what rational
enquiry, pushed as far as it will go, has to say about
those ultimate problems of which the great historical
Religions likewise profess to offer solutions.
The nature and scope of Philosophy is best understood
by examples: and therefore I hope you will excuse
me if without further preface I plunge in medias
res. I shall endeavour to presuppose no
previous acquaintance with technical Philosophy, and
I will ask those who have already made some serious
study of Philosophy kindly to remember that I am trying
to make myself intelligible to those who have not.
I shall not advance anything which I should not
be prepared to defend even before an audience of metaphysical
experts. But I cannot undertake in so short a
course of lectures to meet all the objections which
will, I know, be arising in the minds of any metaphysically
trained hearers who may honour me with their presence,
many of which may probably occur to persons not so
trained. And I further trust the Metaphysicians
among you will forgive me if, in order to be intelligible
to all, I sometimes speak with a little less than
the akribeia at which I might feel bound to
aim if I were reading a paper before an avowedly philosophical
Society. Reservations, qualifications, and elaborate
distinctions must be omitted, if I am to succeed in
saying anything clearly in the course of six lectures.
Moreover, I would remark that, though
I do not believe that an intention to edify is any
excuse for slipshod thought or intellectual dishonesty,
I am speaking now mainly from the point of view of
those who are enquiring into metaphysical truth for
the guidance of their own religious and practical
life, rather than from the point of view of pure speculation.
I do not, for my own part, believe in any solution
of the religious problem which evades the ultimate
problems of all thought. The Philosophy of Religion
is for me not so much a special and sharply distinguished
branch or department of Philosophy as a particular
aspect of Philosophy in general. But many questions
which may be of much importance from the point of
view of a complete theory of the Universe can be entirely,
or almost entirely, put on one side when the question
is, ’What may I reasonably believe about those
ultimate questions which have a direct and immediate
bearing upon my religious and moral life; what may
I believe about God and Duty, about the world and
its ultimate meaning, about the soul and its destiny?’
For such purposes solutions stopping short of what
will fully satisfy the legitimate demands of the professed
Metaphysician may be all that is necessary, or at
least all that is possible for those who are not intending
to make a serious and elaborate study of Metaphysic.
I have no sympathy with the attempt to base Religion
upon anything but honest enquiry into truth:
and yet the professed Philosophers are just those
who will most readily recognize that there are if
not what are technically called degrees of truth still
different levels of thought, different degrees of
adequacy and systematic completeness, even within
the limits of thoroughly philosophical thinking.
I shall assume that you are not content to remain
at the level of ordinary unreflecting Common-sense
or of merely traditional Religion that you
do want (so far as time and opportunity serve) to
get to the bottom of things, but that you will
be content in such a course as the present if I can
suggest to you, or help you to form for yourselves,
an outline what Plato would call the hypotyposis
of a theory of the Universe which may still fall very
far short of a finished and fully articulated metaphysical
system.
I suppose that to nearly everybody
who sets himself down to think seriously about the
riddle of the Universe there very soon occurs the
question whether Materialism may not contain the solution
of all difficulties. I think, therefore, our
present investigation had better begin with an enquiry
whether Materialism can possibly be true. I say
‘can be true’ rather than ‘is true,’
because, though dogmatic Materialists are rare, the
typical Agnostic is one who is at least inclined to
admit the possibility of Materialism, even when he
does not, at the bottom of his mind, practically assume
its truth. The man who is prepared to exclude
even this one theory of the Universe from the category
of possible but unprovable theories is not, properly
speaking, an Agnostic. To know that Materialism
at least is not true is to know something, and something
very important, about the ultimate nature of things.
I shall not attempt here any very precise definition
of what is meant by Materialism. Strictly speaking,
it ought to mean the view that nothing really exists
but matter. But the existence, in some sense
or other, of our sensations and thoughts and emotions
is so obvious to Common-sense that such a creed can
hardly be explicitly maintained: it is a creed
which is refuted in the very act of enunciating it.
For practical purposes, therefore, Materialism may
be said to be the view that the ultimate basis of
all existence is matter; and that thought, feeling,
emotion consciousness of every kind is
merely an effect, a by-product or concomitant, of certain
material processes.
Now if we are to hold that matter
is the only thing which exists, or is the ultimate
source of all that exists, we ought to be able to say
what matter is. To the unreflecting mind matter
seems to be the thing that we are most certain of,
the one thing that we know all about. Thought,
feeling, will, it may be suggested, are in some sense
appearances which (though we can’t help having
them) might, from the point of view of superior insight,
turn out to be mere delusions, or at best entirely
unimportant and inconsiderable entities. This
attitude of mind has been amusingly satirised by the
title of one of Mr. Bradley’s philosophical
essays ’on the supposed uselessness
of the Soul.’ In this state of mind matter
presents itself as the one solid reality as
something undeniable, something perfectly intelligible,
something, too, which is pre-eminently important
and respectable; while thinking and feeling and willing,
joy and sorrow, hope and aspiration, goodness and
badness, if they cannot exactly be got rid of altogether,
are, as it were, negligible quantities, which must
not be allowed to disturb or interfere with the serious
business of the Universe.
From this point of view matter is
supposed to be the one reality with which we are in
immediate contact, which we see and touch and taste
and handle every hour of our lives. It may,
therefore, sound a rather startling paradox to say
that matter matter in the sense of the
Materialist is something which nobody has
ever seen, touched, or handled. Yet that is
the literal and undeniable fact. Nobody has ever
seen or touched or otherwise come in contact with a
piece of matter. For in the experience which
the plain man calls seeing or touching there is always
present another thing. Even if we suppose that
he is Justified in saying ‘I touch matter,’
there is always present the ‘I’ as well
as the matter. It is always and inevitably matter
+ mind that he knows. Nobody ever can get away
from this ‘I,’ nobody can ever see or
feel what matter is like apart from the ‘I’
which knows it. He may, indeed, infer that
this matter exists apart from the ‘I’ which
knows it. He may infer that it exists, and may
even go as far as to assume that, apart from his seeing
or touching, or anybody else’s seeing or touching,
matter possesses all those qualities which it possesses
for his own consciousness. But this is inference,
and not immediate knowledge. And the validity
or reasonableness of the inference may be disputed.
How far it is reasonable or legitimate to attribute
to matter as it is in itself the qualities which it
has for us must depend upon the nature of those qualities.
Let us then go on to ask whether the qualities which
constitute matter as we know it are qualities which
we can reasonably or even intelligibly attribute to
a supposed matter-in-itself, to matter considered
as something capable of existing by itself altogether
apart from any kind of conscious experience.
In matter, as we know it, there are
two elements. There are certain sensations,
or certain qualities which we come to know by sensation,
and there are certain relations. Now, with regard
to the sensations, a very little reflection will,
I think, show us that it is absolutely meaningless
to say that matter has the qualities implied by these
sensations, even when they are not felt, and would
still possess them, even supposing it never had been
and never would be felt by any one whatever.
In a world in which there were no eyes and no
minds, what would be the meaning of saying that things
were red or blue? In a world in which there
were no ears and no minds, there would clearly be
no such thing as sound. This is exactly the point
at which Locke’s analysis stopped. He
admitted that the ’secondary qualities’ colours,
sounds, tastes of objects were really not
in the things themselves but in the mind which perceives
them. What existed in the things was merely
a power of producing these sensations in us, the quality
in the thing being not in the least like the sensations
which it produces in us: he admitted that this
power of producing a sensation was something different
from, and totally unlike, the sensation itself.
But when he came to the primary qualities solidity,
shape, magnitude and the like he supposed
that the qualities in the thing were exactly the same
as they are for our minds. If all mind were to
disappear from the Universe, there would henceforth
be no red and blue, no hot and cold; but things would
still be big or small, round or square, solid or fluid.
Yet, even with these ‘primary qualities’
the reference to mind is really there just as much
as in the case of the secondary qualities; only the
fact is not quite so obvious. And one reason
for this is that these primary qualities involve,
much more glaringly and unmistakably than the secondary,
something which is not mere sensation something
which implies thought and not mere sense.
What do we mean by solidity, for instance?
We mean partly that we get certain sensations from
touching the object sensations of touch
and sensations of what is called the muscular sense,
sensations of muscular exertion and of pressure resisted.
Now, so far as that is what solidity means, it is
clear that the quality in question involves as direct
a reference to our subjective feelings as the secondary
qualities of colour and sound. But something
more than this is implied in our idea of solidity.
We think of external objects as occupying space.
And spaciality cannot be analysed away into mere
feelings of ours. The feelings of touch which
we derive from an object come to us one after the other.
No mental reflection upon sensations which come one
after the other in time could ever give us the idea
of space, if they were not spacially related from
the first. It is of the essence of spaciality
that the parts of the object shall be thought of as
existing side by side, outside one another.
But this side-by-sideness, this outsideness, is after
all a way in which the things present themselves to
a mind. Space is made up of relations; and what
is the meaning of relations apart from a mind which
relates, or for which the things are related?
If spaciality were a quality of the thing in itself,
it would exist no matter what became of other things.
It would be quite possible, therefore, that
the top of this table should exist without the bottom:
yet everybody surely would admit the meaninglessness
of talking about a piece of matter (no matter how
small, be it an atom or the smallest electron conceived
by the most recent physical speculation) which had
a top without a bottom, or a right-hand side without
a left. This space-occupying quality which is
the most fundamental element in our ordinary conception
of matter is wholly made up of the relation of one
part of it to another. Now can a relation exist
except for a mind? As it seems to me, the suggestion
is meaningless. Relatedness only has a meaning
when thought of in connection with a mind which is
capable of grasping or holding together both terms
of the relation. The relation between point
A and point B is not in point A or in
point B taken by themselves. It is all in the
‘between’: ‘betweenness’
from its very nature cannot exist in any one point
of space or in several isolated points of space or
things in space; it must exist only in some one existent
which holds together and connects those points.
And nothing, as far as we can understand, can do
that except a mind. Apart from mind there can
be no relatedness: apart from relatedness no space:
apart from space no matter. It follows that apart
from mind there can be no matter.
It will probably be known to all of
you that the first person to make this momentous
inference was Bishop Berkeley. There was, indeed,
an obscure medieval schoolman, hardly recognized by
the historians of Philosophy, one Nicholas of Autrecourt,
Dean of Metz, who anticipated him in the fourteenth
century, and other better-known schoolmen who approximated
to the position; and there are, of course, elements
in the teaching of Plato and even of Aristotle, or
possible interpretations of Plato and Aristotle, which
point in the same direction. But full-blown
Idealism, in the sense which involves a denial of
the independent existence of matter, is always associated
with the name of Bishop Berkeley.
I can best make my meaning plain to
you by quoting a passage or two from his Principles
of Human Knowledge, in which he extends to the
primary qualities of matter the analysis which Locke
had already applied to the secondary.
’But, though it were possible
that solid, figured, moveable substances may exist
without the mind, corresponding to the ideas we have
of bodies, yet how is it possible for us to know this?
Either we must know it by Sense or by Reason. As
for our senses, by them we have the knowledge only
of our sensations, ideas, or those things that are
immediately perceived by sense, call them what you
will; but they do not inform us that things exist
without the mind, or unperceived, like to those
which are perceived. This the Materialists themselves
acknowledge. It remains therefore that if
we have any knowledge at all of external things, it
must be by Reason inferring their existence from what
is immediately perceived by sense. But what reason
can induce us to believe the existence of bodies without
the mind, from what we perceive, since the very patrons
of Matter themselves do not pretend there is any necessary
connexion betwixt them and our ideas? I say
it is granted on all hands and what happens
in dreams, frenzies, and the like, puts it beyond
dispute that it is possible we might be
affected with all the ideas we have now, though there
were no bodies existing without resembling them.
Hence, it is evident the supposition of external
bodies is not necessary for the producing our ideas;
since it is granted they are produced sometimes, and
might possibly be produced always in the same order
we see them in at present, without their concurrence.
’In short, if there were external
bodies, it is impossible we should ever come to know
it; and if there were not, we might have the very
same reasons to think there were that we have now.
Suppose what no one can deny possible an
intelligence without the help of external bodies,
to be affected with the same train of sensations or
ideas that you are, imprinted in the same order and
with like vividness in his mind. I ask whether
that intelligence hath not all the reason to believe
the existence of corporeal substances, represented
by his ideas, and exciting them in his mind, that
you can possibly have for believing the same thing?
Of this there can be no question which
one consideration were enough to make any reasonable
person suspect the strength of whatever arguments
he may think himself to have, for the existence of
bodies without the mind.’
Do you say that in that case the tables
and chairs must be supposed to disappear the moment
we all leave the room? It is true that we do
commonly think of the tables and chairs as remaining,
even when there is no one there to see or touch them.
But that only means, Berkeley explains, that if we
or any one else were to come back into the room, we
should perceive them. Moreover, even in thinking
of them as things which might be perceived under certain
conditions, they have entered our minds and so proclaimed
their ideal or mind-implying character. To prove
that things exist without the mind we should have to
conceive of things as unconceived or unthought of.
And that is a feat which no one has ever yet succeeded
in accomplishing.
Here is Berkeley’s own answer to the objection:
’But, say you, surely there
is nothing easier than for me to imagine trees, for
instance, in a park, or books existing in a closet,
and nobody by to perceive them. I answer, you
may so, there is no difficulty in it; but what is
all this, I beseech you, more than framing in your
mind certain ideas which you call books and trees,
and at the same time omitting to frame the idea
of any one that may perceive them? But do not
you yourself perceive or think of them all the while?
This therefore is nothing to the purpose: it
only shews you have the power of imagining or forming
ideas in your mind; but it does not shew that you
can conceive it possible the objects of your thought
may exist without the mind. To make out this,
it is necessary that you conceive them existing
unconceived or unthought of, which is a manifest repugnancy.
When we do our utmost to conceive the existence of
external bodies, we are all the while only contemplating
our own ideas. But the mind, taking no notice
of itself, is deluded to think it can and does
conceive bodies existing unthought of or without the
mind, though at the same time they are apprehended
by, or exist in, itself. A little attention
will discover to any one the truth and evidence of
what is here said, and make it unnecessary to insist
on any other proofs against the existence of material
substance.’
Berkeley no doubt did not adequately
appreciate the importance of the distinction between
mere sensations and mental relations. In the
paragraph which I have read to you he tends to explain
space away into mere subjective feelings: in
this respect and in many others he has been corrected
by Kant and the post-Kantian Idealists. Doubtless
we cannot analyse away our conception of space or
of substance into mere feelings. But relations
imply mind no less than sensations. Things are
no mere bundles of sensations; we do think of
them as objects or substances possessing attributes.
Indeed to call them (with Berkeley), ‘bundles
of sensations’ implies that the bundle is as
important an element in thinghood as the sensations
themselves. The bundle implies what Kant would
call the intellectual ‘categories’ of
Substance, Quantity, Quality, and the like. We
do think objects: but an object is still an object
of thought. We can attach no intelligible meaning
to the term ‘object’ which does not imply
a subject.
If there is nothing in matter, as
we know it, which does not obviously imply mind, if
the very idea of matter is unintelligible apart from
mind, it is clear that matter can never have existed
without mind.
What then, it may be asked, of the
things which no human eye has ever seen or even thought
of? Are we to suppose that a new planet comes
into existence for the first time when first it sails
into the telescope of the astronomer, and that Science
is wrong in inferring that it existed not only before
that particular astronomer saw it, but before there
were any astronomers or other human or even animal
intelligences upon this planet to observe it?
Did the world of Geology come into existence for
the first time when some eighteenth-century geologist
first suspected that the world was more than six thousand
years old? Are all those ages of past history,
when the earth and the sun were but nebulae, a mere
imagination, or did that nebulous mass come into existence
thousands or millions of years afterwards when Kant
or Laplace first conceived that it had existed?
The supposition is clearly self-contradictory and
impossible. If Science be not a mass of illusion,
this planet existed millions of years before any human or,
so far as we know, any animal minds existed
to think its existence. And yet I have endeavoured
to show the absurdity of supposing that matter can
exist except for a mind. It is clear, then, that
it cannot be merely for such minds as ours that the
world has always existed. Our minds come and
go. They have a beginning; they go to sleep;
they may, for aught that we can immediately know,
come to an end. At no time does any one of them,
at no time do all of them together, apprehend all
that there is to be known. We do not create a
Universe; we discover it piece by piece, and after
all very imperfectly. Matter cannot intelligibly
be supposed to exist apart from Mind: and yet
it clearly does not exist merely for our minds.
Each of us knows only one little bit of the Universe:
all of us together do not know the whole. If
the whole is to exist at all, there must be some one
mind which knows the whole. The mind which is
necessary to the very existence of the Universe is
the mind that we call God.
In this way we are, as it seems to
me, led up by a train of reasoning which is positively
irresistible to the idea that, so far from matter
being the only existence, it has no existence of its
own apart from some mind which knows it in
which and for which it exists. The existence
of a Mind possessing universal knowledge is necessary
as the presupposition both of there being any world
to know, and also of there being any lesser minds
to know it. It is, indeed, possible to believe
in the eternal existence of limited minds, while denying
the existence of the one Omniscient Mind. That
is a hypothesis on which I will say a word hereafter.
It is enough here to say that it is one which is
not required to explain the world as we know it.
The obvious prima facie view of the matter
is that the minds which apparently have a beginning,
which develope slowly and gradually and in close connexion
with certain physical processes, owe their origin to
whatever is the ultimate source or ground of the physical
processes themselves. The order or systematic
interconnexion of all the observable phenomena
in the Universe suggests that the ultimate Reality
must be one Being of some kind; the argument which
I have suggested leads us to regard that one Reality
as a spiritual Reality. We are not yet entitled
to speak of this physical Universe as caused
by God: that is a question which I hope
to discuss in our next lecture. All that I want
to establish now is that we cannot explain the world
without the supposition of one universal Mind in which
and for which all so-called material things exist,
and always have existed.
So far I have endeavoured to establish
the existence of God by a line of thought which also
leads to the position that matter has no independent
existence apart from conscious mind, that at bottom
nothing exists except minds and their experiences.
Now I know that this is a line of thought which,
to those who are unfamiliar with it, seems so paradoxical
and extravagant that, even when a man does not see
his way to reply to it, it will seldom produce immediate
or permanent conviction the first time he becomes
acquainted with it. It is for the most part
only by a considerable course of habituation, extending
over some years, that a man succeeds in thinking himself
into the idealistic view of the Universe. And
after all, there are many minds some of
them, I must admit, not wanting in philosophical power who
never succeed in accomplishing that feat at all.
Therefore, while I feel bound to assert that the
clearest and most irrefragable argument for the existence
of God is that which is supplied by the idealistic
line of thought, I should be sorry to have to admit
that a man cannot be a Theist, or that he cannot
be a Theist on reasonable grounds, without first being
an Idealist. From my own point of view most of
the other reasons for believing in the existence of
God resolve themselves into idealistic arguments imperfectly
thought out. But they may be very good arguments,
as far as they go, even when they are not thought
out to what seem to me their logical consequences.
One of these lines of thought I shall hope to develope
in my next lecture; but meanwhile let me attempt to
reduce the argument against Materialism to a form in
which it will perhaps appeal to Common-sense without
much profound metaphysical reflection.
At the level of ordinary common-sense
thought there appear to be two kinds of Reality mind
and matter. And yet our experience of the unity
of Nature, of the intimate connexion between human
and animal minds and their organisms (organisms governed
by a single intelligible and interconnected system
of laws) is such that we can hardly help regarding
them as manifestations or products or effects or aspects
of some one Reality. There is, almost obviously,
some kind of Unity underlying all the diversity of
things. Our world does not arise by the coming
together of two quite independent Realities mind
and matter governed by no law or by unconnected
and independent systems of law. All things,
all phenomena, all events form parts of a single inter-related,
intelligible whole: that is the presupposition
not only of Philosophy but of Science. Or if
any one chooses to say that it is a presupposition
and so an unwarrantable piece of dogmatism, I will
say that it is the hypothesis to which all our knowledge
points. It is at all events the one common meeting-point
of nearly all serious thinkers. The question
remains, ’What is the nature of this one Reality?’
Now, if this ultimate Reality be not mind, it must
be one of two things. It must be matter, or
it must be a third thing which is neither mind nor
matter, but something quite different from either.
Now many who will not follow the idealistic line of
thought the whole way so far as to recognize
that the ultimate Reality is Mind will at
least admit that Idealists have successfully shown
the impossibility of supposing that the ultimate Reality
can be matter. For all the properties of matter
are properties which imply some relation to our sensibility
or our thought. Moreover, there is such a complete
heterogeneity between consciousness and unconscious
matter, considered as something capable of existing
without mind, that it seems utterly impossible and
unthinkable that mind should be simply the product
or attribute of matter. That the ultimate Reality
cannot be what we mean by matter has been admitted
by the most naturalistic, and, in the ordinary
sense, anti-religious thinkers Spinoza,
for instance, and Haeckel, and Herbert Spencer.
The question remains, ’Which is the easier,
the more probable, the more reasonable theory that
the ultimate Reality should be Mind, or that it should
be something so utterly unintelligible and inconceivable
to us as a tertium quid a mysterious
Unknown and Unknowable which is neither
mind nor matter?’ For my own part, I see no
reason to suppose that our inability to think of anything
which is neither matter nor mind but quite unlike either
is a mere imperfection of human thought. It
seems more reasonable to assume that our inability
to think of such a mysterious X is due to there being
no such thing.
Our only way of judging of the Unknown
is by the analogy of the known. It is more probable,
surely, that the world known to us should exhibit
something of the characteristics of the Reality from
which it is derived, or of which it forms a manifestation,
than that it should exhibit none of these characteristics.
No doubt, if we were to argue from some small part
of our experience, or from the detailed characteristics
of one part of our experience to what is beyond our
experience; if, for instance (I am here replying
to an objection of Hoeffding’s), a blind man
were to argue that the world must be colourless because
he sees no colour, or if any of us were to affirm
that in other planets there can be no colours but what
we see, no sensations but what we feel, no mental
powers but what we possess, the inference would be
precarious enough. The Anthropomorphist in the
strict sense the man who thinks that God
or the gods must have human bodies no doubt
renders himself liable to the gibe that, if oxen could
think, they would imagine the gods to be like oxen,
and so on. But the cases are not parallel.
We have no difficulty in thinking that in other worlds
there may be colours which we have never seen, or whole
groups of sensation different from our own: we
cannot think that any existence should be neither
mind nor matter, but utterly unlike either. We
are not arguing from the mere absence of some special
experience, but from the whole character of all
the thought and experience that we actually possess,
of all that we are and the whole Universe with which
we are in contact. The characteristic of the
whole world which we know is that it consists of mind
and matter in close connexion we may waive
for a moment the nature of that connexion. Is
it more probable that the ultimate Reality which lies
beyond our reach should be something which possesses
the characteristics of mind, or that it should
be totally unlike either mind or matter? Do you
insist that we logically ought to say it might contain
the characteristics of both mind and matter?
There is only one way in which such a combination
seems clearly thinkable by us, i.e. when we
represent matter as either in the idealistic sense
the thought or experience of mind, or (after the fashion
of ordinary realistic Theism) as created or produced
by mind. But if you insist on something more
than this, if you want to think of the qualities of
matter as in some other way included in the nature
of the ultimate Reality as well as those of mind,
at all events we could still urge that we shall get
nearer to the truth by thinking of this ultimate Reality
in its mind-aspect than by thinking of it in its matter-aspect.
I do not believe that the human mind
is really equal to the task of thinking of a Reality
which is one and yet is neither mind nor matter but
something which combines the nature of both.
Practically, where such a creed is professed, the
man either thinks of an unconscious Reality in some
way generating or evolving mind, and so falls back
into the Materialism which he has verbally disclaimed;
or he thinks of a mind producing or causing or generating
a matter which when produced is something different
from itself. This last is of course ordinary
Theism in the form in which it is commonly held
by those who are not Idealists. From a practical
and religious point of view there is nothing to be
said against such a view. Still it involves a
Dualism, the philosophical difficulties of which I
have attempted to suggest to you. I confess
that for my own part the only way in which I can conceive
of a single ultimate Reality which combines the attributes
of what we call mind with those of what we know as
matter is by thinking of a Mind conscious of a world
or nature which has no existence except in and for
that Mind and whatever less complete consciousnesses
that may be. I trust that those who have failed
to follow my sketch of the arguments which lead to
this idealistic conclusion may at least be led by
it to see the difficulties either of Materialism or
of that kind of agnostic Pantheism which, while admitting
in words that the ultimate Reality is not matter,
refuses to invest it with the attributes of mind.
The argument may be reduced to its simplest form by
saying we believe that the ultimate Reality is Mind
because mind will explain matter, while matter will
not explain mind: while the idea of a Something
which is neither in mind nor matter is both unintelligible
and gratuitous.
And this line of thought may be supplemented
by another. Whatever may be thought of the existence
of matter apart from mind, every one will admit
that matter possesses no value or worth apart from
mind. When we bring into account our moral judgements
or judgements of value, we have no difficulty in recognizing
mind as the highest or best kind of existence known
to us. There is, surely, a certain intrinsic
probability in supposing that the Reality from which
all being is derived must possess at least as much
worth or value as the derived being; and that in thinking
of that Reality by the analogy of the highest kind
of existence known to us we shall come nearer to a
true thought of it than by any other way of thinking
possible to us. This is a line of argument which
I hope to develope further when I come to examine
the bearing upon the religious problem of what is as
real a part of our experience as any other our
moral experience.
I will remind you in conclusion, that
our argument for the existence of God is at present
incomplete. I have tried to lead you to the idea
that the ultimate Reality is spiritual, that it is
a Mind which knows, or is conscious of, matter.
I have tried to lead you with the Idealist to think
of the physical Universe as having no existence except
in the mind of God, or at all events (for those who
fail to follow the idealistic line of thought) to
believe that the Universe does not exist without such
a Mind. What further relation exists between
physical nature and this Universal Spirit, I shall
hope in the next lecture to consider; and in
so doing to suggest a line of argument which will
independently lead to the same result, and which does
not necessarily presuppose the acceptance of the idealistic
creed.
LITERATURE
The reader who wishes to have the
idealistic argument sketched in the foregoing chapter
developed more fully should read Berkeley’s
Principles of Human Knowledge. For the
correction of Berkeley’s sensationalistic mistakes
the best course is to read Kant’s Critique
of Pure Reason or the shorter Prolegomena to
any future Metaphysic or any of the numerous expositions
or commentaries upon Kant. (One of the best is the
‘Reproduction’ prefixed to Dr. Hutchison
Stirling’s Text-book to Kant.) The non-metaphysical
reader should, however, be informed that Kant is very
hard reading, and is scarcely intelligible without
some slight knowledge of the previous history of Philosophy,
especially of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, while some
acquaintance with elementary Logic is also desirable.
He will find the argument for non-sensationalistic
Idealism re-stated in a post-Kantian but much easier
form in Ferrier’s Institutes of Metaphysic.
The argument for a theistic Idealism is powerfully
stated (though it is not easy reading) in the late
Prof. T. H. Green’s Prolegomena to Ethics,
Book I. In view of recent realistic revivals I may
add that the earlier chapters of Mr. Bradley’s
Appearance and Reality still seem to me to
contain an unanswerable defence of Idealism as against
Materialism or any form of Realism, though his Idealism
is not of the theistic type defended in the above
lecture. The idealistic argument is stated in
a way which makes strongly for Theism by Professor
Ward in Naturalism and Agnosticism a
work which would perhaps be the best sequel to these
lectures for any reader who does not want to undertake
a whole course of philosophical reading: readers
entirely unacquainted with Physical Science might
do well to begin with Part II. A more elementary
and very clear defence of Theism from the idealistic
point of view is to be found in Dr. Illingworth’s
Personality Human and Divine. Representatives
of non-idealistic Theism will be mentioned at the
end of the next lecture.