ADAPTING PEOPLE TO INDUSTRY THE GERMAN WAY
Statemanship in Germany covered “industrial
strategy” as well as political. Its labor
protection and regulations were in line with its imperial
policy of domination. Within recent years labor
protection from the point of view of statesmanship
has been urged in England and America. The waste
of life is a matter of unconcern in the United States
so long as private business can replenish its labor
without seriously depleting the oversupply. It
becomes a matter of concern only when there are no
workers waiting for employment. The German state
has regulated the conditions of labor and conserved
human energy because its purpose has been not the
short-lived one of private business, but the long-lived
one of imperial competition. It was the policy
of the Prussian state to conserve human energy for
the strength and the enrichment of the Empire.
Whatever was good for the Empire was good, it was
assumed, for the people. The humanitarians in
the United States who tried to introduce labor legislation
in their own country accepted this naïve philosophy
of the German people, which had been so skilfully
developed by Prussian statesmen, without appreciating
that its result was enervating. Our prevailing
political philosophy, however, that workers and capitalists
understand their own interests and are more capable
than the state of looking after them, stood in the
way of adopting on grounds of statesmanship the German
methods.
The American working man has never
been convinced that he can get odds of material advantage
from the state. His method is to get all he can
through “pull,” good luck or his superior
wits. He could find no satisfaction like his
German brothers in surrendering concrete interests
for some abstract idea of a state. He could find
no greater pleasure in being exploited by the state
than he now finds in exploitation by private business.
The average American values life for what he can get
out of it, or for what he can put into it. He
has no sentimental value of service, nor is service
anywhere with us an institutionalized ideal.
We judge it on its merits, detached perhaps, but still
for what it actually renders in values.
In conformity with American ideals,
wage earners look to their own movements and not to
the state for protection. Their movements require
infinite sacrifice, but they supply them with an interest
and an opportunity for initiative which their job
lacks. The most important antidote for the workers
to factory and business methods is not shorter hours
or well calculated rest periods or even change-off
from one kind of routine work to another. As
important as these may be, reform in labor hours does
not compensate the worker for his exclusion from the
directing end of the enterprise of which he is a part
and from a position where he can understand the purpose
of his work The trade union interference with the
business of wealth production is in part an attempt
to establish a cooerdination of the worker which is
destroyed in the prosecution of business and factory
organization. The interference of the union is
an attempt to bridge the gulf between the routine
of service and the administration, and direction of
the service which the worker gives.
I do not intend to imply that the
labor movement is a conscious attempt at such cooerdination.
It is not. The conscious purpose is the direct
and simple desire to resist specific acts of domination
and to increase labor’s economic returns.
But any one who follows the sacrifices which organized
workers make for some small and equivocal gain or
who watches them in their periods of greatest activity,
knows that the labor movement gets its stimulus, its
high pitch of interest, not from its struggle for
higher wage rates, but from the worker’s participation
in the administration of affairs connected with life
in the shop. The real tragedy in a lost strike
is not the failure to gain the wage demand; It is
the return of the defeated strikers to work, as men
unequipped with the administrative power as
men without will.
There could be no greater contrast
of methods of two movements purporting to be the same,
than the labor movement in Germany and in the United
States. The German workers depended on their political
representatives almost wholly to gain their economic
rewards. Their organizations made their appeal
to the sort of a state which Bismarck set up.
They would realize democracy, happiness, they believed,
when their state represented labor and enacted statutes
in its behalf.
If Germany loses the war the chances
are that the people may recognize what it means for
the people of a nation to let the title to their lives
rest with the state; they will know perhaps whether
for the protection they have been given and for the
regulation of their affairs and destiny they have
paid more than the workers of other countries, who,
less protected by law, suffered the exigencies of
their assumed independence.
How much the German people depended
upon the state and how much their destiny is affected
by it is illustrated better by their educational system
and its relation to industry than by any labor legislative
protective practices or policy.
George Kerschensteiner, the director
of the Munich schools, in his book on “The Idea
of the Industrial School,” tells us that the
Purposes and Duties_ of the schools are to realize
the ideal ethical community, and that this realization
is possible in so far as the educational provisions
are made from the standpoint of the ethical concept
of each state. In America we do not think of the
state as the embodiment of our ethical concepts.
The state, as we know it, is one of the several instruments
for realizing ends, ethical as well as material.
The state is supposed to serve the common ends of all
people. A state may be used, we are all aware,
as an instrument, either by Prussian junkers or American
business men; either may capture a state to serve
their ends. But as a state serves special individuals
it belies its professed reason for existence, and in
America is in danger of falling from grace, so far,
that is, as the common people are concerned.
But when a state stands in the minds of a people as
the embodiment of their ideals as it has in Germany,
it must for its own purpose spend time and substance
in purchasing the people’s confidence.
In assuming the place of guardian it must of necessity
minister to the physical needs of the people.
If it retains the people’s confidence in its
guardianship, it is incumbent on it to pursue this
policy. It is incumbent on such a state to mould
the people’s ideas of what their needs are.
The schools obviously offer the most hopeful media
for the accomplishment of that result, and they have
been used in Germany more effectively in this way than
the schools of any other country. The German
school system follows hard and fast preconceptions
of aims and ends, and because of this it was possible
for Germany to put over its own particular sort of
efficiency.
As a first requisite of efficiency,
Germany classifies its people, gives them a place
in the scheme of things, and holds them there.
By circumscribing within definite limitations the experience
of individuals it produces specialists at the sacrifice
of a larger human development. The classification
of the people and the training of them naturally for
the German purpose falls to the schools. The sorting
out of individuals begins at the early age of ten in
the elementary schools, when each child’s social
and economic position is practically determined.
It is decided then whether he shall be one of the great
army of wage workers or whether he shall fall into
some one of the several social classes and vocations
which stand apart from the common mass of wage earners.
The children in the German schools, who are selected
at the age of ten for a more promising future than
the trades hold out, have more leeway in the making
of their decision. But even these children from
the American point of view are summarily disposed
of and fatally consigned.
The telling off of children at the
age of ten and assigning them to a place in the social
scheme for life is not American in spirit, nor does
it conform to our habits and institutions. But,
it is complained, the American habit of taking chances
is not efficient. The habit of letting children
escape into life with their place unsettled creates
confusion and makes calculations in serious things
like industry difficult. Therefore, unfaithful
to the development of our own concepts of life we
are expected to emulate Germany and to determine the
destiny of the child. Germany undertakes to eliminate
the chances of the individual and the taking of chances
by the state, while the American ideal is to leave
its people free to make the most of each new exigency
that life turns up.
At the age of fourteen it is decided
in Germany what industry or trade the children shall
enter, that is, the children who at ten are told off
to industry. After they enter their trade, their
special education for their job is looked after in
the continuation schools as well as in the shop.
Their attendance at the continuation schools is compulsory.
This compulsory attendance does not only insure supplementary
training for a particular job, but holds the children
to the industry which was chosen for them. That
is, a boy is compelled, if he works in the dining-room
of a hotel, to attend the continuation school for
waiters, until he is eighteen. He may not go to
a continuation school for butchers if he decided at
the end of a year or so in his first job that he would
rather be a butcher, or that he would rather do anything
than wait.
The continuation schools protect German
manufacture and the national industrial efficiency
against indulgence in such vagaries. A butcher
would prefer to engage lads who have had experience
in butcher shops and butcher continuation classes.
Avenues of escape from jobs just because they are
uncongenial are thus quite effectively closed together
with, the chance to experiment with life the
chance which Americans take for granted. But
it is just this element of waywardness and the opportunity
America leaves open for its indulgence among working
people that makes labor from the standpoint of American
manufacture so inefficient. For want of opportunity
to put individuality to some account we frequently
fall back on waywardness in an awkward and futile
protest against domination.
While the German scheme of placing
its workers is efficient in its own way, so also is
the training for each particular trade. A child
is trained first to be skillful and second, to quote
Mr. Kerchensteiner, “to be willing to carry
out some function in the state ... so that he may
directly or indirectly further the aim of the state.”
“Having accomplished this,” he says “the
next duty of the schools is to accustom the individual
to look at his vocation as a duty which he must carry
out not merely in the interest of his own material
and moral welfare but also in the interest of the
state.” From this, he says, follows the
next and “greatest educational duty of the public
school. The school must develop in its pupils
the desire and strength ... through their vocation,
to contribute their share so that the development
of the state to which they belong, may progress in
the direction of the ideal of the community.”
His assumption in defining the “greatest
duty” is that the members of the state are free
to evolve and will evolve a progressive ethical community.
But after a child has passed through the hands of a
competent teaching force which fits him successfully
into a ready-made place, after he has accepted this
ready-made place on the authority of modern technology
and business, on the authority of the state and religion,
that the place given him is his to fill; to fill in
accordance with the standards determined by the schools
and by industry after all this, it is difficult
to imagine what else a child could do but conform.
He could do no more, thus trained, than go forward
in the direction he is pushed and in the direction
determined before he was born. This is not our
idea of a progressive life.
It has been understood generally in
America that Germany’s preparation and classification
of her future workers and their placement in industry,
was more responsible than any other policy for Germany’s
place in the world market. British and American
manufacturers before the war urged the emulation of
German methods of education and a reorganization of
school systems more in conformity with the German.
The demand of the manufacturers for reorganization
came at a time when intelligent educators in America
were recognizing that some reorganization was necessary
to bring the school experience of children into relation
with their environment and with the actualities of
life. The industrial education movement in this
country was based on the German, and the German idea
was the dominating one. The movement here has
shown little-imagination as it adopted a system foreign
to America, instead of initiating schemes which represented
the aspirations of a free people.
Herman Schneider, of the University
of Cincinnati, has made one of the most intelligent
contributions in the adaptation of the German scheme
of education. He divides trades into two classes,
which he calls energizing and enervating. In
those which are energizing there is an element of
individual expression and opportunity for self-direction.
The enervating trades are wholly automatic, and induce
a lethargic state of mind and body. His comment
on the situation is: “We are rapidly dividing
mankind into a staff of mental workers and an army
of purely physical workers. The physical workers
are becoming more and more lethargic. The work
itself is not character building; on the contrary,
it is repressive and when self-expression comes, it
is hardly energizing mentally. The real menace
lies in the fact that in a self-governing industrial
community the minds of the majority are in danger
of becoming less capable of sound and serious thought
because of lack of continuous constructive exercise
in earning a livelihood.”
Professor Schneider undertakes to
enrich this barren soil by alternating the time of
pupils between the shop or store and the school, thus
cooerdinating the worker’s experience, with the
assistance of schoolmasters who go into the shops
and follow the processes the pupils are engaged in
and who see that the experience of the week in the
shop is amplified and supplemented in the school.
The arrangement also provides that the pupils shall
be taken through the various shop processes in the
course of apprenticeship. The experience while
it lasts may have educational value for the pupil.
But in spite of what it may or may not hold, for the
general run of pupils it leads up a blind alley because
the apprenticeship does not fulfill the promise which
apprenticeship supposedly holds out. That is,
the pupil, when he becomes a worker, will be thrown
back into some factory groove where his experience
as an apprentice cannot be used, where he is closed
off from the chance to develop and use the knowledge
or training he received. If, as Dean Schneider
asserts, “we are rapidly dividing mankind into
a staff of mental workers and an army of purely physical
workers,” and if “we cannot reverse our
present economic order of things,” then any
apprenticeship, even this brave effort of his, is a
pseudo-apprenticeship and even in the most energizing
of the trades leads the pupil nowhere in particular.
Even the skilled trade of locomotive engineering,
which Dean Schneider classes as the most highly energized
of trades, does not escape. As a spokesman for
the Brotherhood of Locomotive Engineers observes:
“The big electrical engines which are being
introduced in the railroad system are rapidly eliminating
the factors of judgment on the part of the engineer
and transforming that highly skilled trade into an
automatic exercise.”
The one-time value of a trade apprenticeship
to a youth was that it furnished the background for
mastery of machine processes; but apprenticeship under
modern factory methods can do no more than make a
youth a good servant to machines. The Schneider
system fills, as well as can be filled, a scheme of
apprenticeship in conformity with the prevailing shop
organization and requirements, but it is not a fulfillment
for youth; it is not educational. There is no
progression from apprenticeship to industrial control;
no chance to use the knowledge gained where opportunity
for participation in administration and reorganization
of industry is cut off. The best of trades is
a blind alley, educationally speaking.
However abortive such an effort as
Dean Schneider’s might be in giving workers
opportunity to enrich their experience for their own
reconstructing purposes, it offered the pupils more
content and better training than the ordinary school
drill in its colorless and vapid subject matter.
This fact is necessary to bear in mind, but it should
not obscure the even more significant fact that the
blighting character of industry is due to its motivation,
which is wealth exploitation and not wealth creation.
All of the industrial educational experiments have
succumbed to the fatalism involved in the adaptation
of their experiments to that fact.
A staff of investigators, who made
a year’s survey of the industries of Cleveland
with a view of determining what measures should be
adopted by the school system of the city to prepare
young people for wage earning occupation and to provide
supplementary trade training for those already employed,
concluded that the choice of occupations should be
governed primarily by economic considerations; that
even from the point of view of the school, educational
factors could not take precedence over economic.
They said: “The primary considerations
in the intelligent selection of a vocation relate to
wages, steadiness of employment, health risks, opportunity
for advancement, apprenticeship conditions, union
regulations and the number of chances there are for
getting into it. These things are fundamental,
and any one of them may well take precedence over
the matter of whether the tastes of the future wage
earner run to wood, brick, stone or steel.”
This conclusion is fatalistic, but
it is a brave one. It does not fall back on weak
substitutes for reality; it does not throw the glamor
of history and the aesthetics of industry around trades
with the poor hope that they make up for the content
which is not there; it does not foster the assumption
that training in technique of industry or physical
science can enrich, under the circumstances, the worker’s
experience to any important extent. It accepts
the bald truth that all the material classed as cultural
will count for nothing of value in a factory worker’s
life in comparison with the highest possible wage in
the most enervating of industries. It stresses
this highly important factor, as it should, but merely
as a physical necessity. There is vital education
in the consciousness of self-support, in the consciousness
that one is earning the living one gets. But under
present conditions the educational experience of wage
recompense is not so significant as it might be if
it measured the value of the labor performed; if it
paid the worker according to his needs, and if he
gave in return for the wage according to his ability.
The Gary school system is a notable
effort in public school education to fulfill children’s
desire for productive experience. It is in striking
contrast to the German scheme as it is based on processes
which have educational force and significance.
In saying this I differentiate between training for
industry and participation in the industrial activity
which is an organic part of the life of the children
and of the community. The children are an actual
part of the repair and construction working force
on Gary school buildings and on the equipment.
As the children are involved in the upkeep of a school
it becomes their school. They experience the responsibility
of maintaining the school plant, not by some artificial
scheme of participation, but by the actual application
of trade standards and acquired technique to operations
which have for them and those with whom they live
important significance. They gain in their work
a first hand knowledge of industrial processes and
activity. In conjunction with skilled mechanics
they work on the carpentry, the plumbing, the masonry,
the installation of electricity used in the school
building. They do the school printing and accounting.
The children’s life in these
schools is an experience in industry where there is
nothing to hide, no trade secrets to keep back.
The children have the full opportunity of seeing their
work through to its completion and understanding its
purpose and recognising its value and use. It
provides more than any other school system a liberal
field for productive endeavor. But the Gary schools
are not industry; they are a world apart; they represent,
as all schools are supposed to, moments sacred to
education and growth. They are not subjected to
the test of cooerdination in the world of industry.
They give the children a respect for productive enterprise
that should be invaluable later in effecting their
resistance to the prostitution of their creative power.
They do not give them experience in the administrative
side of industry for which the children of high school
age are ready and in need. But in an admirable
way they subordinate training in technique to purpose
and give the children the experience of exercising
control over their own industrial activity. As
an industrial experience for children of grammar school
age, it is richer than any other school system which
has been developed.
The industrial education of Germany
which was recommended for our adoption and which we
have emulated to an alarming degree in our industrial
towns, imposes prevailing methods of industry and technique
of factory processes as final and determined.
As industrial history and technique are taught in
the schools, in effect they bind the children to the
current industrial practice and to the current conditions.
They stifle imagination and discourage the concept
that industry is an evolving process. The effect
of technical training in the German continuation schools
(and the tendency is the same in our own industrial
education courses) is to teach the children that the
methods and processes as they are carried forward in
the shop are right. No question of their
validity is raised in the school. They are accepted
by the children in the spirit of authority which the
school carries, as they would not be so finally accepted
by them in the shop. The impress of a developed
curriculum, connected with an active trade experience,
that is, a trade in which the children are at work,
like the curriculum of a continuation school, is greater
than the curriculum which has been evolved for its
abstract cultural values. As the curriculum cooerdinates
shop and school activities and as it fails at the
same time to stimulate inquiry on the part of the
pupil into industrial or special trade processes as
they are practiced in the shop, it becomes a positive,
inhibiting factor in the intellectual life of the
children. The perfection of an industrial school
room equipment with its trade samples, its charts and
maps, its literature, relating to the extension, of
trade and of commerce, has the tendency like the curriculum
to impose on the children the weight of accomplishment,
if this equipment is not used to stimulate inquiry
and experiment in industry as the ever fresh field
for adventure that it is. But the intention of
these industrial schools is to train the children
in the acceptance of processes and methods which are
established. Nowhere, in no country, has this
intention been so successfully realized, because nowhere
has it been so successfully organized as in Germany
through its continuation school system. And nowhere
as in Germany are the people so successfully subjected
to an institutionalized life as it has been worked
out in the light of modern technology and business.
There are other and special reasons
why the best of industrial education experiments in
America have not met with greater hospitality.
The average American parent still believes that a boy
“rises” in the industrial world, not as
they once thought through his ability as a workman.
The men of their acquaintance who have been successful,
have attained wealth and position, not as a rule through
their mastery of technique or their skill in a trade;
they have not come by their promotion merely on account
of good workmanship, but through influence. It
might be that they had had their “chance”
through a relative or successful business man, or it
might be that they “got next” to a politician,
who required no other qualification than “smartness.”
A boy in a telegraph or a lawyer’s office has
a better opportunity to reach influence than a boy
in a workshop. The scholastic requirement for
such advancement as these vocations contemplate, is
provided for in the established school program of the
lower grades. A certain display of a few historical
and literary facts beside a facility in reading, writing,
and arithmetic are the qualifications which average
parents believe are the necessary ones for their children’s
advancement. And, taking the situation in general
as it is, they are right, and will be as long as the
whole social system discounts productive effort and
rewards exploitation of productive enterprise.
Obviously false from an educational
point of view as these school standards are, they
are true to the facts, to the actual situation which
the parents have to face. The wave of popular
opposition to a reorganization of the schools for
a preparation of the children for factory life expresses
the original conception of popular education among
sovereign people. The common school system exists,
it is still assumed, to fit the children to rule their
own lives; to give them an equipment which will protect
them from a servitude to others. Its ability
to do this had not been questioned a generation ago
and, theoretical as its original intention is to-day,
its traditional purpose to develop the power of each
child to govern his destiny, holds over. If training
children to read, write and count, training them in
facts relating to history and language, did not, as
it had been hoped, lay the world at the feet of the
children, training them in factory processes, parents
felt competent to declare, laid the children at the
feet of exploiters. That is where in any case,
in the light of common experience, they might expect
them to land. To reorganize the schools with
that possibility in mind was for the parents a surrender
of their gambling chance.
The promoters of industrial education,
with some success, have made it clear to the community
generally that parents were giving heavy odds in their
gamble, but these promoters would have made this more
obvious to parents if they could have shown that the
assets accruing from the new school curriculum increased
more materially than has the wage earning capacity
of their children. The results for individual
children are not sufficiently striking to advertise
the departure, and if they were, the departure would
not warrant the endorsement of the community on the
ground of the higher wage, as wages are fixed by competition.
They are advanced by a general increase in productivity.
But the increase that occurs through more efficient
methods in productive enterprise is not a real increase;
it does not relatively affect the social or economic
position of the wage earner.
In the last analysis, the wage return
is not an educator’s criterion, in spite of
the pragmatic recommendation of the Cleveland Survey.
The Survey’s recommendation for a reorganization
of the school system is based on the belief that the
school is, or should be, an integral expression or
reflection of the life of the community; that to function
vitally it must be contemporaneous with that life,
as are all serviceable institutions. As a school
reflects the life of a community it enriches the experience
of the children and endows them with the knowledge
and power to deal with environment. When a school
system disregards, as our established system does,
the entire reorganization of the industrial world,
it stultifies growth and cultivates at the same time
an artificial concept of life, a false sense of values.
The German system of industrial education has recognized
the reorganization of the industrial world, but this
recognition has meant the sacrifice of individual
life and development; it has come to mean in short
the prostitution of a people and the creation of a
Frankenstein.
None of our industrial educational
systems or vocational guidance experiments disclose
the full content of the industrial life nor do they
give the children the knowledge or power to deal with
it. The general dissatisfaction with these school
movements is that they neither prostitute the schools
in the interest of the employers nor endow the children
with power to meet their own problems. The training
in technique which they supply has a bearing on the
every day life around them which stories of Longfellow’s
life have not. But that technique, divorced as
it is from its purpose, its use or final disposition,
is as valueless as a crutch for a man without arms.
An elaboration of technology through instruction in
the general principles of physical science, industrial
and political history and the aesthetics of industry
only emphasizes the absence of the really significant
factors. The conspicuously absent factors in all
industrial educational schemes are those which give
men the ability to control industry. No work
in subject matter is educational which does not in
intention or in fact give the person involved the ability
to participate in the administration of industry,
or the ability to judge the extent of his mastery
over the subject. Industrial educational schemes,
even the best of them, leave the pupils helpless before
their subject. As they furnish them with a certain
dexterity and acquaintance with processes and a supply
of subject matter necessarily more or less isolated,
the pupils gain a sense of the power of the subject
to control them, rather than an experience in their
power to master the subject. The industrial school
emphasizes the fact that the administration and disposition
of wealth production is no concern of those versed
in the technique of fabrication.
Many educators appreciate the lack
of content provided by industrial school systems as,
with weak emphasis, they undertake to embroider the
system with history and aesthetics of textiles or other
raw material which the workers handle, or introduce
the story of past processes. As this furbishing
of impoverished industry fails dismally to add content,
it succeeds in emphasizing the actual poverty that
exists.
Dr. Stanley Hall makes the suggestion
that books on the leading trades should be written
to stimulate the interest and intelligence of the
young who are engaged in industry or preparing to become
the wage earners of the trades. In speaking of
“the urgent necessity now of books on the leading
trades addressed to the young,” he says; “The
leather industry, particularly boot and shoe manufacture,
is perhaps the most highly specialised of all in the
sense that an operator may work a lifetime in any
one of the between three and four score processes
through which a shoe passes and know little of all
the rest. Now the Shoe Book should describe
hides and leathers, tanning, old and new
methods, with a little of the natural history of the
animals, describe the process of taking them, of curing
and shipping, each stage in the factory, designating
those processes that require skill and those that
do not, and so on to packing, labeling and shipping,
with descriptions showing the principles of the chief
machines and labor-saving devices, at any rate so
far as they are not trade secrets; it should include
a glance at markets, prices, effects of business advance,
depression and strikes, perhaps something about the
hygiene of the foot, about bootblacks and what is done
for them, history of the festivals and organizations
from St. Crispin and the guilds down, tariffs, syndicates,
societies, statistics, social conditions in shoe towns,
nationality of operatives, all these could
be concisely set forth to show the dimensions, the
centers of interest, the social and commercial relations
of the business, etc. What is not yet realized
is that all these things could and should be put down
in print and picture, almost as if it were to be issued
as a text-book or a series of them; all of this could
be done to bring out the very high degree of culture
value now latent in the subject. Just this is
what pedagogues do not and will not see, and what even
shoe men fail to realize; viz., that the story
of their craft rightly told, would tend to give it
some degree of professional and humanistic interest
and dignity which the most unskilled and transient
employee would feel. It would foster an esprit
de corps, pride in membership and above all an intelligent
view of the whole field that would make labor more
valuable and more loyal. This material, once gathered,
should be used in some form in all industrial schools
and courses in towns where this industry dominates.
It would bring a wholesome sense of corporeity, historic
and economic unity, would give a touch of the old
guild spirit and more power to see both sides on the
part of both employers and workmen. Nothing is
so truly educational in the deepest psychological
sense of that word as useful information vitalized
by individual and vocational interest.”
Dr. Hall’s idea of a Book of
Industry might have emanated from the heart of Mr.
Carnegie. With the same benign detachment he seems
to have mused at his desk about the shoe industry
and the people engaged in it. It would not take
more than a passing acquaintance with the girls and
men in shoe manufacturing towns to know that if there
was established a village library equipped with the
history of shoes, the aesthetics of shoes, shoe economics,
shoe technology, and shoe hygiene, not one of the
girls or men who worked in the shoe factories would
darken its doors to read about shoes. They would
not for this simple reason; the workers’ “individual
and vocational interest” does not exist.
They would say that they already knew more than they
cared to about shoes. No literature could add
culture or dignity to the job of stitching vamps
for all the working hours and days of a wage earner’s
year, while there is no experience of cultural value
in the occupation, divided as the making of a shoe
is into some ninety operations, and distributed among
ninety workers. Dr. Hall’s suggestion that
a Shoe Book be written is a good suggestion but he
must supply a better basis for a reader’s interest
than industry has given him, that is, industry as
it is now administered. He cannot impose culture
or dignity through books on a trade which is prostituted
by business for profiteering. If the purpose of
the Shoe Book was to create the glamor that was intended
around the present day arrangement of making shoes,
it would be a false contribution in schoolroom equipment;
it would be as pernicious as other literature that
introduced an artificial note into a real and living
experience like industry.
The most romantic account of shoe
making will do nothing to bridge the gulf between
capital and labor as Dr. Hall seems so confidently
to believe it should. The problem is not so simple
or so easily disposed of. As Dr. Hall himself
says: “As long as workmen are regarded as
parts of the machinery to be dumped on the scrap heap
as soon as younger and stronger hands can be found,
the very point of view needful for the correct solution
of vocational education, is wanting." Dr. Hall
recognizes some evils which are inherent in the present
scheme of industry and which are antagonistic to growth,
but neither he nor any of the advocates of the German
methods of industrial education make provisions in
their educational schemes for eliminating the aspect
which contemplates the dumping of workers on scrap
heaps. None of the advocates view the equipment
of workers for industry in terms radically different
from the terms in which they are viewed by business
men; they offer them technique and matter of insignificance
and indirection; they make no suggestion or move to
open up the adventure of industry for the worker’s
actual participation in it; they accept the organization
of industry which excludes their participation as
an unalterable fact; even unalterable as an experience
in the prevocational schemes of education.
National, state and local campaigns
have been carried on in America during the last fifteen
years for the protection of childhood and youth.
They have been on the whole successful in their purpose
to get children out of factories and stores and into
schools. It was an embarrassment to the pioneers
in the campaign to find that the children were against
them; that they preferred factory or commercial life
to the schools. The evidence of this preference
was their wholesale exodus from schools when they
reached an age where they were acceptable to employers
or where they were not prevented by law. Back
of the exodus, universal as it is, there is an urge
of elemental force. A common accounting for it,
the nearest at hand, is that parents of working class
children are penurious; or that they are too ignorant
to understand the deteriorating effect of factory life
on children; or that they are too hard pressed in
their physical needs to consider the best interest
of the children. This reason given for the failure
of the schools to supply children with matter of interest
or significance to them, explained only why children
did not want to stay in school; it did not explain
their eagerness to enter industry. None of the
reasons accounted for the zest of the children for
wage earning occupation.
The failure of the schools to hold
the children gave educators who recognized the artificial
character of school curricula, their best reason for
introducing matter relating to industrial life.
The children’s preference was indeed a valuable
indication where reality or real subject matter would
be found. The change off from old school subject
matter to instruction in methods of industry was a
logical experiment. But the movement for industrial
education was not inspired by a watchful sympathetic
observation of children’s needs; it was in line
with the general theory, more or less accepted, that
schools should be a reflection of the children’s
environment; it was in line with the demand of employers
for efficient workers either equipped for specific
processes or adaptable to factory methods.
If the promoters of industrial education
had been observers of children from twelve to fourteen
and sixteen years, they would have found that as they
left school they were eager not for skill in technical
processes, not for wages, not for greater freedom of
association in adult life, not for any of these alone,
but for all of these as they were a part of the adventure
of the adult world in which they lived. “We
have neglected to study the most vital thing in the
situation, namely the zests of the young ... we have
not taken account of the nature of the great upheaval
at the dawn of the teens, which marks the pubescent
ferment and which requires distinct change in the
matter and method of education. This instinct
is far stronger and has more very ostensive outcrops
than in any other age and land, and it is less controlled
by the authority of school or the home. It is
a period of very rapid, if not fulminating psychic
expansion. It is the natal hour of new curiosities,
when adult life first begins to exert its potent charm.
It is an age of exploration, of great susceptibility,
plasticity, eagerness, pervaded by the instinct to
try and plan in many different directions."
Children of this adolescent time would
respond more readily to school instruction, related
to the adult activities which held their interest
and connected in some way with their own conception
of their functioning in the adult world. Courses
of study in processes of industry and practice in
the technique of those processes would have actual
bearing on the environment of which they were eager
to be a part.
But instruction in mechanical processes
and practice in technique of manufacture are the husks
of industry when divorced from the planning, the management,
the examination of problems, the determination of the
value of goods in their use and in their place in the
market, the division of labor throughout an enterprise,
the relation of all persons involved to each other
and to the product. The schools with their industrial
education courses do not undertake to supply their
young people with an opportunity to plan; they are
true reflections of factory existence as they eliminate
all the adventure of industry, the opportunity for
experiment and discovery; they do not satisfy the high
impulse of young people to be of use, to be a part
of the world of work. The spirit of the schools
is preparation for something to come; the spirit of
the children is in the present, and the present pressing
impulse of adolescence is to share adult responsibilities.
The impulse of youth to take its place
in adult life is exploited by industry and repressed
or perverted by a system of education which fits the
children into a system of industry without giving them
the insight and power to effect adjustments.
The actual job in a trade has satisfying features
which the school lacks. It pays wages. That
fact for eager children is estimated beyond its purchasing
power. For them it is an acknowledgment, a very
real one, that they have been admitted, are wanted
in the big world where they are impelled by their
psychic needs, to enter. It places them more nearly
on an equality with the older members of their family
and entitles them to consideration which was not given
them as dependent children. They learn shortly
of how little account they are to the boss employer
but they are establishing all the time a new basis
of contact and a new place in their personal relations;
they are establishing it because they have economic
value in the world outside of home as well as in it.
The industrial schools and the old
type of schools are both adult schemes of getting
children ready for adult life, not by experiencing
it, but by doing certain things well so that they can
be entrusted to do later on, what adults in their
wisdom have decided that they are to do. But
they fail to prepare children for the future as they
fail to supply the children’s present urgent
needs. They use the period for ulterior purposes;
purposes ulterior to the period of growth with which
they are dealing. As they use this period for
another time than its own, in effect they exploit
it. Without consciousness of the fact so far
as the children are concerned, the schools exploit
this period of growth as effectively as the employers
reap the profits of child labor. Employers as
beneficiaries have more reason than the schools for
diverting youth from its own purposes, as they are
under the necessity of a price system which is competitive.
The schools as well as industry use up the placticity
of youth; they kill off the eagerness of children
to explore and plan, and cast it aside for more consequential
ends.
The consequential ends in America,
we have seen, have been less clearly defined than
in Germany. Within a year, the United States has
become conscious as a nation of place and power, conscious
that it is to play a part with the other states of
the world. In playing this part, will it retain
its rôle of servant of the people, or will it assume
with its new world dignity the rôle, if not of master,
then of leadership? If still servant, will it
serve more efficiently than it has our dominant institution,
industry? If the silent partnership between business
and the state is strengthened, will not the promoters
of industry be in a better position than before to
appeal through the state, through the patriotism intensified
by our newly acquired world position, for a more universal
and a systematized adaptation of workers in industry?
The schools in their disinterested capacity, disinterested,
that is, in the profits of production, it would seem
could be used most effectively toward this end.
German manufacture made that clear to American manufacture
before the war. It also must be remembered that
it was Prussian pride for imperial position that inspired
the complete and efficient surrender of the German
schools to the needs of the German manufacturers.
America is, of course, “different.”
All peoples are. But so is our position in the
world different from what it was. Our position
is not now, nor could it be, the German position.
Our past is different, and that will continuously
have its effect on our future. But we are facing
a great period of change, and the strongest forces
in the country are the industrial, and the strongest
leaders are the financiers. What the financiers
and industrial managers most want is efficient, docile
labor. The German system of education, in spite
of the fact that we are different, might conceivably
have that effect on the youth of this country.
Under the pressure of industrial rivalry after the
war, under the pressure of an imperial industrial policy,
it may be that the people of the country will yield
to the introduction of a scheme of education which
it has been proved elsewhere can fit children better
than any other known scheme into a system of mass
production.
It is clear that industry could set
up models of behavior more successfully in the name
of education than in its own, and to the extent American
children come up to these models the more employable
they would be from the standpoint of business.
If the pressure is sufficiently strong the people
may yield to the introduction of a system of compulsory
continuation schools similar to those of Germany.
If they do, I believe they will eventually fail.
But there is danger through loss of energy and loss
of purpose in their introduction. Is it impossible
for us to hold to our native experimental habits of
life and attain standards of workmanship? Is
it possible to realize the full strength of associated
effort and at the same time advance wealth production?
Germany’s industrial supremacy
was due, as Professor Veblen shows, to the fact that
machine industry was imposed ready-made on a people
whose psychology was feudal. The schools of Germany,
an essential part of her industrial enterprise, were
organized on the servility of the people. We
now know what building as Germany has built her educational
and industrial system on the weakness of a people means.
We are in the process of discovering whether in sacrificing
the expansion of her people she can secure a permanent
expansion of her Empire. It would seem the better
part of statesmanship in America after the war to
build industrially on the strength of our people and
not on the weakness of another. It is the business
of educators to point out the danger and to discover
whether efficiency may not be gained in the country
by giving children in their adolescent period the impulse
for production and high standards of work, not for
the sake of the state, but for themselves, for the
sake of the community, out of love of work
and for the value of its service.