THE CAREER OF REASON: INTRODUCTION
The foregoing analysis of human behavior
might thus be briefly summarized. We found that
man is born a creature with certain tendencies to
act in certain definite ways, tendencies which he
largely possesses in common with the lower animals.
We found also that man could learn by trial and error,
that his original instinctive equipment could be modified.
Thus far in his mental life man is indistinguishable
from the beasts. But man’s peculiar capacity,
it appeared, lay in his ability to think, to control
his actions in the light of a future, to choose one
response rather than another because of its consequences,
which he could foresee and prefer. This capacity
for reflection, for formulating a purpose and being
able to obtain it, we found to be practical in its
origins, but persisting on its own account in the
disinterested inquiry of philosophy and science and
the free imaginative construction of art. And
in all man’s behavior, whether on the plane of
instinct, habit, or reflection, we found action to
be accompanied by emotion, by love and hate, anger
and awe, which might at once impede action by confusing
it, or sustain it by giving it a vivid and compelling
motive.
The second part of the book was devoted
to an analysis of the various specific traits which
human beings display and the consequences that these
have in men’s relations with one another.
Under certain conditions, one or another of these
may become predominant; in particular historical conditions,
one or another of them may have a high social value
or the reverse. These traits vary in different
individuals; in any of them, a man may be totally
defective or abnormally developed. But taken
in general, they constitute the changeless pattern
of human nature, and fix the conditions and the limits
of action.
But while these universal traits determine
what man may do, and fix definitively the boundaries
of human possibility, within these limits the race
has a wide choice of ideals and attainments.
The standards of what man will and should do, within
the boundaries of the nature which is his inheritance,
are to be found not in his original impulses, but in
his mind and imagination. The human being is
gifted with the ability to imagine a future more desirable
than the present, and to contrive ingeniously in behalf
of anticipated or imagined goods.
These anticipated goods we call ideals,
and these ideals arise, in the last analysis, out
of the initial and inborn hungers and cravings of
men. “Intellect is of the same flesh and
blood with all the instincts, a brother whose superiority
lies in his power to appreciate, harmonize, and save
them all.” The function of reason is not
to set itself over against men’s original desires,
but to envisage ideals and devise instruments whereby
they may all, so far as nature allows, be fulfilled.
Man’s reason, then, which has
its roots in his instincts, is the means of their
harmonious fulfillment. It attempts, in the various
fields of experience, to effect an adjustment between
man’s competing desires, and between man and
his environment. If instincts were left each
to its own free course, they would all be frustrated;
if man did not learn reflectively to control his environment,
and to make it subserve his own ends, he would be
a helpless pygmy soon obliterated by the incomparably
more powerful forces of Nature.
These various attempts of man to effect
an adjustment of his passions with one another, and
his life to his environment, may be described as the
“Career of Reason.” In this career
man has formulated many ideals, not a small number
of which have led him into error, disillusion, and
unhappiness. Sometimes they have misled him by
promising him fulfillments that were in the nature
of things unattainable. They have added to the
real evils of life a longing after impossible goods,
goods which an informed intelligence would early have
dismissed as unattainable. Man has disappointed
himself by counting on joys which, had he been less
incorrigibly addicted to imaginative illusions, he
should never have expected. Sometimes he has
framed ideals which could be fulfilled, but only at
the expense of a large proportion of natural and irrepressible
human desires. Such, for example, have been the
one-sided ascetic ideals of Stoicism or Puritanism,
which in their attempt to give order and form to life,
crush and distort a considerable portion of it.
The same is true of mysticism which seeks frequently
to attain life by altogether denying its instinctive
animal basis. Yet though reason has led men astray,
it is the only and ultimate hope of man’s happiness.
It is responsible for whatever success man has had
in mastering the turmoil of his own passions and the
obstacles of an environment “which was not made
for him but in which he grew.” It has given
point and justice to Swinburne’s exultant boast:
“Glory to man in the highest!
For man is the master of things!”
This Career of Reason has taken various
parallel fulfillments, and in each of them man has
in varying degrees attained mastery. Religion
arose as one of the earliest ways by which man attempted
to win for himself a secure place in the cosmic order.
Science, in its earliest forms hardly distinguishable
from religion, is man’s persistent attempt to
discover the nature of things, and to exploit that
discovery for his own good. Art is again an instance
of man’s march toward mastery. Beginning,
in the broadest sense, in the industrial arts, in
agriculture and handicrafts, it passes, as it were
by accident, from the necessary to the beautiful.
Having in his needful business fortuitously created
beautiful objects, man comes to create them intentionally,
both for their own sake and for the sheer pleasure
of creation.
Finally in morals men have endeavored
to construct for themselves codes of conduct, ideals
of life, in which no possible good should be needlessly
or recklessly sacrificed, and in which men might live
together as happily as is permitted by the nature
which is at once their life and their habitation.
The Career of Reason in these various fields we shall
briefly trace and describe. We must expect to
find, as in any career, however successful, failures
along with the triumphs, and, as in any notable career
still unfinished, possibility and great promise.
Man’s reason and imagination have a long past;
they have also an indefinite future. Man has in
the name of reason made many errors; but to reason
he owes his chief success, and with increasing experience
he may be expected to attain continually to a more
certain and effective wisdom. With these provisos,
let us address ourselves to the Career of Reason,
beginning with religion.