ART AND THE AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE
ART VERSUS NATURE. In
the Career of Reason man has gradually learned to
control the world in which he lives in the interests
of his own welfare as he imaginatively contemplated
it. Deliberate control has been made necessary
because of the fact that man is born into a world
which was not made for him, but in which he must,
if anywhere, grow; in a world which was not designed
to fulfill his desires, but where alone his desires
can find fulfillment. Art may thus, in the broadest
sense, be set over against Nature. It is the activity
by which man realizes ideals. He may realize
them practically, as when he builds a house which
he has first imagined, or reaps a harvest in anticipation
of which he has first sown the seeds. He may
realize them imaginatively, as when in color, form,
or sound he creates some desiderated beauty out of
the crude miscellaneous materials of experience.
Art, in the broad sense of control or direction of
Nature, arises in the double fact of man’s instinctive
activities and desires and the inadequacy of the environment
as it stands to afford them satisfaction. Because
nature is not considerate of his needs, man must himself
take forethought, and devise means by which the forces
and the materials of Nature may be exploited to his
own good. And the realization of this forethought
is made possible through the fact that natural conditions
do lend themselves to modification. Nature, though
indifferent to man’s welfare, is yet partly
congruous with it. While the wind blows careless
of the good or ill it does to him, yet man may learn
by means of windmills or sailboats to turn the wind
to his own interest. Though the river may flow
on forever, oblivious to the men that come and go
along its shores, yet the passing generations may
transform this undeliberate flowing into the power
that yields them clothing, machinery, and transportation.
All civilization is, as Mill says, an exhibition of
Art or Contrivance; it is illustrated by
the junction by bridges of shores
which Nature had made separate, the draining of Nature’s
marshes, the excavation of her wells, the dragging
to light of what she has buried at immense depths in
the earth; the turning away of her thunderbolts by
lightning rods; of her inundations by embankments,
of her oceans by breakwaters.
By irrigation man has learned to make
the “wilderness blossom as the rose.”
By railways, telegraphs, and telephones, he has learned
to minimize the obstacles that time and space offer
to the fulfillment of his desires. By controlling,
by means of education and social organization, his
own instincts in the light of the purposes he would
attain, by studying “the secret processes of
Nature,” man has learned to make the world a
fit habitation for himself. To dig, to plough,
to sow, to reap, are instances of the means whereby
man has applied intelligent control to his half-friendly,
half-hostile environment.
Man’s deliberate control of
Nature arises thus under the sharp pressure of practical
necessity. Man is inherently active, but, as
pointed out in an earlier connection, his activity
takes coherent and consecutive form primarily under
the compulsion of satisfying his physical wants, of
finding food, clothing, and shelter. The greater
part of human energy, certainly under primitive conditions,
is devoted to maintaining a precarious equilibrium
among the mysterious and terrifying forces of a half-understood
environment. There is not much time for leisure,
play, or art, where food is a continuously urgent
problem, where one’s shelter is likely to be
destroyed by storm or wind, where one is threatened
incessantly by beasts of prey, and, as primitive man
supposed, by capricious supernatural powers.
Under such circumstances, life is largely spent in
instrumental or imperative pursuits. Action is
fixed by necessity. It is controlled with immediate
and urgent reference to the business of keeping alive.
There is scarcely time for the activity of art, which
is spontaneous and free.
In civilized life, also, the greater
part of human energy must be spent in necessary or
instrumental business. Men must, as always, be
fed, clothed, and housed, and the fulfillment of these
primary human demands absorbs the greater part of
the waking hours of the majority of mankind. Our
civilization is predominantly industrial; it is devoted
almost entirely to the transforming of the world of
nature into products for the gratification of the
physical wants of men. These wants have, of course,
become much complicated and refined: men wish
not only to live, but to live commodiously and well.
They want not merely a roof over their heads, but a
pleasant and comfortable house in which to live.
They want not merely something to stave off starvation,
but palatable foods. In the satisfaction of these
increasingly complicated demands a great diversity
of industries arises. With every new want to
be fulfilled, there is a new occupation, pursued not
for its own sake, but for the sake of the good which
it produces. There are industrial leaders, of
course, who find in the development and control of
the productive energies of thousands of men, in the
manipulation of immense natural resources, satisfactions
analogous to that of the fine artist. But for
most men engaged in the routine operations of industry,
the work they do is clearly not pursued on its own
account. Industry, viewed in the total context
of the activities of civilization, is a practical
rather than a fine art. Its ideal is efficiency,
which means economy of effort. Its interest is
primarily in producing many goods cheaply.
THE EMERGENCE OF THE FINE ARTS.
In the sharp struggle of man with his environment,
those instincts survived which were of practical use.
The natural impulses with which a human being is at
birth endowed, are chiefly those which enable him
to cope successfully and efficiently with his environment.
But even in primitive life, so exuberant and resilient
is human energy that it is not exhausted by necessary
labors. The plastic arts, for example, began
in the practical business of pottery and weaving.
The weaver and the potter who have acquired skill
and who have a little more vitality than is required
for turning out something that is merely useful, turn
out something that is also beautiful. The decorations
which are made upon primitive pottery exhibit the excess
vitality and skill of the virtuoso. Similarly,
religious ritual, which, as we have seen, arises in
practical commerce with the gods, comes to be in itself
cherished and beautiful. The chants which are
prescribed invocations of divinity, become songs intrinsically
interesting to singer and listener alike; the dance
ceases to be merely a necessary religious form and
becomes an occasion of beauty and delight. Jane
Harrison has shown in detail how ritual arises out
of practical need, and art out of ritual. Thus
the Greek drama had its beginnings in Greek religion;
the incidental beauty of the choruses of the Greek
festivals developed into the eventual tragic art of
AEschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides. Ceasing to
be a practical invocation to the gods it became an
artistic enterprise in and for itself. Repeatedly
we find in primitive life that activity is not exhausted
in agriculture, hunting, and handicraft, or in a desperate
commerce with divinity. Harvest becomes a festival,
pottery becomes an opportunity for decoration, and
prayer, for poetry. Even in primitive life men
find the leisure to let their imaginations loiter over
these intrinsically lovely episodes in their experience.
The potter may be more interested
in making a beautifully moulded and decorated vessel
than merely in turning out a thing of use; the maker
of baskets may come to “play with his materials,”
to make baskets not so much for their usefulness as
for the possible beauty of their patterns. When
this interest in beauty becomes highly developed,
and when circumstances permit, the fine arts arise.
The crafts come to be practiced as intrinsically interesting
employments of the creative imagination. The
moulding of miscellaneous materials into beautiful
forms becomes a beloved habitual practice.
The context in which art appears in
primitive life is paralleled in civilized society.
The energies of men are still largely consumed in
necessary pursuits. Men must, as of old, by the
inadequacy of the natural order in which they find
themselves, find means by which to live; and, being
by nature constituted so that they must live together,
they must find ways of living together justly and
harmoniously. “Industry,” writes
Santayana, “merely gives to Nature that form
which, if more thoroughly humane, she might already
have possessed for our benefit.” It is
creative in so far as it transforms matter from its
crude indifferent state to forms better adapted to
human ideals. It makes cotton into cloth, wool
into clothing, wheat into flour, leather into shoes,
coal into light and power, iron into skyscrapers.
It is devoted to annulling the discrepancies between
nature and human nature. It turns refractory
materials and obdurate forces into commodious goods
and useful powers.
But, in the broadest sense, industry
is a means to an end. Interesting and attractive
it may well become, as when a bookbinder or a printer
takes a craftsman’s proud delight in the manner
in which he performs his work, and in the quality
of its product. But the industrial arts, for the
most part, serve more ultimate purposes. It is
imaginable that Nature might have provided clothing,
food, and shelter ready to our hand. It is questionable
whether under such circumstances men would out of
deliberate choice continue industries which are now
made imperative through necessity. The mines and
the stockyards are necessary rather than beautiful
or intrinsically attractive occupations. But
in the world of fact, those things which are necessary
to us are not ready to our hand. Our civilization
is predominantly industrial, and must be so, if the
billion and a half inhabitants of our world are to
be maintained by the resources at our command.
Nevertheless despite the absorption
of a large proportion of contemporary society in activities
pursued not for their own sakes, but for the goods
which are their fruits, there is still, as it were,
energy left over. This excess vitality may, as
it does for most men, take the form of mere unorganized
play or recreation. But not so for those born
with a singular gift for realizing in color or form
or sound the ideal values which they have imagined.
For these “play” is creative production.
The fine arts are, in a sense, the play of the race.
They are the fruits of such energy as is, through
some fortunate accident of temperament or circumstance,
not caught up in the routine and mechanics of industry
or the trivialities of sport or pleasure. They
are human activities, freed from the limitations imposed
by the exigencies of practical life, and controlled
only by the artist’s imagined visions. Creative
activity is most explicit and most successful in the
fine arts, because in these there are fewer obstacles
to the material realization of imagined perfections.
“The liberal arts bring to spiritual fruition
the matter which either nature or industry has prepared
and rendered propitious.”
The industrial arts are, as already
pointed out, man’s transformation of natural
resources to ideal uses. In the same way political
and social organization are human arts, enterprises,
at their best, in the moulding of men’s natures
to their highest possible realization. But in
the world of action, whether political or industrial,
there are incomparably greater hindrances to the realization
in practice of imagined goods than there are, at least
to the gifted, in the fine arts. Every ideal
for which men attempt to find fulfillment in the world
of action is subject to a thousand accidental deflections
of circumstance. Every enterprise involves conflicting
wills; the larger the enterprise, the more various
and probably the more conflicting the interests involved.
Social movements have their courses determined by
factors altogether beyond the control of their originators.
Statesmen can start wars, but cannot define their
eventual fruits. A man may found a political
party, and live to see it wander far from the ideal
which he had framed. But in the fine arts, to
the imaginatively and technically endowed, the materials
are prepared and controllable. In the hands of
a master, action does not wander from intent.
Language to the poet, for example, is an immediate
and responsive instrument; he can mould it precisely
to his ideal intention. The enterprise of poetry
is less dependent almost than any other undertaking
on the accidents of circumstance, outside the poet’s
initial imaginative resources. In music, even
so simple an instrument as a flute can yield perfection
of sound. The composer of a symphony can invent
a perpetual uncorroded beauty; the sculptor an immortality
of irrefutably persuasive form. This explains
in part why so many artists, of a reflective turn
of mind, are pessimists in practical affairs.
The world of action with its perpetual and pitiful
frustrations, failures, and compromises, seems incomparably
poor, paltry, and sordid, in comparison with the perfection
that is attainable in art.
Haunting foreshadowings of the temple
appear in the realm of imagination, in music, in architecture,
in the untroubled kingdom of reason, and in the golden
sunset magic of lyrics, where beauty shines and glows,
remote from the touch of sorrow, remote from the fear
of change, remote from the failures and disenchantment
of the world of fact. In the contemplation of
these things the vision of heaven will shape itself
in our hearts, giving at once a touchstone to judge
the world about us, and an inspiration by which to
fashion to our needs whatever is capable of serving
as a stone in the sacred temple.
The creative artist gives such form
to the miscellaneous materials at his disposal that
they give satisfaction not only to the senses or the
intellect, but to the imagination. What constitute
some of the chief elements in the aesthetic experience,
we shall presently examine. It must first be pointed
out that in general in the fine arts creative genius
has found ways of imaginatively attaining perfections
not usually accorded in the experiences of the senses,
in the life of society, or in the life of the mind.
The region called imagination has
pleasures more airy and luminous than those of sense,
more massive and rapturous than those of intelligence.
The values inherent in imagination, in instant intuition,
in sense endowed with form, are called aesthetic values;
they are found mainly in nature and in living beings,
but also in man’s artificial works, in images
evoked by language, and in the realm of sound.
The painter imagines and seeks to
realize hues and intensities of color more satisfying
and more suggestive than those commonly experienced
in nature, save in the occasional grace of sunset
on a mountain lake, or the miracle of moonlight on
the ocean. The artist takes his hints from nature,
but clothes the suggestions of sense with the values
and motives which exist only in his own mind and imagination.
A Turner sunset is, as Oscar Wilde points out, in
a sense incomparably superior to one provided by nature.
It not only gives the beautiful sensations to be had
in a landscape suffused with the sunset glow; it infuses
into this experience the passionate and penetrating
insight of a genius. The artist, to an extent,
imitates nature. But, if that were all he did,
he would be no more than a photographer. He pictures
nature, but gives it “tint and melody and breath”;
he gives it a value and significance derived from
his own imaginative vision. The musician combines
sounds more significant, ordered, and rhythmical than
those miscellaneous noises which, in ordinary experience,
beat indifferently or painfully upon our ears.
The poet selects words whose specific music, rhythmical
combinations, and lyrical context produce a something
more evocative, compelling, and euphonic than the
casual and raucous instrument of communication which
constitutes ordinary speech.
Not only do poets give imaginative
and ideal extensions to sense experience; they do
as much with and for social life. In the dreaming
of Utopias, in the building of the Perfect City, men
have found compensations for the imperfect cities
which have been their experiences on earth. They
build themselves in imagination a world where all
injustices are erased, where beauty is perennial,
where truth, courage, kindliness, and merriment are
the pervasive colors of life. In the activity
of creative art, man’s imagination has reached
out beyond the confines of nature and of history, and
built itself, in marble and in music, in lyrics and
in legends, hints of that enchanting possible, of
which the impoverished actual gives tentative and
tenuous hints.
In some men sensitivity to the imaginative
possibilities of the materials of Nature is so high,
that they can find satisfactory activity nowhere else
than in one or another of the fine arts. These
are the poets, the musicians, and the sculptors, who
seek to give realization in the arts in the technique
of which they are especially gifted, to that imagined
beauty by the intimate experience of which they live.
In one way or another the creative artist seeks to
give form and dimension to
“The light that never was on sea
or land,
The consecration and the poet’s
dream.”
This creative impulse may find its
realization, as already pointed out, in industry,
though, with the highly routine character of most
men’s occupations in present-day industrial
life, there is not much opportunity for imaginative
activity. That both work and happiness would
be promoted by the encouragement of the craftsman
ideal goes without saying. Whether or not it
is possible to utilize the creative impulses in the
processes of industry as now organized, there are instances
where the joy of craftsmanship may be exploited both
for the happiness of the worker and the good of the
work. The William Morris ideal of the artist-worker
may be hard to attain, but it is none the less desirable,
both for the sake of the worker and his work.
In science the uses of the imagination
have been frequently commented on, not least by scientists.
The patient collection of facts, the digging and measurement
and inquiry that characterize so much of scientific
investigation are not the whole of it. Inference,
the forming of a generalization, is frequently described
“as a leap from the known to the unknown,”
and this discovery of a binding principle that brings
together a wide variety of disconnected facts is not
unlike the process of the creative artist. The
same unconscious method by which a poet hits upon
an appropriate epithet, a musician upon a melody,
a painter upon an effect of color or line is displayed
in that sudden vivid flash of insight by which a scientist
sees a mass of facts that have long seemed bafflingly
contradictory, gathered up under a single luminous
law. In his famous essay on “The Scientific
Uses of the Imagination,” Tyndall writes:
We are gifted with the power of Imagination,
... and by this power we can lighten the darkness
which surrounds the world of the senses. There
are tories even in science who regard imagination as
a faculty to be feared and avoided rather than employed.
They had observed its action in weak vessels and were
unduly impressed by its disasters. But they might
with equal justice point to exploded boilers as an
argument against the use of steam. Bounded and
conditioned by cooeperant Reason, imagination becomes
the mightiest instrument of the physical discoverer.
Newton’s passage from a falling apple to a falling
moon was, at the outset, a leap of the imagination.
When William Thomson tries to place the ultimate particles
of matter between his compass points, and to apply
to them a scale of millimetres, he is powerfully aided
by this faculty. And in much that has been recently
said about protoplasm and life, we have the outgoings
of the imagination guided and controlled by the known
analogies of science. In fact, without this power,
our knowledge of Nature would be a mere tabulation
of coexistences and sequences. We should
still believe in the succession of day and night,
of summer and winter; but the soul of Force would be
dislodged from our universe; causal relations would
disappear, and with them that science which is now
binding the parts of nature into an organic whole.
As we shall presently see, this imaginative
leap is guarded and controlled, so that no flash of
insight, however attractive, is uncritically accepted.
But the origin of every eventually accepted hypothesis
lies in the upshoot of irresponsible fancy, differing
not at all from the images in the mind of a poet or
painter or the melodies that unpredictably occur to
a musician.
THE AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE. Art
is, on its creative side, as we have seen, the control
of Nature in the practical or imaginative realization
of ideals. The industrial arts are pursued out
of necessity, because man must find himself ways of
living in a world which he must inhabit, though it
is not a prior arranged for his habitation.
The fine arts are pursued as ends in themselves.
The genuinely gifted sing, paint, write poetry, apart
from fame and reward, for the sheer pleasure of creation.
But the products of these creative activities themselves
become satisfactions on a par with other natural goods.
The objects of art poems, paintings, statues,
symphonies are themselves prized and sought
after. They afford satisfaction to that large
number of persons who are sensitive to the beautiful
without having a gift for its creation.
On the other hand, every fine art
involves some elements of merely technical skill or
craftsmanship, which is important in achieving an imaginative
result, but is the skill of the mechanic rather than
the vision of the artist. In surveying the finished
product of art as it appears in a painting by a Turner
or a Cezanne, we may forget the “dust and ointment
of the calling,” but it is none the less there.
The drudgery of art, the practicing of scales. the
mixing of colors, the rehearsing of plays, are, as
it were, the necessary preliminary industry in art.]
AEsthetic appreciation is indeed shared
by all men, and is called out by other objects than
paintings or poems. There is hardly anything
men do which is not affected by what has been called
“an irrelevant access of aesthetic feeling.”
We saw in another connection how our estimates of
persons and situations are qualified by love and hate,
sympathy and revulsion. In the same way all our
experiences have an aesthetic coloring. It may
be nothing more than the curious jubilance and vivacity,
the thrill and tingle of the blood that comes upon
a crisp autumn day. It may be, as Mill pointed
out, the largeness of thought and vision promoted
by habitually working in a spacious and dignified
room. AEsthetic influences are always playing
upon us; they determine not only our tastes in the
decoration of our houses, our choices of places to
walk and to eat, but even such seemingly remote and
abstract matters as a scientific theory or a philosophy
of life. Even the industrial ideal of efficiency
has, “with its suggestion of Dutch neatness
and cleanliness,” order and symmetry, an aesthetic
flavor. Similarly is there an appeal to our aesthetic
sensibilities in the grouping of a wide variety of
facts under sweeping inclusive and simple generalizations.
There is, as has often been pointed out, scarcely
anything to choose from as regards the relative plausibility
of the Copernican over the Ptolemaic system.
The former we choose largely because of its greater
symmetry and simplicity in accounting for the facts.
Even a world view may be chosen on account of its
artistic appeal. One feels moved imaginatively,
even if one disagrees with the logic of those philosophies
which see reality as one luminously transparent conscious
whole, in which every experience is delicately reticulated
with every other, where discord and division are obliterated,
and the multiple variety of mundane facts are gathered
up into the symmetrical unity of the eternal.
APPRECIATION VERSUS ACTION.
Every human experience has thus its particular and
curious aesthetic flavor, as an inevitable though
undetected obligato. AEsthetic values enter into
and qualify our estimates of persons and situations,
and help to determine that general sympathy or revulsion,
that love or hate for people, institutions, or ideas,
which make the pervasive atmosphere of all human action.
But in the world of action, we cannot emphasize these
irrelevant aesthetic feelings. The appreciative
and the practical moods are sharply contrasted.
In the latter we are interested in results, and insist
on the exclusion of all considerations that do not
bear on their accomplishment. The appreciative
or aesthetic mood is detached; it is interested not
to act, but to pause and consider; it does not want
to use the present as a point of departure. It
wants to bask in the present perfection of color, word,
or sound. The practical man is interested in
a present situation for what can be done with it;
he wants to know, in the vernacular, “What comes
next?” “Where do we go from here?”
The appreciator wishes to remain in the lovely interlude
of perfection which he experiences in music, poetry,
or painting.
The aesthetic mood is obviously at
a discount in the world of action. To bask in
the charm of a present situation, to linger and loiter,
as it were, in the sun of beauty, is to accomplish
nothing, to interrupt action. It is precisely
for this reason that persons with extremely high aesthetic
sensibilities are at such a discount in practical
life. They are too easily dissolved in appreciation.
They are too much absorbed, for practical efficiency,
in the tragic, the whimsical, the beautiful, or the
comic aspects of men and affairs. The same sensitivity
to the innuendoes and colors of life that enable some
of such men to give an exquisite and various portraiture
of experience, incapacitates them for action.
The practical man must not observe anything irrelevant
to his immediate business. He must not be dissolved,
at every random provocation, into ecstacy, laughter,
or sorrow. There is too much to be done in business,
government, mechanics, and the laboratory, to allow
one’s attention to wander dreamingly over the
tragic, the beautiful, the pathetic, the comic, and
the grotesque qualities of the day’s work.
To take an extreme case, it would, as Jane Harrison
observes, be a monstrosity, when our friend was drowning,
to note with lingering appreciation the fluent white
curve of his arm in the glimmering waters of the late
afternoon. The man to whom every event is flooded
with imaginative possibilities and emotional suggestions
is a useless or a dangerous character in situations
where it is essential to discriminate the immediate
and important bearings of facts. We cannot select
an expert accountant on the basis of a pleasant smile,
nor a chauffeur for his sense of humor.
But while, in the larger part of the
lives of most men, observation of facts is controlled
with reference to their practical bearings, observation
may sometimes take place for its own sake. The
glory of a sunset is not commonly prized for any good
that may come of it; nobody but a general on a campaign
or a fire warden looks out from a mountain peak upon
the valley below for reasons other than the pleasure
of the beholding. In the case of persons, also,
we are not always interested in them for their uses;
we are sometimes delighted with them in themselves.
We pause to watch merry or quaint children, experts
at tennis, beautiful faces, for their own sakes.
While even in nature and in social
experience, we thus sometimes note specifically aesthetic
values, the objects of fine art have no other justification
than the immediate satisfactions they produce in their
beholder. Those intrinsic pleasures which go
by the general name of beauty are various and complicated.
Our joy may be in the sheer delight of the senses,
as in the hearing of a singularly lucid and sustained
note of a clarinet, a flute, a voice, or a violin.
It may be in the appreciation of form, as in the case
of the symmetry of a temple, an arch, or an altar.
It may be in the simultaneous stirring of the senses,
the imagination, and the intellect, by the presentation
of an idea suffused with music and emotion, as in the
case of an ode by Wordsworth or a sonnet by Milton.
In all these instances we are not
interested in anything beyond the experience itself.
The objects of the fine arts are not drafts on the
future, anticipations of future satisfactions eventually
to be cashed in. They are immediate and intrinsic
goods, absolute fulfillments. They are not signals
to action; they are releases from it. A painting,
a poem, a symphony, do not precipitate movement or
change. They invite a restful absorption.
It was this that made Schopenhauer regard art as a
rest from reality. During these interludes, at
least, we live amid perfections, and are content there
to move and have our being.
SENSE SATISFACTION. Appreciation
of the arts begins in the senses. Sight and sound,
these are unquestionably the chief avenues by which
the imagination is stirred.
In the words of Santayana:
For if nothing not once in sense is
to be found in the intellect, much less is such a
thing to be found in the imagination. If the
cedars of Lebanon did not spread a grateful shade,
or the winds rustle through the maze of their branches,
if Lebanon had never been beautiful to sense, it would
not now be a fit or poetic subject of allusion....
Nor would Samarcand be anything but for the mystery
of the desert, and the picturesqueness of caravans,
nor would an argosy be poetic if the sea had no voices
and no foam, the winds and oars no resistance, and
the rudder and taut sheets no pull. From these
real sensations imagination draws its life, and suggestion
its power.
Satisfaction in sounds arises from
the regular intervals of the vibrations of the air
by which it is produced. The rapidity of these
regular beats determines the pitch. But sounds
also differ in timbre or quality, depending
on the number of overtones which occur in different
modes of production. This explains why a note
on the scale played on the piano, differs from the
same note played on the ’cello or the organ.
From these fundamental sensuous elements of sound,
elaborate symphonic compositions may be built up,
but they remain primary nevertheless. Unless
the sensuous elements of sound were themselves pleasing
it is difficult to imagine that a musical composition
could be. Music would then be like an orchestra
whose members played in unison, but whose violins were
raucous and whose trumpets hoarse.
Color again illustrates the aesthetic
satisfactions that are found in certain kinds of sense
stimulation, apart from the form they are given or
the emotions or ideas they express. The elements
of color, as color, may be reduced to three
simple elements: First may be noted hue,
as yellow or blue; second, value (or notan)
dark or light red; and third intensity (or
brightness to grayness), as vivid blue or dull blue.
Specific vivid aesthetic combinations and variations
are made possible by variations or combinations of
these three elements of color. If a color scheme
is displeasing, the fault may be in the wrong selection
of hues, in weak values, in ill-matched intensities
or all three.
Dutch tiles, Japanese prints and blue
towels, Abruzzi towels, American blue quilts, etc.,
are examples of harmony built up with several values
of one hue.
With two hues innumerable variations
are possible. Japanese prints of the “red
and green” period are compositions in light
yellow-red, middle green, black, and white....
Color varies not only in hue and value
[notan] but in intensity ranging
from bright to gray. Every painter knows that
a brilliant bit of color, set in grayer tones of the
same or neighboring hues, will illuminate the whole
group a distinguished and elusive harmony.
The fire opal has a single point of intense scarlet,
melting into pearl; the clear evening sky is like
this when from the sunken sun the red-orange light
grades away through yellow and green to steel gray.
These variations in hue, value, and
intensity of color afford specific aesthetic satisfactions.
The blueness of the sky is its specific beauty; the
greenness of foliage in springtime is its characteristic
and quite essential charm. Apart from anything
else, sensations themselves afford satisfaction or
the reverse. A loud color, a strident or a shrill
sound may cause a genuine revulsion of feeling.
A soft hue or a pellucid note may be an intrinsic
pleasure, though a formless one, and one expressive
of no meaning at all.
FORM. While the imagination is
stirred most directly by the immediate material beauty,
by the satisfaction of the senses, beauty of form
is an important element in the enhancement of appreciation.
In the plastic arts and in music, it is, next to the
immediate appeal of the sensuous elements involved,
the chief ingredient in the effects produced.
And even in those arts which are notable for their
expressive values, poetry, fiction, drama and painting,
the appeal of form, as in the plot of a drama, or
the structure of an ode or it sonnet is still very
high. Certain dispositions of line and color in
painting; of harmony and counterpoint in music; rhythm,
refrain, and recurrence in poetry; symmetry and balance
in sculpture; all have their specific appeal, apart
from the materials used or the emotions or ideas expressed.
Certain harmonic relations are interesting in music
apart from the particular range of notes employed,
or the particular melody upon which variations are
made. The pattern of a tapestry may be interesting,
apart from the color combinations involved. The
structure of a ballade or a sonnet may be beautiful,
apart from the melody of the words or the persuasiveness
of the emotion or idea. Out of the factors which
enter into the appreciation of form certain elements
stand out.
There is, in the first place, symmetry,
the charm of which lies partly in recognition and
rhythm. “When the eye runs over a façade,
and finds the objects that attract it at equal intervals,
an expectation, like the anticipation of an inevitable
note or requisite word, arises in the mind, and its
non-satisfaction involves a shock."
Similarly, form given to material
brings a variety of details under a comprehensive
unity, enabling us to have at once the stimulation
of diversity and the clarification of a guiding principle.
We cherish sensations in themselves, when they consist
of elements like limpidness of color and lucidity of
sound. But too much miscellany of sensation is
disquieting; it has an effect analogous to noise.
A baby or a barbarian may delight in loud heterogeneity
and vivid confusion, but extravagance of sensation
does not constitute an aesthetic experience.
The discovery of the one in the many,
the immediate apprehension of the fluent tracing of
a pattern, a form, or a structure, is intrinsically
delightful. The pattern of a tapestry design
is as striking and suggestive as the colors themselves.
When musical taste has passed from a sentimental intoxication
with the sensuous beauty of the sounds themselves,
the beauty we admire is primarily beauty of form or
structure. The musical connoisseur likes to trace
the recurrence of a theme in a symphony, its deviations
and disappearances, its distribution in the various
choirs of wood-wind, brass, and strings, its interweaving
with other themes, its resilient, surprising, and
apposite émergences, its pervasive penetration
of the total scheme.
The aesthetic experience, indeed,
as specifically aesthetic, rather than merely sensuous
or intellectual, is, it might be said, almost wholly
a matter of form. It is the artist’s function,
as it is occasionally his achievement, to give satisfying,
determinate forms to the indeterminate and miscellaneous
materials at his command. Formlessness is for
the creator of beauty the unpardonable sin. To
give clarity and coherence to the vague ambiguous
scintillations of sound, to chisel a specific
perfection out of the indefinite inviting possibilities
of marble, to form precise and consecutive suggestions
out of the random and uncertain music of words, is
to achieve, in so far, success in art. Nor does
form mean formality. Experience is so various
and fertile, and so far outruns the types under which
human invention and imagination can apprehend it,
that inexhaustible novelty is possible. Novelty,
on the other hand, does not mean formlessness.
The artist must, if he is to be successful, always
remain something of an artisan. However beautiful
his vision, he must have sufficient command of the
technical resources to his craft to give a specific
and determinate embodiment to his ideal.
Every one has haunting premonitions
of beauty; it is the business of the artist to give
realization in form to the hints of the beautiful
which are present in matter as we meet it in experience,
and to the imaginative longings which they provoke.
In which forms different individuals
will find satisfaction depends on all the circumstances
which go to make one individual different from another.
There cannot be in the case of art, any more than
in any other experience, absolute standards.
We can be pleased only with those arrangements of sound
or color to which our sensibilities have early been
educated. Even the most catholic of tastes becomes
restricted in the course of education. To Western
ears, there is at first no music at all in Chinese
music, and Beethoven would appear to the Chinese as
barbarous as their compositions appear to us.
But while in a wide sense, conformity
to the average determines or limits our possible appreciation
of the beautiful, within these limits certain elements
are intrinsically more pleasing than others.
Those elements of experience, in the first place,
more readily acquire aesthetic values, which in themselves
strikingly impress the senses. Thus tallness in
a man, because it is in the first place striking,
becomes readily incorporated into our standard of
the beautiful. And all elements in themselves
beautiful, the human eye, the curve of the arm, the
wave of the hair, come to be emphasized. These
outstanding elements may themselves become conventionalized
and standardized, so that objects of art which conform
to them are insured thereby of a certain degree of
recognition as beautiful. Too close a conformity
produces monotonous formalities, cloying classicisms.
Too wide a divergence results in shock and unpleasantness.
The history of all the arts, however, is full of instances
of how the taste of a people can be educated to new
forms. Ruskin had to educate the English people
to an appreciation of Turner. The poets of the
Romantic period were condemned by the critics brought
up on the rigid classic models. The so-called
Romantic movements in the arts are, at their best,
departures from old forms, not into formlessness,
but into new, various, and more fruitful forms.
Romanticism at its worst dissolves into mere formlessness
and inarticulate ecstacies. Infinite variety of
forms the world of experience may be made to wear,
but sensations, emotions, and ideas must be given
some form, if they are to pass from a fruitless yearning
after beauty into its positive incarnation in objects
of art.
All forms have their characteristic
emotional effects, as have all materials, even apart
from the emotions or ideas they express. The
glitter of gold and the sparkle of diamonds, the strength
of marble, the sturdiness of oak we hardly
can think of these materials without thinking of the
associations which go with them. Similarly the
symmetry of the colonnades of a temple, the multiplicity
and variety of Gothic architecture, even so simple
a form as a circle, provoke a great or slight characteristic
emotional reaction. Likewise, a staccato or a
fluent rhythm in music, a march, or a dance movement,
have, even apart from their unconscious or intentional
expressiveness, specific emotional values. In
literature, also, where the value of the words themselves
might be expected to give place entirely to the emotions
or ideas of which they are the expressive instruments,
poems may themselves, by their form and music, be
provocative of specific emotional effects.
“...And over them the sea wind sang,
Shrill, chill, with flakes of foam. He, stepping
down By zigzag paths and juts of pointed rock,
Came on the shining levels of the lake.
Dry clashed his harness in the icy
caves,
And barren chasms, and all to left
and right,
The bare black cliff clanged round
him, as he based
His feet on juts of slippery crag
that rang,
Sharp-smitten with the dint of armed
heels
And on a sudden, lo! the level lake,
And the long glories of the winter
moon."
Here the effect lies partly in the
form, but more especially in the timbre and
reverberation of the words themselves. In other
cases, it is the form that is the chief ingredient
in the effect produced. In Alfred Noyes’s
“The Barrel Organ,” apart from the meaning,
it is the rhythmic form that is of chief aesthetic
value:
“Come down to Kew in lilac time,
in lilac time, in lilac time,
Come down to Kew in lilac time,
it is n’t far from London,
And you shall wander hand-in-hand
with love in summer’s wonderland.
Come down to Kew in lilac time;
it is n’t far from London.
“The cherry trees are seas of bloom
and soft perfume and sweet perfume.
The cherry trees are seas of bloom
(and oh, so near to London!)
And there they say, when dawn is
high, and all the world’s a blaze of sky,
The cuckoo, though he’s very
shy, will sing a song for London.”
Apart from all considerations of meaning,
set the easy fluent grace of this lyric over against
the march and majesty of the “Battle Hymn of
the Republic.”
“Mine eyes have seen the glory of
the coming of the Lord;
He is trampling out the vintage
where the grapes of wrath are stored;
He hath loosed the fateful lightning
of His terrible swift sword;
His truth
is marching on.
“He has sounded forth the trumpet
that shall never call retreat;
He is sifting out the hearts of
men before His judgment-seat;
Oh, be swift, my soul, to answer
Him! be jubilant, my feet!
Our God
is marching on.”
EXPRESSION. The objects of art,
as we have seen, are interesting and attractive in
themselves, for the material of which they are formed,
and for the form which the artist has given them.
But they are interesting in another and possibly as
important a way: they are instruments of expression.
That is, a painting is something more than an intrinsically
interesting disposition of line and color, a statue
something more than an exquisite or sublime chiseling
of marble, a poem more than a rhythmic combination
of the music of words. All of these are expressive.
Something in their form is associated with something
in our past experience. Thus, as James somewhere
suggests, “a bare figure by Michelangelo, with
unduly flexed joints, may come somehow to suggest the
moral tragedy of life.” Something in the
face of an old man painted by Rembrandt may recall
to us a similar outward evidence of inner seriousness,
wistfulness, and resignation which we have ourselves
beheld in living people. And we clearly value
the poems of a Wordsworth, a Milton, a Matthew Arnold,
not solely for the magnificent form and music of their
words, but also for the sober beauty of their meaning.
We may come to appreciate even the highly immediate
sensuous and formal pleasure of music for the reverie
or rapture into which by suggestion it throws us.
“Expression may, therefore, make beautiful by
suggestion, things in themselves indifferent, or it
may come to heighten the beauty which they already
possess.”
The objects of art may be appreciated
chiefly either for their material and form, or for
the values which they express. In some cases
the actual object may be beautiful; sometimes the
beauty may lie almost wholly in the image, emotion,
or idea evoked. “Home, Sweet Home,”
for example, may be plausibly held to win admiration
rather for the sentimental associations which it evokes
in the singer or hearer than for its verbal or melodic
beauty. The enjoyment which people without any
musical gifts, out on a camping or canoeing trip,
experience from singing a rather cheap and frayed repertory
is obviously for sentimental rather than for aesthetic
satisfaction. Similarly, we may cherish the mementos
of a lost friend or child, not for their intrinsic
worth, but for the tenderness of the memories they
arouse. The situation is delicately described
in Eugene Field’s “Little Boy Blue”:
“The little toy dog is covered with
dust,
But sturdy and staunch
he stands,
And the little toy soldier is red
with rust,
And his musket moulds
in his hands.
Time was when the little toy dog
was new,
And the soldier was
passing fair,
And that was the time when our Little
Boy Blue
Kissed them and put
them there.”
Some objects of art may indeed become
beautiful almost completely through their expressiveness.
There are certain poets whose music is raucous and
who make little appeal through clarity of form.
These survive almost completely by virtue of the persistent
strength and enduring sublimity of the ideas which
they express. Much of Whitman may be put in this
class, and also much of Browning. Similarly a
sculptor may not captivate us by the fluent beauty
of his marble, but by the power and passion which
his crude mighty figures express. In such cases
we may even come to regard what, from a purely formal
point of view, is unlovely, as a thing of the most
extreme beauty. Even the roughness in such direct
revelations of strength, may come to be regarded as
elements of the beautiful. And where massiveness
of effect does not suffice to retrieve a work of art
from its essential crudities, we may still come to
accept it as beautiful, as it were, in intention,
and for what comes to be regarded as its essence, namely,
the idea or emotion it expresses. We forgive the
imperfections of form as we forgive the stammerings
and stutterings of persons whose broken sayings are
yet full of wisdom.
Usually even where the object, emotion,
or idea expressed is beautiful, we demand certain
formal and material elements of beauty. A telegram
may convey the very apex of felicity, yet be not at
all felicitous in its form or in the music of its
words. If in such cases, we speak of beauty, the
term is altogether metaphorical and imputed; we are
using it in the same analogical sense as when we speak
of a “beautiful operation” or a “beautiful
deed”; it is a moral rather than an aesthetic
term. We may find the letter of a friend expressive
of the gentleness, fidelity, and charm that have endeared
him to us, but unless these have attained sufficiently
clear and explicit form and determinate unmistakable
music, the letter will have a meaningful beauty only
in the light of the peculiar relation existing between
us and the writer. From an impartial aesthetic
point of view, the epistle can only by affectionate
exaggeration be called beautiful.
But the arts, through their beauty
of form, may present pleasingly objects, emotions,
ideas, not in themselves beautiful or pleasing.
The clearest case of this kind is tragedy, where we
may enjoy at arm’s length and through the medium
of art, experiences which would in the near actualities
of life be only unmitigated horror. Refracted
through the medium of poetry and drama, they may appear
beautiful pervasively and long.
We are enabled through the arts to
survey sympathetically universal emotions, those by
which our own lives have been touched, or to which
they are liable; we are enabled to survey bitterness
and frustration calmly because they are set in a perspective,
a beautiful perspective, in which they shine out clear
and persuasive, purified of that bitter personal tang
which makes sorrow in real life so different in tone
from the beauty with which in tragedy it is halved.
Any sensation, as Max Eastman justly remarks in his
“Enjoyment of Poetry,” may, if sufficiently
mild, become pleasing. And there is hardly any
human action or experience, however terrible, which
cannot in the hands of a master be made appealing
and sublime in its emotional effect.
The beauty of Tragedy does but make
visible a quality which, in more or less obvious shapes,
is present always and everywhere in life. In
the spectacle of death, in the endurance of intolerable
pain, and in the irrevocableness of a vanished past,
there is a sacredness, an overpowering awe, a feeling
of the vastness, the depth, the inexhaustible mystery
of existence, in which, as by some strange marriage
of pain, the sufferer is bound to the world by bonds
of sorrow. In these moments of insight we lose
all eagerness of temporary desire, all struggling
and striving for petty ends, all care for the little
trivial things that, to a superficial view, make up
the common life of day by day; we see, surrounding
the narrow raft, illumined by the flickering light
of human comradeship, the dark ocean on whose rolling
waves we toss for a brief hour.
But emotions and experiences that
in real life are displeasing can be made pleasing
in art chiefly by virtue of the qualities of material
and form already discussed. The disappointment,
disillusion, or terror which tragedy so vividly reveals
is made tolerable chiefly through the intrinsic beauty
of the vehicle in which it is set forth. The
high and breathless beauty of rhythm, the verve, the
mystery, and music with which evils are set forth,
may make them not only tolerable but tender and appealing.
What would be as immediate experience altogether heartrending,
for example the torturing remorse of a Macbeth, is
made splendid and moving in the incisive majesty and
penetration of his monologues. At the end of
Hamlet, the utter wreck, unreason, and confusion is
made bearable and beautiful by the tender finality
of Hamlet’s dying words to Horatio:
“Absent thee from felicity awhile
And in this harsh world draw thy
breath in pain,
To tell my story.”
Greek tragedy had the additional accouterments
of a chorus, of music, of production in a vast amphitheater
to give an atmosphere of outward grandeur to the glory
of its intent. Tragedy often relieves the net
horror which is its burden by the pomp and circumstance
of the associations it suggests:
We have palaces for our scene, rank,
beauty, and virtues in our heroes, nobility in their
passions and in their fate, and altogether a sort
of glorification of life without which tragedy would
lose both in depth of pathos since things
so precious are destroyed and in subtlety
of charm, since things so precious are manifested.
Tragedy still more subtly attains
the beauty of expressiveness by making the very evils
and confusions and terrors it presents somehow the
exemplifications of a serene eternal order.
The function of the chorus in Greek tragedy was indeed
chiefly to indicate in solemn strophe and antistrophe
the ordered and harmonious verities of which these
particular follies and frustrations were so tender
and terrible an illustration. They catch up the
present and particular evil into the calm and splendid
interplay of cosmic forces. Thus at the end of
Euripides’s play Medea, when the heroine
has slain the children she has borne to Jason and
in her fury refuses to let him gather up their dead
bodies, when Jason in utter inconsolable despair,
casts himself upon the earth, out of all this wrack
and torture the chorus raises the audience into a
contemplation of the ordered eternity by which these
things come to be. It sings:
“Great treasure halls hath Zeus
in Heaven,
From whence to man strange dooms
be given,
Past hope
or fear;
And the end men looked for cometh
not,
And a path is there where no man
thought:
So hath
it fallen here."
ART AS VICARIOUS EXPERIENCE.
The drama, art, and painting are, in general, ways
by which we can vicariously experience the emotions
of others. All of the expressive arts are made
possible by the fundamental psychological fact that
human beings give certain instinctive and habitual
signs of emotion and instinctively respond to them.
In consequence, through art experience may be immeasurably
broadened, deepened, and mellowed. Through the
medium of art, modes of life long past away can leave
their imperishable and living mementos. Dante
opens to the citizen of the twentieth century the mind
and imagination of the Middle Ages. A Grecian
urn can arouse, at least to a Keats, the whole stilled
magic of the Greek spirit. And not only can we
live through the life and emotion of times long dead,
but the fiction and drama and poetry of our own day
permit us to enter into realms of experience which
in extent and variety would not be possible to one
man. Indeed, the possibility of vicariously enlarging
experience is one of the chief appeals of art.
We cannot all be rovers, but we can have in reading
Masefield a pungent sense of romantic open spaces,
the salt winds, the perilous motion or the broad calm
of the sea. We feel something of the same urgency
as that of the author when we read:
“I must go down to the seas again,
the lonely sea and the sky,
And all I ask is a tall ship and
a star to steer her by,
And the wheel’s kick and the
wind’s song and the white sail’s shaking,
And a gray mist on the sea’s
face and a gray dawn breaking."
Art opens up wide avenues of possibility;
it releases us from the limitations to which a particular
mode of life, an accidental niche in a business or
profession has committed us. It enables us vividly
to experience and sympathetically to appreciate the
lives which are led by other men, and in which something
in our own personalities could have found fulfillment.
While the objects of art thus broaden
our experience by their precise and contagious communication
of emotion, they may also express ideas. Thus
a play may have a message, a poem a vision, a painting
an allegory. Art is both at an advantage and
at a disadvantage in the communication of ideas.
Ideas, if they are to be accurately conveyed, should
be devoid of emotional flourish, and presented with
telegraphic directness and precision. They should
have the clarity of formulas, rather than the distracting
array and atmosphere of form. But ideas presented
in the persuasive garb of beauty, gain in their hold
over men what they lose in precision. Thus an
eloquent orator, a touching letter, a vivid poem,
may do more than volumes of the most definitive and
convincing logic to insinuate an idea into men’s
minds. Compare in effectiveness the most thoroughgoing
treatise on the status of the agricultural laborer
with the stirring momentum of Edwin Markham’s”
The Man With the Hoe”:
“Bowed by the weight of centuries
he leans
Upon his hoe and gazes on the ground,
The emptiness of ages in his face,
And on his back the burden of the
world.
Who made him dead to rapture and
despair,
A thing that grieves not, and that
never hopes,
Stolid and stunned, a brother to
the ox?
Who loosened and let down this brutal
jaw?
Whose was the hand that slanted
back this brow?
Whose breath blew out the light
within this brain?
“Is this the Thing the Lord God
made and gave
To have dominion over sea and land;
To trace the stars and search the
heavens for power,
To feel the passion of Eternity?
Is this the Dream he dreamed who
shaped the suns,
And marked their ways upon the ancient
deep?
Down all the stretch of Hell to
its last gulf
There is no shape more terrible
than this
More tongued with censure of the
world’s blind greed
More filled with signs and portents
for the soul
More fraught with menace to the
universe.”
An idea clothed with such music and
passion is an incomparably effective means of arousing
a response. It is this which makes art so valuable
an instrument of propaganda. People will respond
actively to ideas set forth with fervor by a Tolstoy
or an Ibsen who would be left cold by the flat and
erudite accuracy of a volume on economics. And
the confirmed Platonist is made so perhaps less by
the convincingness of Plato’s logic, than by
the inevitable and irrefutable grace of his dramatic
art.
There is, for certain persons educated
in the arts, a satisfaction that is neither sensuous
nor emotional, but intellectual. These come to
discriminate form with the abstract though warm interest
of the expert. The well-informed concert-goer
begins to appreciate beauties hidden to the uninitiate.
He notes with eager anticipation the technical genius
of a composition as it unfolds, admiring the craft
and skill as well as the vision of the artist.
In extreme cases this may, of course, degenerate into
mere pedantry. But at its best, it is the satisfaction
of the man who, having a keen eye for beauty, is all
the more solicitous for its accurate realization.
The satisfactions of the connoisseur are merely a refinement
of less sophisticated forms of appreciation. To
appreciate the bare sounds of music, or the vividness
of color in a painting is the prelude to more discriminating
tastes. It is impossible for most men to have
in all the arts expert judgment, but the ability to
be able to discriminate with authority the technical
achievements of a work of genius, while it does not
supplant the emotional and sense satisfaction derived
from the arts, nevertheless enhances them.
ART AND AESTHETIC EXPERIENCE IN THE
SOCIAL ORDER. The creative activity which is,
to a peculiar extent, the artist’s, is sought
and practiced to some degree by all men. Genius
is rare, but talent of a minor sort is frequent.
In the playing of a musical instrument, in the practice
of a handicraft, in the cultivation of a garden, ordinary
men in modern society find an outlet for invention,
craftsmanship, and imagination. To give this
joy of creation, in smaller or larger measure, to
all men is to promote social happiness. In the
discussion of instinct it was pointed out that men
come nearest to attaining happiness when they are
doing what is their bent by original nature, when
they are acting out of sheer love of the activity
rather than from compulsion. And since all men
possess, although in moderate degree, the creative
impulse, to give this impulse a chance is a distinct
social good.
The employment of the creative imagination
demands both leisure and training. Leisure is
needed because, in the routine activities of industry,
men’s actions are determined not by their imagination,
but by the immediacies of practical demands.
There may be, as Helen Marot suggests, a possibility
of a wide utilization of the creative impulse in industry.
But a large part of industrial life must of necessity
remain routine. In consequence, during their
leisure hours alone, can men find free scope for some
form of aesthetic interest and activity. The
second requisite is training. Even the poor player
of an instrument can derive some pleasure from his
performance. And, under the accidents of economic
and social circumstance, many a flower may really
be born to blush unseen through the fact that its
talents receive no opportunity. The occasional
“discovery” by a wealthy man of a genius
in the slums, indicates how a more liberal and general
provision of training in the arts might redound to
the general good. And a more widespread endowment
of training in the fine arts, if it did not produce
many geniuses, might at least produce a number of
competent painters and musicians, who, in the practice
of their skill, during their leisure, would derive
considerable and altogether wholesome pleasure.
While high aesthetic capacity may
be lacking in most people, aesthetic appreciation
is widely diffused, and the education of taste and
the growth in appreciation of the arts have been marked.
The museums of art in our large cities report a constantly
increasing attendance, both of visitors to the galleries
and attendants at lectures. And the crowds which
regularly attend musical programs of a sustainedly
high character in many cities, winter and summer,
are evidence of how widespread and eager is appreciation
of the fine arts. In the Scandinavian countries
and in Germany one of the most remarkable social phenomena
has been the growth of a widely supported people’s
theater movement, in which there has been consistent
support of the highest type of operas and plays.
ART AS AN INDUSTRY. The fact
that objects of art are themselves immediate satisfactions
and supply human wants, makes their provision for
large numbers an important social enterprise.
Certain forms of art, therefore, become highly industrialized.
The provision of the objects of art becomes a profitable
business, as it is also made possible only by a large
economic outlay. Tolstoy in his What is Art?
brings out strikingly the economic basis of artistic
enterprises in contemporary society:
For the support of art in Russia ,
the government grants millions of roubles in subsidies
to academies, conservatories, and theatres. In
France, twenty million francs are assigned for art,
and similar grants are made in Germany and England.
In every large town enormous buildings
are erected for museums, academies, conservatories,
dramatic schools, and for performances and concerts.
Hundreds of thousands of workmen carpenters,
masons, painters, joiners, paperhangers, tailors, hairdressers,
jewelers, molders, type-setters spend their
whole lives in hard labor to satisfy the demands of
art, so that hardly any other department of human
activity, except the military, consumes so much energy
as this.
Not only is enormous labor spent on
this activity, but in it, as in war, the very lives
of men are sacrificed. Hundreds of thousands of
people devote their lives from childhood to learning
to twirl their legs rapidly (dancers), or to touch
notes and strings very rapidly (musicians) or to turn
every phrase inside out and find a rhyme for every
word.
Tolstoy’s point in thus emphasizing
the immense energies devoted to artistic enterprises
is to lead us to consider what is the end of all this
labor. He points out scathingly the ugliness,
frivolity, and crudity of much that passes for drama
in the theater, for music in the concert hall, and
for literature between covers. He pleads for
a simple art that shall express with sincerity the
genuine emotions of the great mass of men.
Whatever be our estimate of Tolstoy’s
sweeping condemnation of so much of what has come
to be regarded as classic beauty, the point he makes
about the commercialization of art is incontrovertible.
If art is an industry, the good is determined, as
it were, by popular vote. The many must be pleased
rather than the discriminating. While, as has
been noted, aesthetic appreciation is fairly general,
appreciation of the subtler forms of art requires
training. The glaring, the conspicuous, the broad
effect, is more likely to win rapid popular approval
than the subtle, the quiet, and the fragile.
That taste is readily educable is true. But when
immediate profits are the end, one cannot pause to
educate the public. And publishing and the theater
are two conspicuous instances of the conflicts that
not infrequently arise between standards of economic
return and standards of aesthetic merit. Even
where there is no deliberate selection of the worse
rather than the better, commercial standards operate
to put the novel in art at a discount. As already
pointed out, we tend to appreciate forms and ideas
to which we are accustomed. In consequence, where
commercial demands make immediate widespread appreciation
necessary, the untried, the odd, the radical innovation
in music, literature, or drama, is a questionable
venture. There are notable instances of works
which, though eventually recognized as great, had
to go begging at first for a publisher or a producer.
This was the case with some of Meredith’s earlier
novels; later Meredith, as a publisher’s reader,
turned down some of Shaw. The same inhospitality
met some of the plays of Ibsen and some of the symphonies
of Tschaikowsky.
ART AND MORALS. Attention has
already been called to the fact that objects of art
are powerful vehicles for social propaganda.
Indeed some works become famous less for their intrinsic
beauty than for their moral force. The effectiveness
of art forms as instruments of propaganda lies in the
fact, previously noted, that the ideas presented,
with all the accouterments of color, form, and movement,
are incomparably effective in stimulating passion;
ideas thus aroused in the beholder have the vivid
momentum of emotion to sustain them. There is
only rhetorical exaggeration in the saying, “Let
me sing a country’s songs, and I care not who
makes its laws.” Plato was one of the first
to recognize how influential art could be in influencing
men’s actions and attitudes. So keenly
did he realize its possible influence, that in constructing
his ideal state he provided for the rigid regulation
of all artistic production by the governing power,
and the exile of all poets. He felt deeply how
insinuatingly persuasive poets could become with their
dangerous “beautiful lies.” Artists
have, indeed, not infrequently been revolutionaries,
at least in the sense that the world which they so
ecstatically pictured makes even the best of actual
worlds look pale and paltry in comparison. The
imaginative genius has naturally enough been discontented
with an existing order that could not possibly measure
up to his ardent specifications. Shelley is possibly
the supreme example of the type; against his incorrigible
construction of perfect worlds in imagination he set
the real world in which men live, and found it hateful.
In consequence of this discontent
which the imaginative artist so often expresses with
the real world, and the power of his enthusiastic
visions to win the loyalties and affections of men,
many moralists and statesmen have, like Plato, regarded
the creative artist with suspicion. They have
half believed the lyric boast of the Celtic poet who
wrote:
“One man with a dream at pleasure,
Shall go forth and conquer
a crown,
And three with a new song’s
measure,
Can trample an empire
down.
“We, in the ages lying,
In the buried past of
the earth,
Built Nineveh with our sighing,
And Babel itself with
our mirth;
We o’erthrew them with prophesying
To the old of the new
world’s worth,
For each age is a dream that, is
dying,
Or one that is coming
to birth."
Many, therefore, who have reflected
upon art Plato first and chiefly have
insisted that art must be used to express only those
ideas and emotions which when acted upon would have
beneficent social consequences. Only those stories
are to be told, those pictures to be painted, those
songs to be sung, which contribute to the welfare
of the state. Many artists have similarly felt
a Puritanical responsibility; they have told only
those tales which could be pointed with a moral.
The supreme example of this dedication of art to a
moral purpose is found in the Middle Ages, when all
beauty of architecture, painting, and much of literature
and drama, was pervaded, as it was inspired, with
the Christian message. Later Milton writes at
the beginning of Paradise Lost:
“... What in me is dark, Illumine,
what is low raise and support, That
to the height of this great argument I may assert
Eternal Providence, And justify the ways of God
to man."
In a sense, the supreme achievements
of creative genius have been notable instances of
the expression of great moral or religious or social
ideals. Lucretius’s On the Nature of
Things is the noblest and most passionate extant
rendering of the materialistic conception of life.
Goethe’s Faust expresses in epic magnificence
a whole romantic philosophy of endless exploration
and infinite desire. Dante’s Divine
Comedy sums up in a single magnificent epic the
spirit and meaning of the mediaeval point of view.
As Henry Osborn Taylor writes of it:
Yet even the poem itself was a climax
long led up to. The power of its feeling had
been preparing in the conceptions, even in the reasonings,
which through the centuries had been gaining ardour
as they became part of the entire natures of men and
women. Thus had mediaeval thought become emotionalized
and plastic and living in poetry and art. Otherwise,
even Dante’s genius could not have fused the
contents of mediaeval thought into a poem. How
many passages in the Commedia illustrate this like
the lovely picture of Lia moving in the flowering
meadow, with her fair hands making her a garland.
The twenty-third canto of the Paradiso, telling
of the triumph of Christ and the Virgin, yields a
larger illustration; and within it, as a very concrete
lyric instance, floats that flower of angelic love,
the song of Gabriel circling the Lady of Heaven with
its melody, and giving quintessential utterance to
the love and adoration which the Middle Ages had intoned
to the Virgin. Yes, if it be Dante’s genius,
it is also the gathering emotion of the centuries,
which lifts the last cantos of the Paradiso
from glory to glory, and makes this closing singing
of the Commedia such supreme poetry. Nor
is it the emotional element alone that reaches its
final voice in Dante. Passage after passage of
the Paradiso is the apotheosis of scholastic
thought and ways of stating it, the very apotheosis,
for example, of those harnessed phrases in which the
line of great scholastics had endeavoured to put in
words the universalities of substance and accident
and the absolute qualities of God.
In these supreme instances the ideas
have been given a genuinely aesthetic expression.
They are beautiful in form and music, as well as in
content and vision. But not infrequently where
propaganda appears, art flies out of the window.
Many modern plays and novels might be cited, which
in their serious devotion to the enunciation of some
social ideal, lapse from song into statistics.
The artist with his eye on the social consequences
of his work may come altogether to cease to regard
standards of beauty. It is only the rare genius
who can make poetry out of politics. Even Shelley
lapses into deadly and arid prosiness when his chief
interest becomes the presentation of the political
ideas of Godwin.
In contrast with the theory that art
has a social responsibility, that so powerful an instrument
must be used exclusively in the presentation of adequate
social ideals, must be set the doctrine, widely current
in the late nineteenth century, of “art for
art’s sake.” To the exponents of this
point of view, the artist has only one responsibility,
the creation of beauty. It is his to realize
in form every pulsation of interest and desire, to
provide every possible exquisite sensation. The
artist must not be a preacher; he must not tell men
what is the good; he must show them the good, which
is identical with the beautiful. And he must
exhibit the beautiful in every unique and lovely posture
which can be imagined, and which he can skillfully
realize in color, in word, or in sound. Art is
its own justification; “a thing of beauty is
a joy forever.”
Where art is governed by such intentions,
form and material become more important than expression.
Thus there develops in France in the late nineteenth
century a school of Symbolists and Sensationalists
in poetry, whose single aim is the production of precise
and beautiful sensations through the specific use
of evocative words. The form and the style become
everything in literature, in painting, and the plastic
arts. The emphasis is put upon exquisiteness in
decoration, upon precision in technique, upon loveliness
of material. The Pre-Raphaelite movement in poetry,
with its emphasis on the use of picturesque and decorative
epithets, the exclusive emphasis in some modern music
on subtlety of technique in tone and color, are recent
examples.
The position taken has clearly this
much justification. A work does not become a
work of art through the fact that it expresses noble
sentiments. The most righteous sermon may not
be beautiful. Whatever be the source of its inspiration,
art must make its appeal through the palpable and undeniable
beauty of the formal embodiment it has given to its
vision. However much an object be prized as a
moral instrument, unless it stirs the senses and the
imagination, it hardly can be called a work of art.
On the other hand, things intrinsically beautiful
do seem to be their own justification. A poem
of Keats, a Japanese print, a delicate vase, or an
exquisite song demand no moral justification.
They are their own sufficient excuse for being.
But the “art for art’s
sake” doctrine, carried to extremes, results
in mere decadence or triviality. It produces at
best exquisite decorative trifles rather than works
of a large and serious beauty. Music seems to
be the art where sheer beauty of form is its own justification,
for music can hardly be used as a specific medium
of communication. Those compositions that purport
to be “program music,” to convey definite
impressions of particular scenes or ideas, are somewhat
halting attempts to use music as one uses language.
Yet even in music, though we may enjoy ingenious and
fluent melodic trifles, we regard them less highly
than the earnest and magnificent beauty of a Beethoven
symphony.
But because art is only effective
when it appeals to the senses and to the imagination
does not mean that the senses and the imagination
must be stirred by insignificance. The artist
may use the rhythms of music, line and color, the
suggestiveness of words, in the interests of ideal
values. Gifted, as he is, with imaginative foresight
to imagine a world better than the one in which he
is living, he may, by picturing ideals in persuasive
form, not only bring them before the mind of man,
but insinuate them into his heart. The rational
artist may note the possibilities afoot in his environment.
He may treasure these hints of human happiness, and
by giving them vivid reality in the forms of art indicate
captivatingly to men where possible perfections lie.
“For your young men shall see visions, and your
old men shall dream dreams.” The artist
may become the most influential of prophets, for his
prophecies come to men not as arbitrary counsels,
but as pictures of Perfection intrinsically lovely
and intriguing. When Socrates is asked whether
or not his perfect city exists, he replies that it
exists only in Heaven, but that men in beholding it
may, in the light of that divine pattern, learn to
attain in their earthly cities a not dissimilar beauty.