It is well to remind ourselves, from
time to time, that “Ethics” is but another
word for “righteousness,” that for which
many men and women of every generation have hungered
and thirsted, and without which life becomes meaningless.
Certain forms of personal righteousness
have become to a majority of the community almost
automatic. It is as easy for most of us to keep
from stealing our dinners as it is to digest them,
and there is quite as much voluntary morality involved
in one process as in the other. To steal would
be for us to fall sadly below the standard of habit
and expectation which makes virtue easy. In the
same way we have been carefully reared to a sense
of family obligation, to be kindly and considerate
to the members of our own households, and to feel
responsible for their well-being. As the rules
of conduct have become established in regard to our
self-development and our families, so they have been
in regard to limited circles of friends. If the
fulfilment of these claims were all that a righteous
life required, the hunger and thirst would be stilled
for many good men and women, and the clew of right
living would lie easily in their hands.
But we all know that each generation
has its own test, the contemporaneous and current
standard by which alone it can adequately judge of
its own moral achievements, and that it may not legitimately
use a previous and less vigorous test. The advanced
test must indeed include that which has already been
attained; but if it includes no more, we shall fail
to go forward, thinking complacently that we have
“arrived” when in reality we have not yet
started.
To attain individual morality in an
age demanding social morality, to pride one’s
self on the results of personal effort when the time
demands social adjustment, is utterly to fail to apprehend
the situation.
It is perhaps significant that a German
critic has of late reminded us that the one test which
the most authoritative and dramatic portrayal of the
Day of Judgment offers, is the social test. The
stern questions are not in regard to personal and
family relations, but did ye visit the poor, the criminal,
the sick, and did ye feed the hungry?
All about us are men and women who
have become unhappy in regard to their attitude toward
the social order itself; toward the dreary round of
uninteresting work, the pleasures narrowed down to
those of appetite, the declining consciousness of
brain power, and the lack of mental food which characterizes
the lot of the large proportion of their fellow-citizens.
These men and women have caught a moral challenge
raised by the exigencies of contemporaneous life; some
are bewildered, others who are denied the relief which
sturdy action brings are even seeking an escape, but
all are increasingly anxious concerning their actual
relations to the basic organization of society.
The test which they would apply to
their conduct is a social test. They fail to
be content with the fulfilment of their family and
personal obligations, and find themselves striving
to respond to a new demand involving a social obligation;
they have become conscious of another requirement,
and the contribution they would make is toward a code
of social ethics. The conception of life which
they hold has not yet expressed itself in social changes
or legal enactment, but rather in a mental attitude
of maladjustment, and in a sense of divergence between
their consciences and their conduct. They desire
both a clearer definition of the code of morality
adapted to present day demands and a part in its fulfilment,
both a creed and a practice of social morality.
In the perplexity of this intricate situation at least
one thing is becoming clear: if the latter day
moral ideal is in reality that of a social morality,
it is inevitable that those who desire it must be
brought in contact with the moral experiences of the
many in order to procure an adequate social motive.
These men and women have realized
this and have disclosed the fact in their eagerness
for a wider acquaintance with and participation in
the life about them. They believe that experience
gives the easy and trustworthy impulse toward right
action in the broad as well as in the narrow relations.
We may indeed imagine many of them saying: “Cast
our experiences in a larger mould if our lives are
to be animated by the larger social aims. We
have met the obligations of our family life, not because
we had made resolutions to that end, but spontaneously,
because of a common fund of memories and affections,
from which the obligation naturally develops, and
we see no other way in which to prepare ourselves
for the larger social duties.” Such a demand
is reasonable, for by our daily experience we have
discovered that we cannot mechanically hold up a moral
standard, then jump at it in rare moments of exhilaration
when we have the strength for it, but that even as
the ideal itself must be a rational development of
life, so the strength to attain it must be secured
from interest in life itself. We slowly learn
that life consists of processes as well as results,
and that failure may come quite as easily from ignoring
the adequacy of one’s method as from selfish
or ignoble aims. We are thus brought to a conception
of Democracy not merely as a sentiment which desires
the well-being of all men, nor yet as a creed which
believes in the essential dignity and equality of
all men, but as that which affords a rule of living
as well as a test of faith.
We are learning that a standard of
social ethics is not attained by travelling a sequestered
byway, but by mixing on the thronged and common road
where all must turn out for one another, and at least
see the size of one another’s burdens.
To follow the path of social morality results perforce
in the temper if not the practice of the democratic
spirit, for it implies that diversified human experience
and resultant sympathy which are the foundation and
guarantee of Democracy.
There are many indications that this
conception of Democracy is growing among us.
We have come to have an enormous interest in human
life as such, accompanied by confidence in its essential
soundness. We do not believe that genuine experience
can lead us astray any more than scientific data can.
We realize, too, that social perspective
and sanity of judgment come only from contact with
social experience; that such contact is the surest
corrective of opinions concerning the social order,
and concerning efforts, however humble, for its improvement.
Indeed, it is a consciousness of the illuminating
and dynamic value of this wider and more thorough
human experience which explains in no small degree
that new curiosity regarding human life which has
more of a moral basis than an intellectual one.
The newspapers, in a frank reflection
of popular demand, exhibit an omniverous curiosity
equally insistent upon the trivial and the important.
They are perhaps the most obvious manifestations of
that desire to know, that “What is this?”
and “Why do you do that?” of the child.
The first dawn of the social consciousness takes this
form, as the dawning intelligence of the child takes
the form of constant question and insatiate curiosity.
Literature, too, portrays an equally
absorbing though better adjusted desire to know all
kinds of life. The popular books are the novels,
dealing with life under all possible conditions, and
they are widely read not only because they are entertaining,
but also because they in a measure satisfy an unformulated
belief that to see farther, to know all sorts of men,
in an indefinite way, is a preparation for better social
adjustmentfor the remedying of social ills.
Doubtless one under the conviction
of sin in regard to social ills finds a vague consolation
in reading about the lives of the poor, and derives
a sense of complicity in doing good. He likes
to feel that he knows about social wrongs even if
he does not remedy them, and in a very genuine sense
there is a foundation for this belief.
Partly through this wide reading of
human life, we find in ourselves a new affinity for
all men, which probably never existed in the world
before. Evil itself does not shock us as it once
did, and we count only that man merciful in whom we
recognize an understanding of the criminal. We
have learned as common knowledge that much of the insensibility
and hardness of the world is due to the lack of imagination
which prevents a realization of the experiences of
other people. Already there is a conviction that
we are under a moral obligation in choosing our experiences,
since the result of those experiences must ultimately
determine our understanding of life. We know instinctively
that if we grow contemptuous of our fellows, and consciously
limit our intercourse to certain kinds of people whom
we have previously decided to respect, we not only
tremendously circumscribe our range of life, but limit
the scope of our ethics.
We can recall among the selfish people
of our acquaintance at least one common characteristic,the
conviction that they are different from other men
and women, that they need peculiar consideration because
they are more sensitive or more refined. Such
people “refuse to be bound by any relation save
the personally luxurious ones of love and admiration,
or the identity of political opinion, or religious
creed.” We have learned to recognize them
as selfish, although we blame them not for the will
which chooses to be selfish, but for a narrowness of
interest which deliberately selects its experience
within a limited sphere, and we say that they illustrate
the danger of concentrating the mind on narrow and
unprogressive issues.
We know, at last, that we can only
discover truth by a rational and democratic interest
in life, and to give truth complete social expression
is the endeavor upon which we are entering. Thus
the identification with the common lot which is the
essential idea of Democracy becomes the source and
expression of social ethics. It is as though
we thirsted to drink at the great wells of human experience,
because we knew that a daintier or less potent draught
would not carry us to the end of the journey, going
forward as we must in the heat and jostle of the crowd.
The six following chapters are studies
of various types and groups who are being impelled
by the newer conception of Democracy to an acceptance
of social obligations involving in each instance a
new line of conduct. No attempt is made to reach
a conclusion, nor to offer advice beyond the assumption
that the cure for the ills of Democracy is more Democracy,
but the quite unlooked-for result of the studies would
seem to indicate that while the strain and perplexity
of the situation is felt most keenly by the educated
and self-conscious members of the community, the tentative
and actual attempts at adjustment are largely coming
through those who are simpler and less analytical.