It ought not to be the case that there
is one standard of morality for individuals in their
relations with one another, a different and a slighter
standard for corporations, and a third and still slighter
standard for nations. For, after all, what are
corporations but groupings of individuals for ends
which in the last resort are personal ends? And
what are nations but wider, closer, and more lasting
unions of persons for the attainment of the end they
have in common, i.e., the commonwealth.
Yet we are well aware that the accepted and operative
standards of morality differ widely in the three spheres
of conduct. If a soul is imputed at all to a
corporation, it is a leather soul, not easily penetrable
to the probings of pity or compunction, and emitting
much less of the milk of human kindness than do the
separate souls of its directors and stockholders in
their ordinary human relations. There is a sharp
recognition of this inferior moral make-up of a corporation
in the attitude of ordinary men and women, who, scrupulously
honest in their dealings with one another, slide almost
unconsciously to an altogether lower level in dealing
with a railroad or insurance company. This attitude
is due, no doubt, partly to a resentment of the oppressive
power which great corporations are believed to exercise,
evoking a desire “to get a bit of your own back”;
partly to a feeling that any slight injury to, or
even fraud perpetrated on, a corporation will be so
distributed as to inflict no appreciable harm on any
individual stockholder. But largely it is the
result of a failure to envisage a corporation as a
moral being at all, to whom one owes obligations.
Corporations are in a sense moral monsters; we say
they behave as such and we are disposed to treat them
as such.
The standard of international morality,
particularly in matters of commercial intercourse,
is on a still lower level. If, indeed, one were
to press the theoretic issue, whether a state or a
nation is a morally independent being, or whether
it is in some sense or degree a member of what may
be called an incipient society of states or nations,
nearly every one would sustain the latter view.
We should be reminded that there was such a thing
as international law, however imperfect its sanctions
might be, and that treaties, alliances, and other agreements
between nations implied the recognition of some moral
obligation. How weak this interstate morality
is appears not merely from the fact that under strong
temptation governments repudiate their most express
and solemn agreements to that temptation
individuals sometimes yield in their dealings with
one another but also from the nature of
the defence which they make of such repudiation.
The plea of state necessity, which Germany made for
the violation of the neutrality of Belgium, and which
was stretched to cover the brutal mishandling of the
Belgian people, is unfortunately but an extreme instance
of conduct to which every state has had recourse at
times, and still more significant which
every state defends by adducing the same maxim, “salus
reipublicae suprema lex”.
Here is the sharpest distinction between
individual and national morality. There are certain
deeds which a good and honorable man would not do
even to save his life; there are no deeds, which it
is admitted that a statesman, acting on behalf of
his country, may not do to save that country.
It is foolish to try to shirk this disconcerting admission.
The Machiavellian doctrine of “reason of state”
is, in the last resort, the accepted standard of national
conduct. This does not signify that a nation
and its government admit no obligation to fulfil their
promises, or even voluntarily to perform good offices
for other nations, but that there is always implied
the reservation that the necessity, or, shall we say,
the vital interests, of the nation override, cancel,
and nullify all such obligations. And when “necessity”
is stretched to cover any vital interest or urgent
need, it is easy to recognize on what a slippery slope
such international morality reposes.
International morality is impaired,
however, not only by this feeble sense of mutual obligation,
but by the still more injurious assumption of conflicting
interests between nations. Nations are represented
not merely as self-centered, independent moral systems,
but as, in some degree, mutually repellent systems.
This notion is partly the product of the false patriotic
teaching of our schools and press, which seek to feed
our sense of national unity more upon exclusive than
inclusive sentiments. Nations are represented
as rivals and competitors in some struggle for power,
or greatness, or prestige, instead of as cooeperators
in the general advance of civilization. This presumption
of opposing interests is, of course, more strongly
marked in the presentation of commercial relations
than in any other. Putting the issue roughly,
but with substantial truth, the generally accepted
image of international trade is one in which a number
of trading communities, as, for instance, the United
States, Britain, Germany, France, Japan, etc.,
are engaged in striving, each to win for itself, and
at the expense of the others, the largest possible
share of a strictly limited objective the
world market.
Now there are three fatal flaws in
this image. First comes the false presentation
of the United States, Britain, Germany, and other
political beings in the capacity of trading firms.
So far as world or international trade is rightly
presented as a competitive process, that competition
takes place, not between America, Britain, Germany,
but between a number of separate American, British,
German firms. The immediate interests of these
firms are not directed along political lines.
Generally speaking, the closer rivalry is between firms
belonging to the same nation and conducting their business
upon closely similar conditions. One Lancashire
cotton exporter competes much more closely with other
Lancashire exporters than he does with German, American,
or Japanese exporters of similar goods. So it
is everywhere, save in the exceptional times and circumstances
in which governments themselves take over the regulation
and conduct of foreign trade.
For certain purposes it is, no doubt,
convenient to have balances and analyses of foreign
trade presented separately, so as to show the volumes
and values of different goods which pass from the members
of one nation to those of another. But the imputation
of political significance to these statistics, taken
either in aggregate or in relation to separate countries,
as if they were themselves indices of public gain
or public loss, has most injurious reactions upon the
intelligent understanding of commerce.
The second flaw is the assumption
of a limited amount of market, which carries with
it the assumption that the groups of traders, gathered
under their national flags, are engaged in a conflict
in which they are entitled to embroil their governments.
By tariff bargaining and by all sorts of diplomatic
weapons each government is called upon to assist its
nationals and to cripple or exclude the nationals of
other states. Now it is untrue that the world
market is strictly limited, with the consequence that
every advance of one group of traders is at the expense
of another group. The world market is indefinitely
expansible, and is always expanding; and commercial
experience shows that the rapid expansion of the overseas
trade of one country does not preclude the expansion
of trade of other countries. I do not, of course,
deny that at a particular time and in relation to
some particular lucrative opportunity, genuine clashes
of interests may arise. But, envisaging the whole
range of foreign commerce, one feels that the image
of it as a prize which governments can, and ought
to win for their traders at the expense of the traders
supported by other governments, has been a most fertile
source of international misunderstanding.
Perhaps the worst of the three fallacies,
and in a sense the deepest-rooted, is the concept
of export trade as of more value than import trade.
This is often traced back to the time when governments
deemed it desirable to accumulate in their countries
treasures of gold and silver and to this end encouraged
the sale of goods abroad and discouraged the payment
for them in foreign goods. There are, however,
modern supporters of the assumption that it is more
important to sell than to buy, although the money
received for sales has no other significance or value
than its power to buy, and trade can only be imaged
truly as an exchange of goods for goods in which the
processes of selling and of buying are complementary.
The economic explanation of the double
falsehood of dividing buying from selling and of imputing
a higher value to the latter process, lies beyond
the scope of this address. But the injuries resulting
from the superior pressure upon governments of organized
bodies of producers and merchants who have things
to sell, to the detriment of the consuming public
who have only buying needs, are too grave matters to
be neglected here. It is not too much to say
that, if the interests of consumers and the interests
of producers weighed equally in the eyes of governments,
as they should, the strongest of all obstacles to a
peaceful, harmonious society of nations would be overcome.
For the suspicions, jealousies, and hostilities of
nations are inspired more by the tendency of groups
of producers to misrepresent their private interests
as the good of their respective countries than by any
other single circumstance.
This analysis has seemed necessary
in order to clear away the intellectual and moral
fogs which prevent a true realization of the economic,
and therefore the moral, interdependence of nations.
For every bond of economic interest involves moral
obligation also. If it is true that the fabric
of commercial relations is all the time being knit
closer between the different peoples of the earth,
then the moral isolation and the antagonism which
earlier statecraft inculcated, and which still obsess
so many minds, must be dissipated and give place to
active sentiments of human cooeperation.
There were, indeed, those who thought
that already the web of commerce and finance had been
woven strong enough to save nations from the calamity
of war. Their miscalculation arose from underestimating
the power over the mind and the passions of that false
image of trade. But because the modern internationalism
of commerce and finance did not prove strong enough
to stem the full and sudden tide of war passions fed
from the barbarous traditions of a dateless past, we
ought not to disparage the potentiality of this internationalism
as the foundation of a new and better world order.
For, though those bonds of common interest broke under
the strain of war, the confusion in which we find
ourselves without them is itself a terrible testimony
to their value. The enforced sundering of ordinary
trade relations between members of different countries
has taught two clear lessons. The first is this:
that hardly any civilized nation is or can be economically
independent in respect to essential supplies or industries.
There is no European country that does not rely for
the subsistence of its inhabitants upon supplies of
goods and raw materials from foreign lands, mostly
from countries outside the European continent.
While Britain both leaned more heavily upon other
countries and contributed most to other countries
from her surplus produce, every other country, in larger
or less degree great countries such as
France, Germany, Austria, Italy, little ones like
Belgium, Holland, Switzerland, Scandinavia, and Denmark were
increasingly dependent upon outside sources for their
livelihood. It is true that there remained a very
few great backward countries, such as Russia and China,
where a life of economic isolation was possible had
they been willing to dispense with the higher products
of civilized industry and with the fertilizing streams
of capital without which progress is impossible.
No civilized European country was self-sufficing in
the vital factors of a productive and progressive
civilization food, raw materials, machinery,
fuel, transport, finance, and adequate supplies of
skilled labor. The services which countries near
or distant rendered to one another were becoming constantly
more numerous, more complex, and more urgent.
The obstructions and stoppages of war has driven home
the lesson painfully to the inhabitants of every European
country, belligerent or neutral. What lesson?
That we have erred in permitting ourselves to grow
dependent on the industry, goodwill, and intercourse
of other nations, and that we should endeavor to hark
back to an earlier economic state of national independence?
Well, there are even in Britain rhetorical politicians
who speak of the necessity of retaining all “key”
or “essential” industries within their
national control who propose to reverse
the tide of social evolution by some flimsy apparatus
of tariffs and subsidies. This is impossible.
The war has left the European peoples, one and all,
more than ever dependent for their economic livelihood
upon one another, and upon the material resources
and labor of other continents.
The second lesson is that, other things
equal, it is the most highly civilized and highly
developed countries that are the most dependent upon
others. In a word, there is a presumption that
economic internationalism is an essential feature
of civilization.
You will observe that so far I have
made no mention of America. And yet all that
I have been saying is, in a sense, introductory to
the unique problem presented by this country.
America is the only civilized country in the world
that is virtually self-sufficing as regards the primary
requirements of her economic life. Her soil can
and does supply nearly all her essential foods, her
natural resources include the materials of her great
textile, metal, and other basic industries, the heat,
light, electricity, and other forms of natural energy
which satisfy her national needs. She has access
to skilled and unskilled labor sufficient to develop
and utilize all these natural resources. Most
of her pre-war imports might be placed under four heads:
articles of luxury and taste in dress, jewelry, etc.;
certain chemical and other scientific products; supplementary
supplies of some foods and materials, from other countries
of the American continent, for manufactures and export
trade; and a number of tropical products, almost all
of subsidiary significance in the production and consumption
of the American people. This slight dependence
upon foreign countries has been considerably reduced
as the result of war exigency. The art products
of France and Italy, the fine textile goods from Britain,
the dye-stuffs, drugs, and scientific instruments
from Germany in a word, the great bulk
of the imports from Europe, have either been cut out
of American consumption or have been displaced, temporarily,
at any rate, by home products. For several generations
the main dependence of America upon Europe and particularly
upon Britain was for capital to supplement home savings
that she might make use of the stream of immigrant
labor in the development of her great continent.
This dependence upon European capital, of greatly
diminishing importance during the last three decades
has, of course, now been reversed, and the principal
European countries are heavy debtors to the United
States.
One other important economic lesson
war experience has taught, viz., the vast capacity
for increased productivity which every industrial
nation possesses, and America especially, in better
organization and fuller utilization of natural and
human resources. It is evident that, far from
the age of great inventions and of mechanical development
drawing to a close, we are in the actual process of
reaching new discoveries in wealth production, which
will make the most famous advances of the nineteenth
century mean by comparison. But without drawing
upon a speculative future, a better and more systematic
application of the knowledge which has been already
tested enlarged production, elimination
of waste, and improved business methods is
clearly capable of doubling or trebling the output
of material wealth without involving any excessive
strain upon human effort.
Here, as in other ways, America stands
in a place of unique vantage by reason of the magnitude
and variety of her national resources, and the vigor
and enterprise of her people.
It is evident that, if any country
can afford to stand alone in full economic self-sufficiency,
that country is America. It is feasible for America
to contract within very narrow limits her commercial
and political relations with the rest of the world,
or, if she chooses, to confine her commercial and
financial relations to this continent, leaving the
old world to get on by itself as well as it can.
This view is, indeed, conformable with the main tradition
of American history up to the close of the last century.
Even the Spanish war, with its sequel of imperialism,
was but a slight and reparable breach in this tradition.
The world war seems at first sight to have plunged
America deeper into the European trough. But
even this more serious committal is not irretrievable.
She can step back to the doctrine and policy of ‘America
for Americans’ and refuse any organic contact
with a troublesome, a quarrelsome and, as it seems,
a ruined Europe. America’s economic status
in Europe is not such as to preclude her taking this
course. I may be reminded that the indebtedness
of Europe to America is a solid economic bond, for
it cannot be presumed that America would pursue the
policy of liberalism so far as to cancel this debt.
But, large as is this credit, it need not constitute
a strong or a lasting bond of commerce, compelling
America to receive such large imports of goods from
Europe as materially to impair her self-sufficiency.
A large and increasing part of the interest and capital
of this indebtedness would be defrayed by the expenditure
of American travellers and residents in Europe, while
the importation of objects of art and luxury would
not interfere appreciably with the policy of economic
nationalism. If America decides to go no further
in this business, it will not be too late to draw
out.
The choice before her is momentous.
So far I have presented it as an economic problem.
It is also quite evidently a political and moral problem
of the first significance, for economic national self-sufficiency
is a phase of political independence. But business
and politics alike belong to the wider art of human
conduct; and the choice before America is primarily
a moral choice.
By saying this I do not wish to appear
to prejudge the issue. I have always felt that
a stronger case could be made for the political and
economic isolation of America than for that of any
other country, partly because, as I have said, she
has within her political domain all the resources
of national well-being; partly, also, because it is
of supreme importance that the great experiment of
democracy should not be unduly hampered by excessive
inpourings of ill-assimilable foreign blood, and by
dangerous contacts with obsolete or inapplicable European
institutions. As an economist, steeped in the
principles of Cobden and his British school of liberals,
my predilections (prejudices if you will) have always
been in favor of the freest possible movement, alike
of trade and persons, and against fiscal protection
and immigrant restrictions. But, when confronted
with the special situation of America, I have recognized
that a reasoned argument could be addressed to prove
that the economy of national security and progress
for this country lay along the lines of political,
economic and defensive self-containedness. I
am convinced that many must be led to support this
policy, not on grounds of selfishness, because they
desire to conserve for America alone her great opportunities,
and not mainly from fear, lest America should be embroiled
again in the dangerous quarrels of distant European
nations, but because they are animated by that pure
desire, which has inspired so many generations of high-minded
Americans, that American democracy should grow to its
full stature by its own unaided efforts and save the
world by its example.
I wish to give due respect to the
sincerity of this conviction the more because I wish
to lay before you some grounds for questioning its
ultimate validity. It is no problem of abstract
politics or ethics with which I here confront your
minds, but one of concrete and immediate urgency.
Distinctively economic in its substance, it brings
right into the daylight the hitherto obscure issue
of the duty of nations as members of an actual or
potential society of nations. As a result of
the destruction of war a large part of Europe lies
today in economic ruin. By that I do not only,
or chiefly, refer to the material havoc wrought by
the direct operations of war in France, Belgium, Poland,
Servia, and elsewhere. I mean the imminent starvation
which this winter awaits large populations of those
and other countries, both our allies and our late
enemies, and the misery and anarchy arising from their
utter inability to resume the ordinary processes of
productive industry. It is not only food and
clothing but raw materials, tools, machinery, transport,
and fuel that are lacking over a large part of the
European continent. If they are left to their
own unaided resources, millions of these people, especially
in Russia, Poland, Austria, and sections of the late
Turkish Empire, will perish. They cannot feed
themselves. The land remains, but large tracts
of it have been untilled; large numbers of the peasantry
have fallen in the war, or are wandering as disbanded
soldiers, far from home; the women and the aged and
the children, underfed and broken in health and spirit,
are utterly unequal to the task of growing the food
for their livelihood. The factories and workshops
are idle or are ill-equipped, for materials, tools,
and fuel are everywhere lacking; unemployment holds
large industrial populations in destitution and despair.
Even where plant and materials are present, the physical
strength of the workers is so let down that efficient
productivity is impossible. Even in countries
that are not war-broken, the blockade, and the long
stoppage of normal commerce, have caused great scarcity
of many important foods and materials, and famine
prices bring grievous suffering to the poorer classes.
Britain alone among the belligerent countries is not
in immediate distress, but only because she has had
larger outside resources and larger borrowing powers
on which to draw. Even the few neutral nations
which are said to have profited by war are severely
crippled by the lack of some essentials of their economic
life.
All in different degrees are economic
victims of the havoc and the waste of war. It
is not Central Europe only, together with large parts
of the Balkans, of Russia, and of Eastern Asia, that
is in this evil plight. Europe as a whole is
unprovided with the foodstuffs with which to feed
its population and the raw materials with which to
furnish employment. If there were prevailing
among them the best of wills and of cooeperative arrangements,
the European peoples could not keep themselves alive
this winter and make any substantial advance towards
reparation of the damage of war and industrial recovery.
If human cooeperation is to save these weak and desperate
peoples, it must be a cooeperation of more than the
nations of Europe. Only by the better provided
nations of the world coming to the rescue can the
worse-provided nations survive and recover. It
would be foolish to mince words in so grave an issue.
We are all acquainted with the main facts of the world
situation and are familiar with the place which America
occupies in it as the chief repository of those surpluses
of foods, materials, and manufactured goods which
Europe needs so sorely. The term ‘surplus’
is, of course, somewhat deceptive. Surplus depends
largely on home consumption, itself an elastic condition.
But for practical purposes we may take the exportable
surplus to mean the product which remains for sale
abroad after the normal wants of the home population
are supplied. It might mean something more, viz.,
that the home population would voluntarily keep down
or reduce their consumption, in order that more might
be available for export. The American people
actually did exercise this self-denying ordinance to
an appreciable extent, in order to help win the war.
Are they willing to do the same in order to help the
world in a distress as dire as war itself?
It may be said, perhaps truly, that
this presumes that America is in the peace as much
as she was in the war, that she has decided to link
her destiny closely and lastingly with that of Europe,
that she definitely accepts a proffered place as a
member of the society of nations, and under circumstances
which make an immediate call upon her economic and
financial resources in a manner in which there can
be no direct reciprocity.
Now it may reasonably be urged that
America is not prepared for such a committal, that
such obligations as she undertook, as an associated
power, in the conduct of the war, terminate with the
making of peace; and that, as regards the future structure
of international relations, she proposes to preserve
full freedom to cooeperate with other nations, or
to stand alone, according to her estimate of each occasion.
It is here convenient to treat separately
two issues which are none the less closely related,
viz., the issue of international cooeperation
for the immediate work of the salvage and restoration
of Europe, and the issue of a permanent cooeperation
or agreement for the equitable use of the economic
resources of the world. The urgency for Europe
of the first issue has been already indicated.
If the weaker European nations are left to the ordinary
play of economic laws for the supplies they need,
they must lapse into starvation and social anarchy.
A lifting of the war blockades and embargoes hardly
helps them. The formal restoration of free commerce
is little better than a mockery to those who lack
the power to buy and sell. Free commerce would
simply mean that America’s surplus, the food,
materials, and manufactured goods she has to sell
abroad, would be purchased exclusively by those more
prosperous foreigners who have the means to pay in
money, or in export goods available for credit purposes.
Now the populations and the governments of these broken
countries have neither money nor goods in hand.
The return of peace has left them with depleted purses
and empty stores. If the purchase and consumption
of the available surplus of foods, materials, and
manufactures from America and other prosperous countries
is distributed according to the separate powers of
purchase in the European countries, the countries
and the classes of population which are least in need
will get all, those which are most in need, nothing.
How can it be otherwise, if immediate ability to pay
is the criterion? In ordinary times the machinery
of international finance does tend to distribute surplus
stocks according to the needs of the different nations,
for the production of the actual goods for export
trade with which imports are paid for, the true base
of credit, is continually proceeding. But the
war broke this machinery of regular exchange.
It cannot be immediately restored. America or
Argentina cannot sell their surplus wheat in the ordinary
way to Poland, Austria, Belgium and other needy countries,
because, largely for the very lack of these goods
and materials, their industries are not operating,
so that the goods they should produce, upon which
credit would be built, are not forthcoming.
This is one of the most terrible of
the vicious circles in which the war has bound the
world. The weak nations cannot buy, because they
are not producing goods to sell; they cannot produce,
because they cannot buy. What are the strong
nations, those with surplus goods, the transport,
and the credit, going to do about it? It is a
question of emergency finance based on an emergency
morality. The nations which have surpluses to
sell abroad must not only send the goods but provide
the credit to pay for them if they are to reach the
peoples that need them most. But how, it is said,
can you expect the business man in America or any
other country to perform such an act of charity?
How can you expect them to sell to those who have
not credit and cannot pay, instead of selling to those
who have credit and can pay? The answer is sometimes
stated thus. It is not charity you are asked to
perform, but such consideration for customers as a
really intelligent sense of self-interest will endorse.
We ask you to put up a temporary bridge over the financial
chasm in order to afford time for this restoration
of the ordinary processes of exchange. If the
enfeebled industrial peoples can be furnished now
with foods and materials they will set to work, and
in the course of time they will be able, out of the
product of their industry, to repay your advances
and reestablish the normal circle of exchange.
In presenting this course as a policy
of intelligent self-interest, I am not really disparaging
the claims of humanity or of morals. I am merely
maintaining the utilitarian ethics which insist that
morality, the performance of human obligations, is
the best policy, that policy which in the long run
will yield the fullest satisfaction to social beings.
If I were an American exporter in control of large
amounts of food, it would doubtless pay me better
personally at the present time to sell it to firms
in European countries which have good credit, for
consumption by people who are in no great want.
As an individual business man, I could hardly do otherwise
with any assurance of financial profit. I am
not here presenting the issue as a matter of individual
morals. If the surplus of economic supplies is
to be distributed according to needs, on an emergency
credit basis adjusted to that end, it is evident that
this can be done only by international cooeperation.
This shifts the moral problem from the individual to
the nation. Rich nations, or their governments,
are asked to assist poor nations by making an apportionment
of goods and credit which the individual members of
the rich nations, the owners of the surplus, would
not make upon their own account. The edge of this
issue should not be blunted. If the people and
government of America were only concerned to let their
individual citizens extort the highest prices they
could get for their surplus in the best markets, they
would let Central and Eastern Europe starve.
If, however, they also take into account the social,
political, and economic reactions of a starving Europe
upon the future of a world in which they will have
to live as members of a world society which must grow
ever closer in its physical, economic, and spiritual
contacts, they may decide differently. The issue
arises in the highest economic sphere, that of finance.
Are the nations and governments of the world sufficiently
alive to the urgency of the situation to enter into
an organization of credit for the emergency use of
transport and for the distribution of foods and materials
on a basis of proved needs? The richer nations,
in proportion to their resources, would appear to
be called upon to make a present sacrifice for the
benefit of the poorer nations in any such pooling of
credit facilities. That risk of sacrifice, however,
need not be great, and need not be felt at all by
the individual members of rich nations, provided that
the hitherto unused resources of national credit can
be built into a strong structure of mutual support.
If America were invited to find adequate credits for
Italian or Polish needs at the present time, she might
well hesitate. But if a consortium of European
governments, including Britain and the richer neutrals,
were joint guarantors of such advances, this cooeperative
basis might furnish the necessary confidence.
It is not within my scope to discuss the various forms
a financial consortium might take; whether America,
as representative of the creditor nations, should
enter such a consortium, or should approach the organized
credit of Europe in the capacity of a friendly uncle.
It must suffice here to indicate the moral test which
this grave issue presents to the nations regarded as
economic powers.
Upon the policy adopted for this emergency
will doubtless depend in large measure the whole future
of economic internationalism. For not only does
confidence grow with effective cooeperation, but upon
this post-war cooeperation between nations for an
emergency commerce and finance, or its rejection,
will depend not only America’s future place
in a world society but the structure of that world
society in its essential character.
For in each great nation of the world
the same great choice, the same great struggle of
contending principles and policies, is taking place.
National self-dependence or internationalism that
is everywhere the issue. It is true that in no
European country can that issue be so sharply presented
as in America. For economic self-sufficiency in
a full sense and, therefore, political isolation,
is not possible for any European state. Even
a peaceful and reviving Russia must lean upon her
more advanced neighbors for the economic essentials
of capital and organizing skill. But the several
nations can strive to reduce their interdependence
and their national aid to the narrowest dimensions,
and where they cannot free themselves from extraneous
alliances they can restrict the area of economic dependence
within a chosen circle. Britain, for example,
could set her policy closely and consistently to make
her world-wide empire into a self-sufficing system,
and if, as is likely, she learned that even the diversified
fifth of the entire globe which owns allegiance to
her Crown could not satisfy all her wants, she could
eke out this inadequacy with some carefully selected
and purchased friendships.
This harking back to an economic nationalism
is a natural reaction of the war, and is fed by a
dangerous and precarious peace. Fear, greed,
and suspicion prompt the victorious nations to guard
their gains by reverting to a close nationalism or
a ringed alliance; humiliation, without humility,
the bitter pain of thwarted ambitions, resentment at
their punishment, dispose the vanquished nations to
keep their own company and form if possible, an economic
system of their own. A prolonged war, followed
by a bad peace, may leave this indelible scar upon
the growing economic internationalism of the world.
The richly nourished patriotism of
war breeds divisions and antagonisms which are easily
exploited afterwards by political, racial, religious,
and cultural passions, but most of all by economic
interests.
Before the war internationalism was
visibly advancing with every fresh decade. The
bonds of commercial and financial intercourse between
the peoples of different countries were continually
woven closer; the policy of self-sufficiency was continually
giving way before the superior economy of specialization
on a basis of natural or acquired advantages.
Any reversal of this policy would be far costlier than
may at present appear, even for those countries best
qualified by size and resources to stand alone.
For it is not merely the direct sacrifice
of the wider world economy of production and exchange,
the advantage of a wider over a narrower area of free
commerce, that is involved. It is the indirect
perils and costs of the policy of close nationalism
or restricted economic alliances that count heaviest.
For economic nationalism means protective and discriminative
tariffs, and a conservation of national, imperial or
allied resources within a circle of favored beneficiaries.
This is the temptation held out to the British people
today by the protectionist interests working upon
the animosity of the war spirit and the sentiment
of imperialism. The welding of an empire into
an independent economic system, the conservation of
essential or key industries and the safeguarding of
our industries against “dumping,” are the
ostensible objectives of a policy whose chief driving
motive and end is the establishment of strong industrial,
commercial and financial trusts and combinations,
defended by tariff walls, and endowed with the profits
of monopoly.
There are two difficulties in such
a course of action, which, though especially urgent
in the case of Britain, beset every great country
that chooses the same path, and not least, America.
The first is the fomentation of a class war, based
upon divisions of interests between capital and labor,
producer and consumer, protected and unprotected industries.
The initial skirmishes of such a conflict are already
visible in every country where wages, prices, and profiteering
are burning issues. I would most earnestly appeal
to thoughtful citizens in this as in my own country
to pause before heaping fuel on these fires.
For the policy of national self-sufficiency or isolation
means nothing less than this. Not merely does
it strengthen the power of capitalistic combinations
and thereby incite labor unions to direct action,
blackmailing demands, and sabotage. Not merely
does it let loose upon the business world all sorts
of ill-considered governmental interferences for the
fixation of prices or subsidies to consumers.
It keeps alive and feeds the habit and the spirit
of strife. For it was no accident that the great
international war left as its legacy smaller international
class wars in European countries. Remove from
a nation the economic supports it formerly received
from other nations, markets wherein to buy and sell,
and you starve that nation; and starvation breeds
class war and anarchy. Can any one doubt this
with the terrible examples of Russia and Hungary before
their eyes? But it is not a matter of war conditions
alone. Carry through a policy of economic nationalism,
under which all the large and well-equipped nations
and empires conserve for their exclusive uses the
national resources they command, and what happens?
The smaller and the poorer nations, however free in
the political sense, become their economic bond slaves,
at the mercy of the master states for their foods
and other necessaries of life. Take the case
of Austria under the new conditions, with a thick
population concentrated in a great political capital
suddenly deprived of all free access to its former
sources of supply and the markets it used to serve.
For her it is a sentence of economic strangulation.
Here is an extreme instance of the effect of economic
isolation on a weak country. But the dangerous
truth may be more broadly stated. A very few
great empires and nations today control the whole available
supplies of many of the foods, fabrics, and metals,
the shipping and finance, that are essential to the
livelihood and progress of every civilized people.
Are Britain, America, France, and Japan and
especially the two greatest of these powers going
to absorb or monopolize for their exclusive purposes
of trade or consumption these supplies which every
country needs, or are they going to let the rest of
the world have fair access to them? I think this
to be upon the whole the most important of the many
urgent issues that confront us. For, if close
nationalism or imperialism should prevail, the weaker
placed nations could not acquiesce. Close economic
nationalism is not for them a possibility. They
must win access to the world’s supplies, peacefully
if possible, or else by force.
The fatality of the great choice is
thus evident. Nations must and will fight for
the means of life. Close economic nationalism
or imperialism on the part of the great empires must,
therefore, compel the restricted countries to organize
force for their economic liberation. This in turn
will compel the great empires to maintain strong military
and naval defences. It is impossible for the
other nations of the earth to leave the essential
supplies of metals, foods, and oils, and the control
of transport in the exclusive possession of one or
a few close national corporations or a permanent “Big
Four.” Under such conditions the sacrifices
of the great war would have been made in vain.
Nothing would have been done to end war, or to rescue
the world from the burden of militarism. The
pre-war policy of contending alliances and of competing
armaments, draining more deeply than ever the surplus
incomes of each people, would be resumed. And
it would bring no sense of security, but only the
postponement of further inevitable conflicts in which
the very roots of western civilization might perish.
The renewed and intolerable burdens
of such a militarism, with its accompaniments of autocracy,
must let loose class war in every nation which has
gone through the agony of the European struggle and
has seen the great hope of a peaceful internationalism
blighted.
It is predominantly upon America and
Britain that this great moral economic choice rests,
the choice on which the safety and the progress of
humanity depend. A refusal by either of these
great powers can make any league of nations and any
economic internationalism impossible. The confident
consent of both can furnish the material and moral
support for the new order. If these countries
in close concerted action were prepared to place at
the service of the new world order their exclusive
or superior resources of foods, materials, transport
and finance the economic pillars of civilization the
stronger pooling their resources with the weaker for
the rescue work in this dire emergency, this political
cooeperation would supply that mutual confidence and
goodwill without which no governmental machinery of
a League of Nations, however skilfully contrived,
can begin to work.
I have spoken of Britain and America
as the two countries upon whose choice this supreme
issue hangs. But the act of choice is not the
same for the two. The British imperial policy
(apart from that of the self-governing dominions)
has been conducted on a basis of free trade or economic
internationalism. A reversion to close imperialism
would be for her a retrogression. The United
States, on the other hand, has practised a distinctively
national economy, and the adoption of a free internationalism
would be a great act of faith, or as some
would put it a leap in the dark.
I prefer the former term as indicative
of the new truth which is dawning on the world, the
conviction that just as an individual can only fully
realize his personality in a society of other individuals,
that is, a nation, so nations cannot rise to the full
stature of nationalism save in a society of nations.
For only thus can nationality, either in its economic
or its spiritual side, make full use of its special
opportunities for the development of a distinctive
national character. The supreme challenge is,
therefore, not to the continental European nations,
not even to Britain, but to America. For her
alone the choice has the full quality of moral freedom.
For she alone is able to refuse. Other great
western nations might seek to stand alone for economic
life and for defence. They could not long succeed;
they are too deeply implicated in one another’s
destinies. Even Britain with her vast extra-European
territories could not hope to disentangle herself
from the affairs of her near neighbors. America
could do this, at any rate for some considerable time
to come. True she has economic committals in
Europe. She has loaned European governments and
peoples some ten milliards of money. She
is still lending her credit to support the large surplus
supplies of foods and other goods she is selling Europe.
If this business is to continue, it will implicate
her even closer in European affairs. Europe in
its present case can hardly be presented as a safe
business proposition. If America proceeds along
this path, it will be because she looks beyond the
immediate risks to the wider future of a safer and
more prosperous world. She could now draw out;
she could cut the present economic losses of her European
loans; she could divert her attention from the European
markets to the development of the American continent
as the principal area for the disposal of her surplus
goods and energies.
It is open to her to take this course.
Prudence may seem to dictate it. The reckless
mismanagement of European governments, the wild unsettlement
of peoples, the badness of the peace, are, indeed,
strong arguments for America cleaving to her old ways.
Europe has no rightful claim upon
America, either for the urgent work of economic rescue,
or for participation in the permanent project of a
society of nations. America not only has the right
to refuse; it is probably to her immediate interest
to refuse. But, at the risk of misinterpretation,
as an officious outsider, I will venture to present
an appeal to the wider and deeper interests of Americans.
The refusal of America not only shuts the gate of
hope for millions of war-broken, famine-ridden people
in Central and Eastern Europe, it removes the keystone
for the edifice of a society of nations. For effective
international cooeperation in economic resources and
opportunities is the indispensable condition of such
a society. No League of Nations can survive its
infancy without this economic nourishment. The
world’s wealth for the world’s wants:
unless this maxim can in some effective way be realized,
no such escape has been made from the pre-war policy
of greed and grab as will furnish a reasonable hope
for a world redeemed from war a world clothed
and in its right mind.
Is it not the larger and the longer
hope and interest of America to live as a great partner
in such a society of nations, rather than to live
a life of isolated prosperity, perhaps the sole survivor
in the collapse of western civilized states?
I make this appeal in the language of Edmund Burke,
in his great plea for conciliation with America, when
he reminded his hearers that “Magnanimity in
politics is not seldom the truest wisdom.”
This, I venture to say, is the true appeal of Europe
to America today. Burke’s words, I feel,
must kindle conviction in every generous heart, for
in the last resort it is the desire of the heart and
not the calculation of the intellect that governs
and should govern human conduct. For morality
among nations, as among individuals, implies faith
and risk-taking, not recklessness, indeed, but dangerous
living, a willingness and a desire to take a hand
in the largest game of life and continually to “pluck
out of the nettle, danger, safety”; but this
safety itself only as a momentary resting-place in
the unceasing urge of nations to use their nationality,
not for the achievement of some selfish separate perfection,
but for the ever advancing realization of national
ends within the wider circle of humanity.