THE ROMANIA IDEA AND THE ENGLISH IDEA.
It used to be the fashion of historians,
looking superficially at the facts presented in chronicles
and tables of dates, without analyzing and comparing
vast groups of facts distributed through centuries,
or even suspecting the need for such analysis and
comparison, to assign the date 476 A.D. as the moment
at which the Roman Empire came to an end. It was
in that year that the soldier of fortune, Odovakar,
commander of the Herulian mercenaries in Italy, sent
the handsome boy Romulus, son of Orestes, better known
as “little Augustus,” from his imperial
throne to the splendid villa of Lucullus near Naples,
and gave him a yearly pension of $35,000 [6,000 solidi]
to console him for the loss of a world. As 324
years elapsed before another emperor was crowned at
Rome, and as the political headship of Europe after
that happy restoration remained upon the German soil
to which the events of the eighth century had shifted
it, nothing could seem more natural than the habit
which historians once had, of saying that the mighty
career of Rome had ended, as it had begun, with a
Romulus. Sometimes the date 476 was even set up
as a great landmark dividing modern from ancient history.
For those, however, who took such a view, it was impossible
to see the events of the Middle Ages in their true
relations to what went before and what came after.
It was impossible to understand what went on in Italy
in the sixth century, or to explain the position of
that great Roman power which had its centre on the
Bosphorus, which in the code of Justinian left us
our grandest monument of Roman law, and which for a
thousand years was the staunch bulwark of Europe against
the successive aggressions of Persian, Saracen, and
Turk. It was equally impossible to understand
the rise of the Papal power, the all-important politics
of the great Saxon and Swabian emperors, the relations
of mediaeval England to the Continental powers, or
the marvellously interesting growth of the modern
European system of nationalities.
Since the middle of the nineteenth
century the study of history has undergone changes
no less sweeping than those which have in the same
time affected the study of the physical sciences.
Vast groups of facts distributed through various ages
and countries have been subjected to comparison and
analysis, with the result that they have not only thrown
fresh light upon one another, but have in many cases
enabled us to recover historic points of view that
had long been buried in oblivion. Such an instance
was furnished about twenty-five years ago by Dr. Bryce’s
epoch-making work on the Holy Roman Empire. Since
then historians still recognize the importance of
the date 476 as that which left the Bishop of Rome
the dominant personage in Italy, and marked the shifting
of the political centre of gravity from the Palatine
to the Lateran. This was one of those subtle
changes which escape notice until after some of their
effects have attracted attention. The most important
effect, in this instance, realized after three centuries,
was not the overthrow of Roman power in the West,
but its indefinite extension and expansion. The
men of 476 not only had no idea that they were entering
upon a new era, but least of all did they dream that
the Roman Empire had come to an end, or was ever likely
to. Its cities might be pillaged, its provinces
overrun, but the supreme imperial power itself was
something without which the men of those days could
not imagine the world as existing. It must have
its divinely ordained representative in one place
if not in another. If the throne in Italy was
vacant, it was no more than had happened before; there
was still a throne at Constantinople, and to its occupant
Zeno the Roman Senate sent a message, saying that
one emperor was enough for both ends of the earth,
and begging him to confer upon the gallant Odovakar
the title of patrician, and entrust the affairs of
Italy to his care. So when Sicambrian Chlodwig
set up his Merovingian kingdom in northern Gaul, he
was glad to array himself in the robe of a Roman consul,
and obtain from the eastern emperor a formal ratification
of his rule.
If we look back for a moment to the
primitive stages of society, we may picture to ourselves
the surface of the earth sparsely and scantily covered
with wandering tribes of savages, rude in morals and
manners, narrow and monotonous in experience, sustaining
life very much as lower animals sustain it, by gathering
wild fruits or slaying wild game, and waging chronic
warfare alike with powerful beasts and with rival tribes
of men.
In the widest sense the subject of
political history is the description of the processes
by which, under favourable circumstances, innumerable
such primitive tribes have become welded together into
mighty nations, with elevated standards of morals
and manners, with wide and varied experience, sustaining
life and ministering to human happiness by elaborate
arts and sciences, and putting a curb upon warfare
by limiting its scope, diminishing its cruelty, and
interrupting it by intervals of peace. The story,
as laid before us in the records of three thousand
years, is fascinating and absorbing in its human interest
for those who content themselves with the study of
its countless personal incidents, and neglect its
profound philosophical lessons. But for those
who study it in the scientific spirit, the human interest
of its details becomes still more intensely fascinating
and absorbing. Battles and coronations, poems
and inventions, migrations and martyrdoms, acquire
new meanings and awaken new emotions as we begin to
discern their bearings upon the solemn work of ages
that is slowly winning for humanity a richer and more
perfect life. By such meditation upon men’s
thoughts and deeds is the understanding purified,
till we become better able to comprehend our relations
to the world and the duty that lies upon each of us
to shape his conduct rightly.
In the welding together of primitive
shifting tribes into stable and powerful nations,
we can seem to discern three different methods that
have been followed at different times and places, with
widely different results. In all cases the fusion
has been effected by war, but it has gone on in three
broadly contrasted ways. The first of these methods,
which has been followed from time immemorial in the
Oriental world, may be roughly described as conquest
without incorporation. A tribe grows to national
dimensions by conquering and annexing its neighbours,
without admitting them to a share in its political
life. Probably there is always at first some
incorporation, or even perhaps some crude germ of
federative alliance; but this goes very little way, only
far enough to fuse together a few closely related
tribes, agreeing in speech and habits, into a single
great tribe that can overwhelm its neighbours.
In early society this sort of incorporation cannot
go far without being stopped by some impassable barrier
of language or religion. After reaching that
point, the conquering tribe simply annexes its neighbours
and makes them its slaves. It becomes a superior
caste, ruling over vanquished peoples, whom it oppresses
with frightful cruelty, while living on the fruits
of their toil in what has been aptly termed Oriental
luxury. Such has been the origin of many eastern
despotisms, in the valleys of the Nile and Euphrates,
and elsewhere. Such a political structure admits
of a very considerable development of material civilization,
in which gorgeous palaces and artistic temples may
be built, and perhaps even literature and scholarship
rewarded, with money wrung from millions of toiling
wretches. There is that sort of brutal strength
in it, that it may endure for many long ages, until
it comes into collision with some higher civilization.
Then it is likely to end in sudden collapse, because
the fighting quality of the people has been destroyed.
Populations that have lived for centuries in fear of
impalement or crucifixion, and have known no other
destination for the products of their labour than
the clutches of the omnipresent tax-gatherer, are
not likely to furnish good soldiers. A handful
of freemen will scatter them like sheep, as the Greeks
did twenty-three centuries ago at Kynaxa, as the English
did the other day at Tel el-Kebir. On the other
hand, where the manliness of the vanquished people
is not crushed, the sway of the conquerors who cannot
enter into political union with them is likely to
be cast off, as in the case of the Moors in Spain.
There was a civilization in many respects admirable.
It was eminent for industry, science, art, and poetry;
its annals are full of romantic interest; it was in
some respects superior to the Christian system which
supplanted it; in many ways it contributed largely
to the progress of the human race; and it was free
from some of the worst vices of Oriental civilizations.
Yet because of the fundamental defect that between
the Christian Spaniard and his Mussulman conqueror
there could be no political fusion, this brilliant
civilization was doomed. During eight centuries
of more or less extensive rule in the Spanish peninsula,
the Moor was from first to last an alien, just as
after four centuries the Turk is still an alien in
the Balkan peninsula. The natural result was a
struggle that lasted age after age till it ended in
the utter extermination of one of the parties, and
left behind it a legacy of hatred and persecution that
has made the history of modern Spain a dismal record
of shame and disaster.
In this first method of nation-making,
then, which we may call the Oriental method, one now
sees but little to commend. It was better than
savagery, and for a long time no more efficient method
was possible, but the leading peoples of the world
have long since outgrown it; and although the resulting
form of political government is the oldest we know
and is not yet extinct, it nevertheless has not the
elements of permanence. Sooner or later it will
disappear, as savagery is disappearing, as the rudest
types of inchoate human society have disappeared.
The second method by which nations
have been made may be called the Roman method; and
we may briefly describe it as conquest with incorporation,
but without representation. The secret of
Rome’s wonderful strength lay in the fact that
she incorporated the vanquished peoples into her own
body politic. In the early time there was a fusion
of tribes going on in Latium, which, if it had gone
no further, would have been similar to the early fusion
of Ionic tribes in Attika or of Iranian tribes
in Media. But whereas everywhere else this political
fusion soon stopped, in the Roman world it went on.
One after another Italian tribes and Italian towns
were not merely overcome but admitted to a share in
the political rights and privileges of the victors.
By the time this had gone on until the whole Italian
peninsula was consolidated under the headship of Rome,
the result was a power incomparably greater than any
other that the world had yet seen. Never before
had so many people been brought under one government
without making slaves of most of them. Liberty
had existed before, whether in barbaric tribes or
in Greek cities. Union had existed before, in
Assyrian or Persian despotisms. Now liberty and
union were for the first time joined together, with
consequences enduring and stupendous. The whole
Mediterranean world was brought under one government;
ancient barriers of religion, speech, and custom were
overthrown in every direction; and innumerable barbarian
tribes, from the Alps to the wilds of northern Britain,
from the Bay of Biscay to the Carpathian mountains,
were more or less completely transformed into Roman
citizens, protected by Roman law, and sharing in the
material and spiritual benefits of Roman civilization.
Gradually the whole vast structure became permeated
by Hellenic and Jewish thought, and thus were laid
the lasting foundations of modern society, of a common
Christendom, furnished with a common stock of ideas
concerning man’s relation to God and the world,
and acknowledging a common standard of right and wrong.
This was a prodigious work, which raised human life
to a much higher plane than that which it had formerly
occupied, and endless gratitude is due to the thousands
of steadfast men who in one way or another devoted
their lives to its accomplishment.
This Roman method of nation-making
had nevertheless its fatal shortcomings, and it was
only very slowly, moreover, that it wrought out its
own best results. It was but gradually that the
rights and privileges of Roman citizenship were extended
over the whole Roman world, and in the mean time there
were numerous instances where conquered provinces
seemed destined to no better fate than had awaited
the victims of Egyptian or Assyrian conquest.
The rapacity and cruelty of Caius Verres could
hardly have been outdone by the worst of Persian satraps;
but there was a difference. A moral sense and
political sense had been awakened which could see
both the wickedness and the folly of such conduct.
The voice of a Cicero sounded with trumpet tones against
the oppressor, who was brought to trial and exiled
for deeds which under the Oriental system, from the
days of Artaxerxes to those of the Grand Turk, would
scarcely have called forth a reproving word. It
was by slow degrees that the Roman came to understand
the virtues of his own method, and learned to apply
it consistently until the people of all parts of the
empire were, in theory at least, equal before the law.
In theory, I say, for in point of fact there was enough
of viciousness in the Roman system to prevent it from
achieving permanent success. Historians have
been fond of showing how the vitality of the whole
system was impaired by wholesale slave-labour, by
the false political economy which taxes all for the
benefit of a few, by the debauching view of civil office
which regards it as private perquisite and not as public
trust, and worst of all, perhaps by
the communistic practice of feeding an idle proletariat
out of the imperial treasury. The names of these
deadly social evils are not unfamiliar to American
ears. Even of the last we have heard ominous
whispers in the shape of bills to promote mendicancy
under the specious guise of fostering education or
rewarding military services. And is it not a
striking illustration of the slowness with which mankind
learns the plainest rudiments of wisdom and of justice,
that only in the full light of the nineteenth century,
and at the cost of a terrible war, should the most
intelligent people on earth have got rid of a system
of labour devised in the crudest ages of antiquity
and fraught with misery to the employed, degradation
to the employers, and loss to everybody?
These evils, we see, in one shape
or another, have existed almost everywhere; and the
vice of the Roman system did not consist in the fact
that under it they were fully developed, but in the
fact that it had no adequate means of overcoming them.
Unless helped by something supplied from outside the
Roman world, civilization must have succumbed to these
evils, the progress of mankind must have been stopped.
What was needed was the introduction of a fierce spirit
of personal liberty and local self-government.
The essential vice of the Roman system was that it
had been unable to avoid weakening the spirit of personal
independence and crushing out local self-government
among the peoples to whom it had been applied.
It owed its wonderful success to joining Liberty with
Union, but as it went on it found itself compelled
gradually to sacrifice Liberty to Union, strengthening
the hands of the central government and enlarging
its functions more and more, until by and by the political
life of the several parts had so far died away that,
under the pressure of attack from without, the Union
fell to pieces and the whole political system had
to be slowly and painfully reconstructed.
Now if we ask why the Roman government
found itself thus obliged to sacrifice personal liberty
and local independence to the paramount necessity
of holding the empire together, the answer will point
us to the essential and fundamental vice of the Roman
method of nation-making. It lacked the principle
of representation. The old Roman world knew nothing
of representative assemblies.
Its senates were assemblies of notables,
constituting in the main an aristocracy of men who
had held high office; its popular assemblies were
primary assemblies, town-meetings.
There was no notion of such a thing as political power
delegated by the people to representatives who were
to wield it away from home and out of sight of their
constituents. The Roman’s only notion of
delegated power was that of authority delegated by
the government to its generals and prefects who discharged
at a distance its military and civil functions.
When, therefore, the Roman popular government, originally
adapted to a single city, had come to extend itself
over a large part of the world, it lacked the one
institution by means of which government could be carried
on over so vast an area without degenerating into
despotism.
Even could the device of representation
have occurred to the mind of some statesman trained
in Roman methods, it would probably have made no difference.
Nobody would have known how to use it. You cannot
invent an institution as you would invent a plough.
Such a notion as that of representative government
must needs start from small beginnings and grow in
men’s minds until it should become part and parcel
of their mental habits. For the want of it the
home government at Rome became more and more unmanageable
until it fell into the hands of the army, while at
the same time the administration of the empire became
more and more centralized; the people of its various
provinces, even while their social condition was in
some respects improved, had less and less voice in
the management of their local affairs, and thus the
spirit of personal independence was gradually weakened.
This centralization was greatly intensified by the
perpetual danger of invasion on the northern and eastern
frontiers, all the way from the Rhine to the Euphrates.
Do what it would, the government must become more and
more a military despotism, must revert toward the
Oriental type. The period extending from the
third century before Christ to the third century after
was a period of extraordinary intellectual expansion
and moral awakening; but when we observe the governmental
changes introduced under the emperor Diocletian at
the very end of this period, we realize how serious
had been the political retrogression, how grave the
danger that the stream of human life might come to
stagnate in Europe, as it had long since stagnated
in Asia.
Two mighty agents, cooperating in
their opposite ways to prevent any such disaster,
were already entering upon the scene. The first
was the colonization of the empire by Germanic tribes
already far advanced beyond savagery, already somewhat
tinctured with Roman civilization, yet at the same
time endowed with an intense spirit of personal and
local independence. With this wholesome spirit
they were about to refresh and revivify the empire,
but at the risk of undoing its work of political organization
and reducing it to barbarism. The second was the
establishment of the Roman church, an institution capable
of holding European society together in spite of a
political disintegration that was widespread and long-continued.
While wave after wave of Germanic colonization poured
over romanized Europe, breaking down old boundary-lines
and working sudden and astonishing changes on the map,
setting up in every quarter baronies, dukedoms, and
kingdoms fermenting with vigorous political life;
while for twenty generations this salutary but wild
and dangerous work was going on, there was never a
moment when the imperial sway of Rome was quite set
aside and forgotten, there was never a time when union
of some sort was not maintained through the dominion
which the church had established over the European
mind. When we duly consider this great fact in
its relations to what went before and what came after,
it is hard to find words fit to express the debt of
gratitude which modern civilization owes to the Roman
Catholic church. When we think of all the work,
big with promise of the future, that went on in those
centuries which modern writers in their ignorance used
once to set apart and stigmatize as the “Dark
Ages”; when we consider how the seeds of what
is noblest in modern life were then painfully sown
upon the soil which imperial Rome had prepared; when
we think of the various work of a Gregory, a Benedict,
a Boniface, an Alfred, a Charlemagne; we feel that
there is a sense in which the most brilliant achievements
of pagan antiquity are dwarfed in comparison with these.
Until quite lately, indeed, the student of history
has had his attention too narrowly confined to the
ages that have been preeminent for literature and
art the so-called classical ages and
thus his sense of historical perspective has been
impaired. When Mr. Freeman uses Gregory of Tours
as a text-book, he shows that he realizes how an epoch
may be none the less portentous though it has not
had a Tacitus to describe it, and certainly no part
of history is more full of human interest than the
troubled period in which the powerful streams of Teutonic
life pouring into Roman Europe were curbed in their
destructiveness and guided to noble ends by the Catholic
church. Out of the interaction between these two
mighty agents has come the political system of the
modern world. The moment when this interaction
might have seemed on the point of reaching a complete
and harmonious result was the glorious thirteenth century,
the culminating moment of the Holy Roman Empire.
Then, as in the times of Cæsar or Trajan, there might
have seemed to be a union among civilized men, in
which the separate life of individuals and localities
was not submerged. In that golden age alike of
feudal system, of empire, and of church, there were
to be seen the greatest monarchs, in fullest sympathy
with their peoples, that Christendom has known, an
Edward I., a St. Louis, a Frederick ii.
Then when in the pontificates of Innocent iii.
and his successors the Roman church reached its apogee,
the religious yearnings of men sought expression in
the sublimest architecture the world has seen.
Then Aquinas summed up in his profound speculations
the substance of Catholic theology, and while the
morning twilight of modern science might be discerned
in the treatises of Roger Bacon, while wandering minstrelsy
revealed the treasures of modern speech, soon to be
wrought under the hands of Dante and Chaucer into forms
of exquisite beauty, the sacred fervour of the apostolic
ages found itself renewed in the tender and mystic
piety of St. Francis of Assisi. It was a wonderful
time, but after all less memorable as the culmination
of mediaeval empire and mediaeval church than as the
dawning of the new era in which we live to-day, and
in which the development of human society proceeds
in accordance with more potent methods than those devised
by the genius of pagan or Christian Rome.
For the origin of these more potent
methods we must look back to the early ages of the
Teutonic people; for their development and application
on a grand scale we must look chiefly to the history
of that most Teutonic of peoples in its institutions,
though perhaps not more than half-Teutonic in blood,
the English, with their descendants in the New World.
The third method of nation-making may be called the
Teutonic or preeminently the English method.
It differs from the Oriental and Roman methods which
we have been considering in a feature of most profound
significance; it contains the principle of representation.
For this reason, though like all nation-making it
was in its early stages attended with war and conquest,
it nevertheless does not necessarily require war and
conquest in order to be put into operation. Of
the other two methods war was an essential part.
In the typical Oriental nation, such as Assyria or
Persia, we see a conquering tribe holding down a number
of vanquished peoples, and treating them like slaves:
here the nation is very imperfectly made, and its
government is subject to sudden and violent changes.
In the Roman empire we see a conquering people hold
sway over a number of vanquished peoples, but instead
of treating them like slaves, it gradually makes them
its equals before the law; here the resulting political
body is much more nearly a nation, and its government
is much more stable. A Lydian of the fifth century
before Christ felt no sense of allegiance to the Persian
master who simply robbed and abused him; but the Gaul
of the fifth century after Christ was proud of the
name of Roman and ready to fight for the empire of
which he was a citizen. We have seen, nevertheless,
that for want of representation the Roman method failed
when applied to an immense territory, and the government
tended to become more and more despotic, to revert
toward the Oriental type. Now of the English or
Teutonic method, I say, war is not an essential part;
for where representative government is once established,
it is possible for a great nation to be formed by
the peaceful coalescence of neighbouring states, or
by their union into a federal body. An instance
of the former was the coalescence of England and Scotland
effected early in the eighteenth century after ages
of mutual hostility; for instances of the latter we
have Switzerland and the United States. Now federalism,
though its rise and establishment may be incidentally
accompanied by warfare, is nevertheless in spirit
pacific. Conquest in the Oriental sense is quite
incompatible with it; conquest in the Roman sense is
hardly less so. At the close of our Civil War
there were now and then zealous people to be found
who thought that the southern states ought to be treated
as conquered territory, governed by prefects sent
from Washington, and held down by military force for
a generation or so. Let us hope that there are
few to-day who can fail to see that such a course would
have been fraught with almost as much danger as the
secession movement itself. At least it would
have been a hasty confession, quite uncalled for and
quite untrue, that American federalism had thus far
proved itself incompetent, that we had
indeed preserved our national unity, but only at the
frightful cost of sinking to a lower plane of national
life.
But federalism, with its pacific implications,
was not an invention of the Teutonic mind. The
idea was familiar to the city communities of ancient
Greece, which, along with their intense love of self-government,
felt the need of combined action for warding off external
attack. In their Achaian and Aitolian leagues
the Greeks made brilliant attempts toward founding
a nation upon some higher principle than that of mere
conquest, and the history of these attempts is exceedingly
interesting and instructive. They failed for lack
of the principle of representation, which was practically
unknown to the world until introduced by the Teutonic
colonizers of the Roman empire. Until the idea
of power delegated by the people had become familiar
to men’s minds in its practical bearings, it
was impossible to create a great nation without crushing
out the political life in some of its parts. Some
centre of power was sure to absorb all the political
life, and grow at the expense of the outlying parts,
until the result was a centralized despotism.
Hence it came to be one of the commonplace assumptions
of political writers that republics must be small,
that free government is practicable only in a confined
area, and that the only strong and durable government,
capable of maintaining order throughout a vast territory,
is some form of absolute monarchy.
It was quite natural that people should
formerly have held this opinion, and it is indeed
not yet quite obsolete, but its fallaciousness will
become more and more apparent as American history is
better understood. Our experience has now so
far widened that we can see that despotism is not
the strongest but wellnigh the weakest form of government;
that centralized administrations, like that of the
Roman empire, have fallen to pieces, not because of
too much but because of too little freedom; and that
the only perdurable government must be that which succeeds
in achieving national unity on a grand scale, without
weakening the sense of personal and local independence.
For in the body politic this spirit of freedom is
as the red corpuscles in the blood; it carries the
life with it. It makes the difference between
a society of self-respecting men and women and a society
of puppets.
Your nation may have art, poetry,
and science, all the refinements of civilized life,
all the comforts and safeguards that human ingenuity
can devise; but if it lose this spirit of personal
and local independence, it is doomed and deserves
its doom. As President Cleveland has well said,
it is not the business of a government to support its
people, but of the people to support their government;
and once to lose sight of this vital truth is as dangerous
as to trifle with some stealthy narcotic poison.
Of the two opposite perils which have perpetually
threatened the welfare of political society anarchy
on the one hand, loss of self-government on the other Jefferson
was right in maintaining that the latter is really
the more to be dreaded because its beginnings are
so terribly insidious. Many will understand what
is meant by a threat of secession, where few take
heed of the baneful principle involved in a Texas
Seed-bill.
That the American people are still
fairly alive to the importance of these considerations,
is due to the weary ages of struggle in which our
forefathers have manfully contended for the right of
self-government. From the days of Arminius and
Civilis in the wilds of lower Germany to the
days of Franklin and Jefferson in Independence Hall,
we have been engaged in this struggle, not without
some toughening of our political fibre, not without
some refining of our moral sense. Not among our
English forefathers only, but among all the peoples
of mediaeval and modern Europe has the struggle gone
on, with various and instructive results. In
all parts of romanized Europe invaded and colonized
by Teutonic tribes, self-government attempted to spring
up. What may have been the origin of the idea
of representation we do not know; like most origins,
it seems lost in the prehistoric darkness. Wherever
we find Teutonic tribes settling down over a wide
area, we find them holding their primary assemblies,
usually their annual March-meetings, like those in
which Mr. Hosea Biglow and others like him have figured.
Everywhere, too, we find some attempt at representative
assemblies, based on the principle of the three estates,
clergy, nobles, and commons. But nowhere save
in England does the representative principle become
firmly established, at first in county-meetings, afterward
in a national parliament limiting the powers of the
national monarch as the primary tribal assembly had
limited the powers of the tribal chief. It is
for this reason that we must call the method of nation-making
by means of a representative assembly the English
method. While the idea of representation was
perhaps the common property of the Teutonic tribes,
it was only in England that it was successfully put
into practice and became the dominant political idea.
We may therefore agree with Dr. Stubbs that in its
political development England is the most Teutonic
of all European countries, the country
which in becoming a great nation has most fully preserved
the local independence so characteristic of the ancient
Germans. The reasons for this are complicated,
and to try to assign them all would needlessly encumber
our exposition. But there is one that is apparent
and extremely instructive. There is sometimes
a great advantage in being able to plant political
institutions in a virgin soil, where they run no risk
of being modified or perhaps metamorphosed through
contact with rival institutions. In America the
Teutonic idea has been worked out even more completely
than in Britain; and so far as institutions are concerned,
our English forefathers settled here as in an empty
country. They were not obliged to modify their
political ideas so as to bring them into harmony with
those of the Indians; the disparity in civilization
was so great that the Indians were simply thrust aside,
along with the wolves and buffaloes.
This illustration will help us to
understand the peculiar features of the Teutonic settlement
of Britain. Whether the English invaders really
slew all the romanized Kelts who dwelt in the island,
except those who found refuge in the mountains of
Cumberland, Wales, and Cornwall, or fled across the
channel to Brittany, we need not seek to decide.
It is enough to point out one respect in which the
Teutonic conquest was immeasurably more complete in
Britain than in any other part of the empire.
Everywhere else the tribes who settled upon Roman soil the
Goths, Vandals, Suevi, and Burgundians were
christianized, and so to some extent romanized, before
they came to take possession. Even the more distant
Franks had been converted to Christianity before they
had completed their conquest of Gaul. Everywhere
except in Britain, therefore, the conquerors had already
imbibed Roman ideas, and the authority of Rome was
in a certain sense acknowledged. There was no
break in the continuity of political events. In
Britain, on the other hand, there was a complete break,
so that while on the continent the fifth and sixth
centuries are seen in the full midday light of history,
in Britain they have lapsed into the twilight of half-legendary
tradition. The Saxon and English tribes, coming
from the remote wilds of northern Germany, whither
Roman missionaries had not yet penetrated, still worshipped
Thor and Wodan; and their conquest of Britain was
effected with such deadly thoroughness that Christianity
was destroyed there, or lingered only in sequestered
nooks. A land once christianized thus actually
fell back into paganism, so that the work of converting
it to Christianity had to be done over again.
From the landing of heathen Hengest on the isle of
Thanet to the landing of Augustine and his monks on
the same spot, one hundred and forty-eight years elapsed,
during which English institutions found time to take
deep root in British soil with scarcely more interference,
as to essential points, than in American soil twelve
centuries afterward.
The century and a half between 449
and 597 is therefore one of the most important epochs
in the history of the people that speak the English
language. Before settling in Britain our forefathers
had been tribes in the upper stages of barbarism;
now they began the process of coalescence into a nation
in which the principle of self-government should be
retained and developed. The township and its town-meeting
we find there, as later in New England. The county-meeting
we also find, while the county is a little state in
itself and not a mere administrative district.
And in this county-meeting we may observe a singular
feature, something never seen before in the world,
something destined to work out vaster political results
than Cæsar ever dreamed of. This county-meeting
is not a primary assembly; all the freemen from all
the townships cannot leave their homes and their daily
business to attend it. Nor is it merely an assembly
of notables, attended by the most important men of
the neighbourhood. It is a representative assembly,
attended by select men from each township. We
may see in it the germ of the British parliament and
of the American congress, as indeed of all modern
legislative bodies, for it is a most suggestive commentary
upon what we are saying that in all other countries
which have legislatures, they have been copied, within
quite recent times, from English or American models.
We can seldom if ever fix a date for the beginning
of anything, and we can by no means fix a date for
the beginning of representative assemblies in England.
We can only say that where we first find traces of
county organization, we find traces of representation.
Clearly, if the English conquerors of Britain had left
the framework of Roman institutions standing there,
as it remained standing in Gaul, there would have
been great danger of this principle of representation
not surviving. It would most likely have been
crushed in its callow infancy. The conquerors
would insensibly have fallen into the Roman way of
doing things, as they did in Gaul.
From the start, then, we find the
English nationality growing up under very different
conditions from those which obtained in other parts
of Europe. So far as institutions are concerned,
Teutonism was less modified in England than in the
German fatherland itself, For the gradual conquest
and Christianization of Germany which began with Charles
the Great, and went on until in the thirteenth century
the frontier had advanced eastward to the Vistula,
entailed to a certain extent the romanization of Germany.
For a thousand years after Charles the Great, the
political head of Germany was also the political head
of the Holy Roman Empire, and the civil and criminal
code by which the daily life of the modern German
citizen is regulated is based upon the jurisprudence
of Rome. Nothing, perhaps, could illustrate more
forcibly than this sheer contrast the peculiarly Teutonic
character of English civilization. Between the
eighth and the eleventh centuries, when the formation
of English nationality was approaching completion,
it received a fresh and powerful infusion of Teutonism
in the swarms of heathen Northmen or Danes who occupied
the eastern coasts, struggled long for the supremacy,
and gradually becoming christianized, for a moment
succeeded in seizing the crown. Of the invasion
of partially romanized Northmen from Normandy which
followed soon after, and which has so profoundly affected
English society and English speech, we need notice
here but two conspicuous features. First, it increased
the power of the crown and the clergy, brought all
England more than ever under one law, and strengthened
the feeling of nationality. It thus made England
a formidable military power, while at the same time
it brought her into closer relations with continental
Europe than she had held since the fourth century.
Secondly, by superposing a new feudal nobility as the
upper stratum of society, it transformed the Old-English
thanehood into the finest middle-class of rural gentry
and yeomanry that has ever existed in any country;
a point of especial interest to Americans, since it
was in this stratum of society that the two most powerful
streams of English migration to America the
Virginia stream and the New England stream alike
had their source.
By the thirteenth century the increasing
power and pretensions of the crown, as the unification
of English nationality went on, brought about a result
unlike anything known on the continent of Europe; it
brought about a resistless coalition between the great
nobles, the rural gentry and yeomanry, and the burghers
of the towns, for the purpose of curbing royalty,
arresting the progress of centralization, and setting
up representative government on a truly national scale.
This grand result was partly due to peculiar circumstances
which had their origin in the Norman conquest; but
it was largely due to the political habits generated
by long experience of local representative assemblies, habits
which made it comparatively easy for different classes
of society to find their voice and use it for the
attainment of ends in common. On the continent
of Europe the encroaching sovereign had to contend
with here and there an arrogant vassal, here and there
a high-spirited and rebellious town; in England, in
this first great crisis of popular government, he
found himself confronted by a united people. The
fruits of the grand combination were first,
the wresting of Magna Charta from King John in 1215,
and secondly, the meeting of the first House
of Commons in 1265. Four years of civil war were
required to secure these noble results. The Barons’
War, of the years 1263 to 1267, was an event of the
same order of importance as the Great Rebellion of
the seventeenth century and the American Revolution;
and among the founders of that political freedom which
is enjoyed to-day by all English-speaking people,
the name of Simon de Montfort, Earl of Leicester,
deserves a place in our grateful remembrance beside
the names of Cromwell and Washington. Simon’s
great victory at Lewes in 1264 must rank with Naseby
and Yorktown. The work begun by his House of Commons
was the same work that has continued to go on without
essential interruption down to the days of Cleveland
and Gladstone. The fundamental principle of political
freedom is “no taxation without representation”;
you must not take a farthing of my money without consulting
my wishes as to the use that shall be made of it.
Only when this principle of justice was first practically
recognized, did government begin to divorce itself
from the primitive bestial barbaric system of tyranny
and plunder, and to ally itself with the forces that
in the fulness of time are to bring peace on earth
and good will to men. Of all dates in history,
therefore, there is none more fit to be commemorated
than 1265; for in that year there was first asserted
and applied at Westminster, on a national scale, that
fundamental principle of “no taxation without
representation,” that innermost kernel of the
English Idea, which the Stamp Act Congress defended
at New York exactly five hundred years afterward.
When we think of these dates, by the way, we realize
the import of the saying that in the sight of the Lord
a thousand years are but as a day, and we feel that
the work of the Lord cannot be done by the listless
or the slothful. So much time and so much strife
by sea and land has it taken to secure beyond peradventure
the boon to mankind for which Earl Simon gave up his
noble life on the field of Evesham! Nor without
unremitting watchfulness can we be sure that the day
of peril is yet past. From kings, indeed, we have
no more to fear; they have come to be as spooks and
bogies of the nursery. But the gravest dangers
are those which present themselves in new forms, against
which people’s minds have not yet been fortified
with traditional sentiments and phrases. The
inherited predatory tendency of men to seize upon
the fruits of other people’s labour is still
very strong, and while we have nothing more to fear
from kings, we may yet have trouble enough from commercial
monopolies and favoured industries, marching to the
polls their hordes of bribed retainers. Well indeed
has it been said that eternal vigilance is the price
of liberty. God never meant that in this fair
but treacherous world in which He has placed us we
should earn our salvation without steadfast labour.
[Eternal vigilance is the price of liberty]
To return to Earl Simon, we see that
it was just in that wonderful thirteenth century,
when the Roman idea of government might seem to have
been attaining its richest and most fruitful development,
that the richer and more fruitful English idea first
became incarnate in the political constitution of
a great and rapidly growing nation. It was not
long before the struggle between the Roman Idea and
the English Idea, clothed in various forms, became
the dominating issue in European history. We
have now to observe the rise of modern nationalities,
as new centres of political life, out of the various
provinces of the Roman world. In the course of
this development the Teutonic representative assembly
is at first everywhere discernible, in some form or
other, as in the Spanish Cortes or the States-General
of France, but on the continent it generally dies
out. Only in such nooks as Switzerland and the
Netherlands does it survive. In the great nations
it succumbs before the encroachments of the crown.
The comparatively novel Teutonic idea of power delegated
by the people to their representatives had not become
deeply enough rooted in the political soil of the continent;
and accordingly we find it more and more disused and
at length almost forgotten, while the old and deeply
rooted Roman idea of power delegated by the governing
body to its lieutenants and prefects usurps its place.
Let us observe some of the most striking features of
this growth of modern nationalities.
The reader of medieval history cannot
fail to be impressed with the suddenness with which
the culmination of the Holy Roman Empire, in the thirteenth
century, was followed by a swift decline. The
imperial position of the Hapsburgs was far less splendid
than that of the Hohenstauffen; it rapidly became
more German and less European, until by and by people
began to forget what the empire originally meant.
The change which came over the papacy was even more
remarkable. The grandchildren of the men who
had witnessed the spectacle of a king of France and
a king of England humbled at the feet of Innocent iii.,
the children of the men who had found the gigantic
powers of a Frederick ii. unequal to the task
of curbing the papacy, now beheld the successors of
St. Peter carried away to Avignon, there to be kept
for seventy years under the supervision of the kings
of France. Henceforth the glory of the papacy
in its political aspect was to be but the faint shadow
of that with which it had shone before. This
sudden change in its position showed that the medieval
dream of a world-empire was passing away, and that
new powers were coming uppermost in the shape of modern
nationalities with their national sovereigns.
So long as these nationalities were in the weakness
of their early formation, it was possible for pope
and emperor to assert, and sometimes to come near
maintaining, universal supremacy. But the time
was now at hand when kings could assert their independence
of the pope, while the emperor was fast sinking to
be merely one among kings.
As modern kingdoms thus grew at the
expense of empire and papacy above, so they also grew
at the expense of feudal dukedoms, earldoms, and baronies
below. The fourteenth and fifteenth centuries
were as fatal to feudalism as to world-empire and
world-church. A series of wars occurring at this
time were especially remarkable for the wholesale
slaughter of the feudal nobility, whether on the field
or under the headsman’s axe. This was a
conspicuous feature of the feuds of the Trastamare
in Spain, of the English invasions of France, followed
by the quarrel between Burgundians and Armagnacs,
and of the great war of the Roses in England.
So thorough-going was the butchery in England, for
example, that only twenty-nine lay peers could be found
to sit in the first parliament of Henry vii in
1485. The old nobility was almost annihilated,
both in person and in property; for along with the
slaughter there went wholesale confiscation, and this
added greatly to the disposable wealth of the crown.
The case was essentially similar in France and Spain.
In all three countries the beginning of the sixteenth
century saw the power of the crown increased and increasing.
Its vast accessions of wealth made it more independent
of legislative assemblies, and at the same time enabled
it to make the baronage more subservient in character
by filling up the vacant places with new creations
of its own. Through the turbulent history of
the next two centuries, we see the royal power aiming
at unchecked supremacy and in the principal instances
attaining it except in England. Absolute despotism
was reached first in Spain, under Philip ii.;
in France it was reached a century later, under Louis
xiv.; and at about the same time in the hereditary
estates of Austria; while over all the Italian and
German soil of the disorganized empire, except among
the glaciers of Switzerland and the dykes of the Netherlands,
the play of political forces had set up a host of petty
tyrannies which aped the morals and manners of
the great autocrats at Paris and Madrid and Vienna.
As we look back over this growth of
modern monarchy, we cannot but be struck with the
immense practical difficulty of creating a strong
nationality without sacrificing self-government.
Powerful, indeed, is the tendency toward over-centralization,
toward stagnation, toward political death. Powerful
is the tendency to revert to the Roman, if not to
the Oriental method. As often as we reflect upon
the general state of things at the end of the seventeenth
century the dreadful ignorance and misery
which prevailed among most of the people of continental
Europe, and apparently without hope of remedy so
often must we be impressed anew with the stupendous
significance of the part played by self-governing
England in overcoming dangers which have threatened
the very existence of modern civilization. It
is not too much to say that in the seventeenth century
the entire political future of mankind was staked
upon the questions that were at issue in England.
To keep the sacred flame of liberty alive required
such a rare and wonderful concurrence of conditions
that, had our forefathers then succumbed in the strife,
it is hard to imagine how or where the failure could
have been repaired. Some of these conditions
we have already considered; let us now observe one
of the most important of all. Let us note the
part played by that most tremendous of social forces,
religious sentiment, in its relation to the political
circumstances which we have passed in review.
If we ask why it was that among modern nations absolute
despotism was soonest and most completely established
in Spain, we find it instructive to observe that the
circumstances under which the Spanish monarchy grew
up, during centuries of deadly struggle with the Mussulman,
were such as to enlist the religious sentiment on the
side of despotic methods in church and state.
It becomes interesting, then, to observe by contrast
how it was that in England the dominant religious
sentiment came to be enlisted on the side of political
freedom.
In such an inquiry we have nothing
to do with the truth or falsity of any system of doctrines,
whether Catholic or Protestant. The legitimate
purposes of the historian do not require him to intrude
upon the province of the theologian. Our business
is to trace the sequence of political cause and effect.
Nor shall we get much help from crude sweeping statements
which set forth Catholicism as invariably the enemy
and Protestantism as invariably the ally of human liberty.
The Catholic has a right to be offended at statements
which would involve a Hildebrand or a St. Francis
in the same historical judgment with a Sigismund or
a Torquemada. The character of ecclesiastical
as of all other institutions has varied with the character
of the men who have worked them and the varying needs
of the times and places in which they have been worked;
and our intense feeling of the gratitude we owe to
English Puritanism need in nowise diminish the enthusiasm
with which we praise the glorious work of the mediaeval
church. It is the duty of the historian to learn
how to limit and qualify his words of blame or approval;
for so curiously is human nature compounded of strength
and weakness that the best of human institutions are
likely to be infected with some germs of vice or folly.
Of no human institution is this more
true than of the great medieval church of Gregory
and Innocent when viewed in the light of its claims
to unlimited temporal and spiritual sovereignty.
In striking down the headship of the emperors, it
would have reduced Europe to a sort of Oriental caliphate,
had it not been checked by the rising spirit of nationality
already referred to. But there was another and
even mightier agency coming in to curb its undue pretensions
to absolute sovereignty. That same thirteenth
century which witnessed the culmination of its power
witnessed also the first bold and determined manifestation
of the Protestant temper of revolt against spiritual
despotism. It was long before this that the earliest
Protestant heresy had percolated into Europe, having
its source, like so many other hérésies, in that
eastern world where the stimulating thought of the
Greeks busied itself with the ancient theologies of
Asia. From Armenia in the eighth century came
the Manichaean sect of Paulicians into Thrace, and
for twenty generations played a considerable part
in the history of the Eastern Empire. In the
Bulgarian tongue they were known as Bogomilians, or
men constant in prayer. In Greek they were called
Cathari, or “Puritans.” They accepted
the New Testament, but set little store by the Old;
they laughed at transubstantiation, denied any mystical
efficiency to baptism, frowned upon image-worship
as no better than idolatry, despised the intercession
of saints, and condemned the worship of the Virgin
Mary. As for the symbol of the cross, they scornfully
asked, “If any man slew the son of a king with
a bit of wood, how could this piece of wood be dear
to the king?” Their ecclesiastical government
was in the main presbyterian, and in politics they
showed a decided leaning toward democracy. They
wore long faces, looked askance at frivolous amusements,
and were terribly in earnest. Of the more obscure
pages of mediaeval history, none are fuller of interest
than those in which we decipher the westward progress
of these sturdy heretics through the Balkan peninsula
into Italy, and thence into southern France, where
toward the end of the twelfth century we find their
ideas coming to full blossom in the great Albigensian
heresy. It was no light affair to assault the
church in the days of Innocent iii. The
terrible crusade against the Albigenses, beginning
in 1207, was the joint work of the most powerful of
popes and one of the most powerful of French kings.
On the part of Innocent it was the stamping out of
a revolt that threatened the very existence of the
Catholic hierarchy; on the part of Philip Augustus
it was the suppression of those too independent vassals
the Counts of Toulouse, and the decisive subjection
of the southern provinces to the government at Paris.
Nowhere in European history do we read a more frightful
story than that which tells of the blazing fires which
consumed thousand after thousand of the most intelligent
and thrifty people in France. It was now that
the Holy Inquisition came into existence, and after
forty years of slaughter these Albigensian Cathari
or Puritans seemed exterminated. The practice
of burning heretics, first enacted by statute in Aragon
in 1197, was adopted in most parts of Europe during
the thirteenth century, but in England not until the
beginning of the fifteenth. The Inquisition was
never established in England. Edward ii.
attempted to introduce it in 1311 for the purpose
of suppressing the Templars, but his utter failure
showed that the instinct of self-government was too
strong in the English people to tolerate the entrusting
of so much power over men’s lives to agents
of the papacy. Mediaeval England was ignorant
and bigoted enough, but under a representative government
which so strongly permeated society, it was impossible
to set the machinery of repression to work with such
deadly thoroughness as it worked under the guidance
of Roman methods. When we read the history of
persecution in England, the story in itself is dreadful
enough; but when we compare it with the horrors enacted
in other countries, we arrive at some startling results.
During the two centuries of English persecution, from
Henry IV. to James I., some 400 persons were burned
at the stake, and three-fourths of these cases occurred
in 1555-57, the last three years of Mary Tudor.
Now in a single province of Spain, in the single year
1482, about 2000 persons were burned. The lowest
estimates of the number slain for heresy in the Netherlands
in the course of the sixteenth century place it at
75,000. Very likely such figures are in many cases
grossly exaggerated. But after making due allowance
for this, the contrast is sufficiently impressive.
In England the persecution of heretics was feeble and
spasmodic, and only at one moment rose to anything
like the appalling vigour which ordinarily characterized
it in countries where the Inquisition was firmly established.
Now among the victims of religious persecution must
necessarily be found an unusual proportion of men and
women more independent than the average in their thinking,
and more bold than the average in uttering their thoughts.
The Inquisition was a diabolical winnowing machine
for removing from society the most flexible minds
and the stoutest hearts; and among every people in
which it was established for a length of time it wrought
serious damage to the national character. It
ruined the fair promise of Spain, and inflicted incalculable
detriment upon the fortunes of France. No nation
could afford to deprive itself of such a valuable
element in its political life as was furnished in
the thirteenth century by the intelligent and sturdy
Cathari of southern Gaul.
The spirit of revolt against the hierarchy,
though broken and repressed thus terribly by the measures
of Innocent iii., continued to live on obscurely
in sequestered spots, in the mountains of Savoy, and
Bosnia, and Bohemia, ready on occasion to spring into
fresh and vigorous life. In the following century
Protestant ideas were rapidly germinating in England,
alike in baron’s castle, in yeoman’s farmstead,
in citizen’s shop, in the cloistered walks of
the monastery. Henry Knighton, writing in the
time of Richard ii., declares, with the exaggeration
of impatience, that every second man you met was a
Lollard, or “babbler,” for such was the
nickname given to these free-thinkers, of whom the
most eminent was John Wyclif, professor at Oxford,
and rector of Lutterworth, greatest scholar of the
age.
The career of this man is a striking
commentary upon the difference between England and
continental Europe in the Middle Ages. Wyclif
denied transubstantiation, disapproved of auricular
confession, opposed the payment of Peter’s pence,
taught that kings should not be subject to prelates,
translated the Bible into English and circulated it
among the people, and even denounced the reigning
pope as Antichrist; yet he was not put to death, because
there was as yet no act of parliament for the burning
of heretics, and in England things must be done according
to the laws which the people had made. Pope Gregory
XI. issued five bulls against him, addressed to the
king, the archbishop of Canterbury, and the university
of Oxford; but their dictatorial tone offended the
national feeling, and no heed was paid to them.
Seventeen years after Wyclif’s death, the statute
for burning heretics was passed, and the persecution
of Lollards began. It was feeble and ineffectual,
however. Lollardism was never trampled out in
England as Catharism was trampled out in France.
Tracts of Wyclif and passages from his translation
of the Bible were copied by hand and secretly passed
about to be read on Sundays in the manor-house, or
by the cottage fireside after the day’s toil
was over. The work went on quietly, but not the
less effectively, until when the papal authority was
defied by Henry viii., it soon became apparent
that England was half-Protestant already. It then
appeared also that in this Reformation there were
two forces cooperating, the sentiment of
national independence which would not brook dictation
from Rome, and the Puritan sentiment of revolt against
the hierarchy in general. The first sentiment
had found expression again and again in refusals to
pay tribute to Rome, in defiance of papal bulls, and
in the famous statutes of praemunire, which
made it a criminal offence to acknowledge any authority
in England higher than the crown. The revolt
of Henry viii. was simply the carrying out of
these acts of Edward I. and Edward iii. to their
logical conclusion. It completed the detachment
of England from the Holy Roman Empire, and made her
free of all the world. Its intent was political
rather than religious. Henry, who wrote against
Martin Luther, was far from wishing to make England
a Protestant country. Elizabeth, who differed
from her father in not caring a straw for theology,
was by temperament and policy conservative. Yet
England could not cease to be Papist without ceasing
in some measure to be Catholic; nor could she in that
day carry on war against Spain without becoming a
leading champion of Protestantism. The changes
in creed and ritual wrought by the government during
this period were cautious and skilful; and the resulting
church of England, with its long line of learned and
liberal divines, has played a noble part in history.
But along with this moderate Protestantism
espoused by the English government, as consequent
upon the assertion of English national independence,
there grew up the fierce uncompromising democratic
Protestantism of which the persecuted Lollards had
sown the seeds. This was not the work of government.
By the side of Henry viii. stands
the sublime figure of Hugh Latimer, most dauntless
of preachers, the one man before whose stern rebuke
the headstrong and masterful Tudor monarch quailed.
It was Latimer that renewed the work of Wyclif. and
in his life as well as in his martyrdom, to
use his own words of good cheer uttered while the fagots
were kindling around him, lighted “such
a candle in England as by God’s grace shall
never be put out.” This indomitable man
belonged to that middle-class of self-governing, self-respecting
yeomanry that has been the glory of free England and
free America. He was one of the sturdy race that
overthrew French chivalry at Crecy and twice drove
the soldiery of a tyrant down the slope of Bunker
Hill. In boyhood he worked on his father’s
farm and helped his mother to milk the thirty kine;
he practised archery on the village green, studied
in the village school, went to Cambridge, and became
the foremost preacher of Christendom. Now the
most thorough and radical work of the English Reformation
was done by this class of men of which Latimer was
the type. It was work that was national in its
scope, arousing to fervent heat the strong religious
and moral sentiment of the people, and hence it soon
quite outran the cautious and conservative policy
of the government, and tended to introduce changes
extremely distasteful to those who wished to keep
England as nearly Catholic as was consistent with independence
of the pope. Hence before the end of Elizabeth’s
reign, we find the crown set almost as strongly against
Puritanism as against Romanism. Hence, too, when
under Elizabeth’s successors the great decisive
struggle between despotism and liberty was inaugurated,
we find all the tremendous force of this newly awakened
religious enthusiasm cooperating with the English
love of self-government and carrying it under Cromwell
to victory. From this fortunate alliance of religious
and political forces has come all the noble and fruitful
work of the last two centuries in which men of English
speech have been labouring for the political regeneration
of mankind. But for this alliance of forces,
it is quite possible that the fateful seventeenth
century might have seen despotism triumphant in England
as on the continent of Europe, and the progress of
civilization indefinitely arrested.
In illustration of this possibility,
observe what happened in France at the very time when
the victorious English tendencies were shaping themselves
in the reign of Elizabeth. In France there was
a strong Protestant movement, but it had no such independent
middle-class to support it as that which existed in
England; nor had it been able to profit by such indispensable
preliminary work as that which Wyclif had done; the
horrible slaughter of the Albigenses had deprived France
of the very people who might have played a part in
some way analogous to that of the Lollards. Consequently
the Protestant movement in France failed to become
a national movement. Against the wretched Henry
iii who would have temporized with it, and the
gallant Henry IV who honestly espoused it, the oppressed
peasantry and townsmen made common cause by enlisting
under the banner of the ultra-Catholic Guises.
The mass of the people saw nothing in Protestantism
but an idea favoured by the aristocracy and which
they could not comprehend. Hence the great king
who would have been glad to make France a Protestant
country could only obtain his crown by renouncing
his religion, while seeking to protect it by his memorable
Edict of Nantes. But what a generous despot could
grant, a bigoted despot might revoke; and before another
century had elapsed, the good work done by Henry IV.
was undone by Louis xiv., the Edict of Nantes
was set aside, the process of casting out the most
valuable political element in the community was carried
to completion, and seven percent of the population
of France was driven away and added to the Protestant
populations of northern Germany and England and America.
The gain to these countries and the damage to France
was far greater than the mere figures would imply;
for in determining the character of a community a
hundred selected men and women are more potent than
a thousand men and women taken at random. Thus
while the Reformation in France reinforced to some
extent the noble army of freemen, its triumphs were
not to be the triumphs of Frenchmen, but of the race
which has known how to enlist under its banner the
forces that fight for free thought, free speech, and
self-government, and all that these phrases imply.
In view of these facts we may see
how tremendous was the question at stake with the
Puritans of the seventeenth century. Everywhere
else the Roman idea seemed to have conquered or to
be conquering, while they seemed to be left as the
forlorn hope of the human race. But from the
very day when Oliver Cromwell reached forth his mighty
arm to stop the persécutions in Savoy, the victorious
English idea began to change the face of things.
The next century saw William Pitt allied with Frederick
of Prussia to save the work of the Reformation in central
Europe and set in motion the train of events that
were at last to make the people of the Teutonic fatherland
a nation. At that same moment the keenest minds
in France were awaking to the fact that in their immediate
neighbourhood, separated from them only by a few miles
of salt water, was a country where people were equal
in the eye of the law. It was the ideas of Locke
and Milton, of Vane and Sidney, that, when transplanted
into French soil, produced that violent but salutary
Revolution which has given fresh life to the European
world. And contemporaneously with all this, the
American nation came upon the scene, equipped as no
other nation had ever been, for the task of combining
sovereignty with liberty, indestructible union of
the whole with indestructible life in the parts.
The English idea has thus come to be more than national,
it has become imperial. It has come to rule, and
it has come to stay.
We are now in a position to answer
the question when the Roman Empire came to an end,
in so far as it can be answered at all. It did
not come to its end at the hands of an Odovakar in
the year 476, or of a Mahomet ii in 1453, or
of a Napoleon in 1806. It has been coming to its
end as the Roman idea of nation-making has been at
length decisively overcome by the English idea.
For such a fact it is impossible to assign a date,
because it is not an event but a stage in the endless
procession of events. But we can point to landmarks
on the way. Of movements significant and prophetic
there have been many. The whole course of the
Protestant reformation, from the thirteenth century
to the nineteenth, is coincident with the transfer
of the world’s political centre of gravity from
the Tiber and the Rhine to the Thames and the Mississippi.
The whole career of the men who speak English has within
this period been the most potent agency in this transfer.
In these gigantic processes of evolution we cannot
mark beginnings or endings by years, hardly even by
centuries. But among the significant events which
prophesied the final triumph of the English over the
Roman idea, perhaps the most significant the
one which marks most incisively the dawning of a new
era was the migration of English Puritans
across the Atlantic Ocean, to repeat in a new environment
and on a far grander scale the work which their forefathers
had wrought in Britain. The voyage of the Mayflower
was not in itself the greatest event in this migration;
but it serves to mark the era, and it is only when
we study it in the mood awakened by the general considerations
here set forth that we can properly estimate the historic
importance of the great Puritan Exodus.