1712-1778.
SOCIALISM AND EDUCATION.
Two great political writers in the
eighteenth century, of antagonistic views, but both
original and earnest, have materially affected the
whole science of government, and even of social life,
from their day to ours, and in their influence really
belong to the nineteenth century. One was the
apostle of radicalism; the other of conservatism.
The one, more than any other single man, stimulated,
though unwittingly, the French Revolution; the other
opposed that mad outburst with equal eloquence, and
caused in Europe a reaction from revolutionary principles.
While one is far better known to-day than the other,
to the thoughtful both are exponents and representatives
of conflicting political and social questions which
agitate this age.
These men were Jean Jacques Rousseau
and Edmund Burke, one Swiss, and the other
English. Burke I have already treated of in a
former volume. His name is no longer a power,
but his influence endures in all the grand reforms
of which he was a part, and for which his generation
in England is praised; while his writings remain a
treasure-house of political and moral wisdom, sure
to be drawn upon during every public discussion of
governmental principles. Rousseau, although a
writer of a hundred years ago, seems to me a fit representative
of political, social, and educational ideas in the
present day, because his theories are still potent,
and even in this scientific age more widely diffused
than ever before. Not without reason, it is true,
for he embodied certain germinant ideas in a fascinating
literary style; but it is hard to understand how so
weak a man could have exercised such far-reaching
influence.
Himself a genuine and passionate lover
of Nature; recognizing in his principles of conduct
no duties that could conflict with personal inclinations;
born in democratic and freedom-loving Switzerland,
and early imbued through his reading of German and
English writers with ideas of liberty, which
in those conservative lands were wholesome, he
distilled these ideas into charming literary creations
that were eagerly read by the restless minds of France
and wrought in them political frenzy. The reforms
he projected grew out of his theories of the “rights”
of man, without reference to the duties that limit
those rights; and his appeal for their support to
men’s passions and selfish instincts and to
a sentimental philosophy, in an age of irreligion and
immorality, aroused a political tempest which he little
contemplated.
In an age so infidel and brilliant
as that which preceded the French Revolution, the
writings of Rousseau had a peculiar charm, and produced
a great effect even on men who despised his character
and ignored his mission. He engendered the Robespierres
and Condorcets of the Revolution, those
sentimental murderers, who under the guise of philosophy
attacked the fundamental principles of justice and
destroyed the very rights which they invoked.
Jean Jacques Rousseau was born at
Geneva in the year 1712, when Voltaire was first rising
into notice. He belonged to the plebeian ranks,
being the son of a watchmaker; was sickly, miserable,
and morbid from a child; was poorly educated, but
a great devourer of novels (which his father sentimental
as he read with him), poetry, and gushing
biographies; although a little later he became, with
impartial facility, equally delighted with the sturdy
Plutarch. His nature was passionate and inconstant,
his sensibilities morbidly acute, and his imagination
lively. He hated all rules, precedents, and authority.
He was lazy, listless, deceitful, and had a great
craving for novelties and excitement, as
he himself says, “feeling everything and knowing
nothing.” At an early age, without money
or friends, he ran away from the engraver to whom
he had been apprenticed, and after various adventures
was first kindly received by a Catholic priest in Savoy;
then by a generous and erring woman of wealth lately
converted to Catholicism; and again by the priests
of a Catholic Seminary in Sardinia, under whose tuition,
and in order to advance his personal fortunes, he
abjured the religion in which he had been brought up,
and professed Catholicism. This, however, cost
him no conscientious scruples, for his religious training
had been of the slimmest, and principles he had none.
We next see Rousseau as a footman
in the service of an Italian Countess, where he was
mean enough to accuse a servant girl of a theft he
had himself committed, thereby causing her ruin.
Again, employed as a footman in the service of another
noble family, his extraordinary talents were detected,
and he was made secretary. But all this kindness
he returned with insolence, and again became a wanderer.
In his isolation he sought the protection of the Swiss
lady who had before befriended him, Madame de Warens.
He began as her secretary, and ended in becoming her
lover. In her house he saw society and learned
music.
A fit of caprice induced Rousseau
to throw up this situation, and he then taught music
in Chambéry for a living, studied hard, read Voltaire,
Descartes, Locke, Hobbes, Leibnitz, and Puffendorf,
and evinced an uncommon vivacity and talent for conversation,
which made him a favorite in social circles.
His chief labor, however, for five years was in inventing
a system of musical notation, which led him to Lyons,
and then, in 1741, to Paris.
He was now twenty-nine years old, a
visionary man, full of schemes, with crude opinions
and unbounded self-conceit, but poor and unknown, a
true adventurer, with many agreeable qualities, irregular
habits, and not very scrupulous morals. Favored
by letters of introduction to ladies of distinction, for
he was a favorite with ladies, who liked his enthusiasm,
freshness, elegant talk, and grand sentiments, he
succeeded in getting his system of musical notation
examined, although not accepted, by the French Academy,
and secured an appointment as secretary in the suite
of the Ambassador to Venice.
In this city Rousseau remained but
a short time, being disgusted with what he called
“official insolence,” which did not properly
recognize native genius. He returned to Paris
as poor as when he left it, and lived in a cheap restaurant.
There he made the acquaintance of his Therese, a healthy,
amiable woman, but low, illiterate, unappreciative,
and coarse, the author of many of his subsequent miseries.
She lived with him till he died, at first
as his mistress and housekeeper, although later in
life he married her. She was the mother of his
five children, every one of whom he sent to a foundling
hospital, justifying his inhumanity by those sophistries
and paradoxes with which his writings abound, even
in one of his letters appealing for pity because he
“had never known the sweetness of a father’s
embrace.” With extraordinary self-conceit,
too, he looked upon himself, all the while, in his
numerous illicit loves, as a paragon of virtue, being
apparently without any moral sense or perception of
moral distinctions.
It was not till Rousseau was thirty-nine
years of age that he attracted public attention by
his writings, although earlier known in literary circles, especially
in that infidel Parisian coterie, where Diderot,
Grimm, D’Holbach, D’Alembert, David
Hume, the Marquis de Mirabeau, Helvetius,
and other wits shined, in which circle no genius was
acknowledged and no profundity of thought was deemed
possible unless allied with those pagan ideas which
Saint Augustine had exploded and Pascal had ridiculed.
Even while living among these people, Rousseau had
all the while a kind of sentimental religiosity which
revolted at their ribald scoffing, although he never
protested.
He had written some fugitive pieces
of music, and had attempted and failed in several
slight operettas, composing both music and words; but
the work which made Rousseau famous was his essay on
a subject propounded in 1749 by the Academy of Dijon:
“Has the Progress of Science and the Arts Contributed
to Corrupt or to Purify Morals?” This was a
strange subject for a literary institution to propound,
but one which exactly fitted the genius of Rousseau.
The boldness of his paradox for he maintained
the evil effects of science and art and
the brilliancy of his style secured readers, although
the essay was crude in argument and false in logic.
In his “Confessions” he himself condemns
it as the weakest of all his works, although “full
of force and fire;” and he adds: “With
whatever talent a man may be born, the art of writing
is not easily learned.” It has been said
that Rousseau got the idea of taking the “off
side” of this question from his literary friend
Diderot, and that his unexpected success with it was
the secret of his life-long career of opposition to
all established institutions. This is interesting,
but not very authentic.
The next year, his irregular activity
having been again stimulated by learning that his
essay had gained the premium at Dijon, and by the fact
of its great vogue as a published pamphlet, another
performance fairly raised Rousseau to the pinnacle
of fashion; and this was an opera which he composed,
“Le Devin du Village” (The Village Sorcerer),
which was performed at Fontainebleau before the Court,
and received with unexampled enthusiasm. His
profession, so far as he had any, was that of a copyist
of music, and his musical taste and facile talents
had at last brought him an uncritical recognition.
But Rousseau soon abandoned music
for literature. In 1753 he wrote another essay
for the Academy of Dijon, on the “Origin of the
Inequality of Man,” full of still more startling
paradoxes than his first, in which he attempted to
show, with great felicity of language, the superiority
of savage life over civilization.
At the age of forty-two Rousseau revisited
Protestant Geneva, abjured in its turn the Catholic
faith, and was offered the post of librarian of the
city. But he could not live out of the atmosphere
of Paris; nor did he wish to remain under the shadow
of Voltaire, living in his villa near the City Gate
of Geneva, who had but little admiration for Rousseau,
and whose superior social position excited the latter’s
envy. Yet he professed to hate Paris with its
conventionalities and fashions, and sought a quiet
retreat where he could more leisurely pursue his studies
and enjoy Nature, which he really loved. This
was provided for him by an enthusiastic friend, Madame
d’Epinay, in the beautiful valley
of Montmorenci, and called “The Hermitage,”
situated in the grounds of her Chateau de la Chevrette.
Here he lived with his wife and mother-in-law, he
himself enjoying the hospitalities of the Chateau besides, society
of a most cultivated kind, also woods, lawns, parks,
gardens, all for nothing; the luxuries
of civilization, the glories of Nature, and the delights
of friendship combined. It was an earthly paradise,
given him by enthusiastic admirers of his genius and
conversation.
In this retreat, one of the most favored
which a poor author ever had, Rousseau, ever craving
some outlet for his passionate sentiments, created
an ideal object of love. He wrote imaginary letters,
dwelling with equal rapture on those he wrote and
those he fancied he received in return, and which
he read to his lady friends, after his rambles in
the forests and parks, during their reunions at the
supper-table. Thus was born the “Nouvelle
Heloise,” a novel of immense fame,
in which the characters are invested with every earthly
attraction, living in voluptuous peace, yet giving
vent to those passions which consume the unsatisfied
soul. It was the forerunner of “Corinne,”
“The Sorrows of Werther,” “Thaddeus
of Warsaw,” and all those sentimental romances
which amused our grandfathers and grandmothers, but
which increased the prejudice of religious people
against novels. It was not until Sir Walter Scott
arose with his wholesome manliness that the embargo
against novels was removed.
The life which Rousseau lived at the
Hermitage reveries in the forest, luxurious
dinners, and sentimental friendships led
to a passionate love-affair with the Comtesse
d’Houdetot, a sister-in-law of his patroness
Madame d’Epinay, a woman not only
married, but who had another lover besides. The
result, of course, was miserable, jealousies,
piqués, humiliations, misunderstandings, and the
sundering of the ties of friendship, which led to the
necessity of another retreat: a real home the
wretched man never had. This was furnished, still
in the vicinity of Montmorenci, by another aristocratic
friend, the Marechal de Luxembourg, the fiscal agent
of the Prince de Conde. And nothing to me is
stranger than that this wandering, morbid, irritable
man, without birth or fortune, the father of the wildest
revolutionary and democratic doctrines, and always
hated both by the Court and the Church, should have
found his friends and warmest admirers and patrons
in the highest circles of social life. It can
be explained only by the singular fascination of his
eloquence, and by the extreme stolidity of his worshippers
in appreciating his doctrines, and the state of society
to which his principles logically led.
In this second retreat Rousseau had
the entree to the palace of the Duke of Luxembourg,
where he read to the friends assembled at its banquets
his new production, “Emile,” a
singular treatise on education, not so faulty as his
previous works, but still false in many of its principles,
especially in regard to religion. This book contained
an admirable and powerful impulse away from artificiality
and towards naturalness in education, which has exerted
an immense influence for good; we shall revert to
it later.
A few months before the publication
of “Emile,” Rousseau had issued “The
Social Contract,” the most revolutionary of all
his works, subversive of all precedents in politics,
government, and the organization of society, while
also confounding Christianity with ecclesiasticism
and attacking its influence in the social order.
All his works obtained a wide fame before publication
by reason of his habit of reading them to enthusiastic
and influential friends who made them known.
“The Social Contract,”
however, dangerous as it was, did not when published
arouse so much opposition as “Emile.”
The latter book, as we now see, contained much that
was admirable; but its freedom and looseness in religious
discussion called down the wrath of the clergy, excited
the alarm of the government, and finally compelled
the author to fly for his life to Switzerland.
Rousseau is now regarded as an enemy
to Christian doctrine, even as he was a foe to the
existing institutions of society. In Geneva his
books are publicly burned. Henceforth his life
is embittered by constant persecution. He flies
from canton to canton in the freest country in Europe,
obnoxious not only for his opinions but for his habits
of life. He affectedly adopts the Armenian dress,
with its big fur bonnet and long girdled caftan, among
the Swiss peasantry. He is as full of personal
eccentricities as he is of intellectual crotchets.
He becomes a sort of literary vagabond, with every
man’s hand against him. He now writes a
series of essays, called “Letters from the Mountain,”
full of bitterness and anti-Christian sentiments.
So incensed by these writings are the country people
among whom he dwells that he is again forced to fly.
David Hume, regarding him as a mild,
affectionate, and persecuted man, gives Rousseau a
shelter in England. The wretched man retires to
Derbyshire, and there writes his “Confessions,” the
most interesting and most dangerous of his books,
showing a diseased and irritable mind, and most sophistical
views on the immutable principles of both morality
and religion. A victim of mistrust and jealousy,
he quarrels with Hume, who learns to despise his character,
while pitying the sensitive sufferings of one whom
he calls “a man born without a skin.”
Rousseau returns to France at the
age of fifty-five. After various wanderings he
is permitted to settle in Paris, where he lives with
great frugality in a single room, poorly furnished, supporting
himself by again copying music, sought still in high
society, yet shy, reserved, forlorn, bitter; occasionally
making new friends, who are attracted by the infantine
simplicity of his manners and apparent amiability,
but losing them almost as soon as made by his petty
jealousies and irritability, being “equally
indignant at neglect and intolerant of attention.”
Rousseau’s declining health
and the fear of his friends that he was on the borders
of insanity led to his last retreat, offered by a
munificent friend, at Ermenonville, near Paris, where
he died at sixty-six years of age, in 1778, as some
think from poison administered by his own hand.
The revolutionary National Assembly of France in 1790
bestowed a pension of fifteen hundred francs on his
worthless widow, who had married a stable-boy soon
after the death of her husband.
Such was the checkered life of Rousseau.
As to his character, Lord Brougham says that “never
was so much genius before united with so much weakness.”
The leading spring of his life was egotism. He
never felt himself wrong, and the sophistries he used
to justify his immoralities are both ludicrous and
pitiable. His treatment of Madame de Warens, his
first benefactor, was heartless, while the abandonment
of his children was infamous. He twice changed
his religion without convictions, for the advancement
of his fortunes. He pretended to be poor when
he was independent in his circumstances. He supposed
himself to be without vanity, while he was notoriously
the most conceited man in France. He quarrelled
with all his friends. He made war on society itself.
He declared himself a believer in Christianity, but
denied all revelation, all miracles, all inspiration,
all supernaturalism, and everything he could not reconcile
with his reason. His bitterest enemies were the
atheists themselves, who regarded him as a hypocrite,
since he professed to believe in what he undermined.
The hostility of the Church was excited against him,
not because he directly assailed Christianity, but
because he denied all its declarations and sapped its
authority.
Rousseau was, however, a sentimentalist
rather than a rationalist, an artist rather than a
philosopher. He was not a learned man, but a bold
thinker. He would root out all distinctions in
society, because they could not be reconciled with
his sense of justice. He preached a gospel of
human rights, based not on Christianity but on instinct.
He was full of impracticable theories. He would
have no war, no suffering, no hardship, no bondage,
no fear, and even no labor, since these were evils,
and, according to his notions of moral government,
unnecessary. But in all his grand theories he
ignored the settled laws of Providence, even
those of that “Nature” he so fervently
worshipped, all that is decreed concerning
man or woman, all that is stern and real in existence;
and while he uttered such sophistries, he excited
discontent with the inevitable condition of man, he
loosened family ties, he relaxed wholesome restraints,
he infused an intense hatred of all conditions subject
to necessary toil.
The life of this embittered philanthropist
was as great a contradiction as were his writings.
This benevolent man sends his own children to a foundling
hospital. This independent man lives for years
on the bounty of an erring woman, whom at last he
exposes and deserts. This high-minded idealizer
of friendship quarrels with every man who seeks to
extricate him from the consequences of his own imprudence.
This affectionate lover refuses a seat at his table
to the woman with whom he lives and who is the mother
of his children. This proud republican accepts
a pension from King George III., and lives in the houses
of aristocratic admirers without payment. This
religious teacher rarely goes to church, or respects
the outward observances of the Christianity he affects.
This moral theorizer, on his own confession, steals
and lies and cheats. This modest innocent corrupts
almost every woman who listens to his eloquence.
This lofty thinker consumes his time in frivolity and
senseless quarrels. This patriot makes war on
the institutions of his country and even of civilized
life. This humble man turns his back on every
one who will not do him reverence.
Such was this precursor of revolutions,
this agitator, this hypocrite, this egotist, this
lying prophet, a man admired and despised,
brilliant but indefinite, original but not true, acute
but not wise; logical, but reasoning on false premises;
advancing some great truths, but spoiling their legitimate
effect by sophistries and falsehoods.
Why, then, discuss the ideas and influence
of so despicable a creature? Because, sophistical
as they were, those ideas contained truths of tremendous
germinant power; because in the rank soil of his times
they produced a vast crop of bitter, poisonous fruit,
while in the more open, better aerated soil of this
century they have borne and have yet to bear a fruitage
of universal benefit. God’s ways seem mysterious;
it is for men patiently to study, understand, and
utilize them.
Let us turn to the more definite consideration
of the writings which have given this author so brilliant
a fame. I omit any review of his operas and his
system of musical notation, as not bearing on the
opinions of society.
The first work, as I have said, which
brought Rousseau into notice was the treatise for
the Academy of Dijon, as to whether the arts and sciences
have contributed to corrupt or to purify morals.
Rousseau followed the bent of his genius, in maintaining
that they have done more harm than good; and he was
so fresh and original and brilliant that he gained
the prize. This little work contains the germ
of all his subsequent theories, especially that in
which he magnifies the state of nature over civilization, an
amazing paradox, which, however, appealed to society
when men were wearied with the very pleasures for which
they lived.
Rousseau’s cant about the virtues
engendered by ignorance, idleness, and barbarism is
repulsive to every sound mind, Civilization may present
greater temptations than a state of nature, but these
are inseparable from any growth, and can be overcome
by the valorous mind. Who but a madman would
sweep away civilization with its factitious and remediable
evils for barbarism with its untutored impulses and
animal life? Here Rousseau makes war upon society,
upon all that is glorious in the advance of intellect
and the growth of morality, upon the reason
and aspirations of mankind. Can inexperience
be a better guide than experience, when it encounters
crime and folly? Yet, on the other hand, a plea
for greater simplicity of life, a larger study of Nature,
and a freer enjoyment of its refreshing contrasts
to the hot-house life of cities, is one of the most
reasonable and healthful impulses of our own day.
What can be more absurd, although
bold and striking, than Rousseau’s essay on
the “Origin of Human Inequalities”!
In this he pushes out the doctrine of personal liberty
to its utmost logical sequence, so as to do away with
government itself, and with all regulation for the
common good. We do not quarrel with his abstract
propositions in respect to political equality; but
his deductions strike a blow at civilization, since
he maintains that inequalities of human condition are
the source of all political and social evils, while
Christianity, confirmed by common-sense, teaches that
the source of social evils is in the selfish nature
of man rather than in his outward condition. And
further, if it were possible to destroy the inequalities
of life, they would soon again return, even with the
most boundless liberty. Here common-sense is
sacrificed to a captivating theory, and all the experiences
of the world are ignored.
This shows the folly of projecting
any abstract theory, however true, to its remote and
logical sequence. In the attempt we are almost
certain to be landed in absurdity, so complicated
are the relations of life, especially in governmental
and political science. What doctrine of civil
or political economy would be applicable in all ages
and all countries and all conditions? Like the
ascertained laws of science, or the great and accepted
truths of the Bible, political axioms are to be considered
in their relation with other truths equally accepted,
or men are soon brought into a labyrinth of difficulties,
and the strongest intellect is perplexed.
And especially will this be the case
when a theory under consideration is not a truth but
an assumption. That was the trouble with Rousseau.
His theories, disdainful of experience, however logically
treated, became in their remotest sequence and application
insulting to the human understanding, because they
were often not only assumptions, but assumptions of
what was not true, although very specious and flattering
to certain classes.
Rousseau confounded the great truth
of the justice of moral and political equality with
the absurd and unnatural demand for social and material
equality. The great modern cry for equal opportunity
for all is sound and Christian; but any attempt to
guarantee individual success in using opportunity,
to insure the lame and the lazy an equal rank in the
race, must end in confusion and distraction.
The evil of Rousseau’s crude
theories or false assumptions was practically seen
in the acceptance of their logical conclusions, which
led to anarchy, murder, pillage, and outrageous excess.
The great danger attending his theories is that they
are generally half-truths, truth and falsehood
blended. His writings are sophistical. It
is difficult to separate the truth from the error,
by reason of the marvellous felicity of his language.
I do not underrate his genius or his style. He
was doubtless an original thinker and a most brilliant
and artistic writer; and by so much did he confuse
people, even by the speciousness of his logic.
There is nothing indefinite in what he advances.
He is not a poet dealing in mysticisms, but a rhetorical
philosopher, propounding startling theories, partly
true and partly false, which he logically enforces
with matchless eloquence.
Probably the most influential of Rousseau’s
writings was “The Social Contract,” the
great textbook of the Revolution. In this famous
treatise he advanced some important ideas which undoubtedly
are based on ultimate truth, such as that the people
are the source of power, that might does not make
right, that slavery is an aggression on human rights;
but with these ideal truths he combines the assertion
that government is a contract between the governor
and the governed. In a perfect state of society
this may be the ideal; but society is not and never
has been perfect, and certainly in all the early ages
of the world governments were imposed upon people
by the strong hand, irrespective of their will and
wishes, and these were the only governments
which were fit and useful in that elder day.
Governments, as a plain matter of fact, have generally
arisen from circumstances and relations with which
the people have had little to do. The Oriental
monarchies were the gradual outgrowth of patriarchal
tradition and successful military leadership, and
in regard to them the people were never consulted at
all. The Roman Empire was ruled without the consent
of the governed. Feudal monarchies in Europe
were based on the divine rights of kings. There
was no state in Europe where a compact or social contract
had been made or implied. Even later, when the
French elected Napoleon, they chose a monarch because
they feared anarchy, without making any stipulation.
There were no contracting parties.
The error of Rousseau was in assuming
a social contract as a fact, and then reasoning upon
the assumption. His premises are wrong, or at
least they are nothing more than statements of what
abstractly might be made to follow from the assumption
that the people actually are the source of power, a
condition most desirable and in the last analysis correct,
since even military despots use the power of the people
in order to oppress the people, but which is practically
true only in certain states. Yet, after all,
when brought under the domain of law by the sturdy
sense and utilitarian sagacity of the Anglo-Saxon race,
Rousseau’s doctrine of the sovereignty of the
people is the great political motor of this century,
in republics and monarchies alike.
Again, Rousseau maintains that, whatever
acquisitions an individual or a society may make,
the right to this property must be always subordinate
to the right which the community at large has over
the possessions of all. Here is the germ of much
of our present-day socialism. Whatever element
of truth there may be in the theory that would regard
land and capital, the means of production, as the joint
possession of all the members of the community, the
basic doctrine of socialism, any forcible
attempt to distribute present results of individual
production and accumulation would be unjust and dangerous
to the last degree. In the case of the furious
carrying out of this doctrine by the crazed French
revolutionists, it led to outrageous confiscation,
on the ground that all property belonged to the state,
and therefore the representatives of the nation could
do what they pleased with it. This shallow sophistry
was accepted by the French National Convention when
it swept away estates of nobles and clergy, not on
the tenable ground that the owners were public enemies,
but on the baseless pretext that their property belonged
to the nation.
From this sophistry about the rights
of property, Rousseau advanced another of still worse
tendency, which was that the general will is always
in the right and constantly tends to the public good.
The theory is inconsistent with itself. Light
and truth do not come from the universal reason, but
from the thoughts of great men stimulated into growth
among the people. The teachers of the world belong
to a small class. Society is in need of constant
reforms, which are not suggested by the mass, but
by a few philosophers or reformers, the
wise men who save cities.
Rousseau further says that a whole
people can never become corrupted, a most
barefaced assertion. Have not all nations suffered
periods of corruption? This notion, that the
whole people cannot err, opens the door for any license.
It logically leads to that other idea, of the native
majesty of man and the perfectibility of society, which
this sophist boldly accepted. Rousseau thought
that if society were released from all law and all
restraint, the good impulses and good sense of the
majority would produce a higher state of virtue and
wisdom than what he saw around him, since majorities
could do no wrong and the universal reason could not
err. In this absurdity lay the fundamental principle
of the French Revolution, so far as it was produced
by the writings of philosophers. This doctrine
was eagerly seized upon by the French people, maddened
by generations of oppression, poverty, and degradation,
because it appealed to the pride and vanity of the
masses, at that time congregated bodies of ignorance
and wickedness.
Rousseau had an unbounded trust in
human nature, that it is good and wise,
and will do the best thing if left to itself.
But can anything be more antagonistic to all the history
of the race? I doubt if Rousseau had any profound
knowledge, or even really extensive reading. He
was a dreamer, a theorist, a sentimentalist.
He was the arch-priest of all sensationalism in the
guise of logic. What more acceptable to the vile
people of his age than the theory that in their collective
capacity they could not err, that the universal reason
was divine? What more logical than its culmination
in that outrageous indecency, the worship of Reason
in the person of a prostitute!
Again, Rousseau’s notion of
the limitations of law and the prerogative of the
people, carried out, would lead to the utter subversion
of central authority, and reduce nations to an absolute
democracy of small communities. They would divide
and subdivide until society was resolved into its
original elements. This idea existed among the
early Greek states, when a state rarely comprised
more than a single city or town or village, such as
might be found among the tribes of North American
Indians. The great political question in Ancient
Greece was the autonomy of cities, which kept the
whole land in constant wars and dissensions and quarrels
and jealousies, and prevented that centralization of
power which would have made Greece unconquerable and
the mistress of the world. Our wholesome American
system of autonomy in local affairs, with a common
authority in matters affecting the general good, is
organized liberty. But the ancient and outgrown
idea of unregulated autonomy was revived by Rousseau;
and though it could not be carried out by the French
Revolutionists who accepted nearly all his theories,
it led to the disintegration of France, and the multiplication
of offices fatal to a healthy central power.
Napoleon broke up all this in his centralized despotism,
even if, to keep the Revolutionary sympathy, he retained
the Departments which were substituted for the ancient
Provinces.
The extreme spirit of democratic liberty
which is the characteristic of Rousseau’s political
philosophy led to the advocacy of the wildest doctrines
of equality. He would prevent the accumulation
of wealth, so that, to use his words, “no one
citizen should be rich enough to buy another, and
no one so poor as to be obliged to sell himself.”
He would have neither rich people nor beggars.
What could flow from such doctrines but discontent
and unreasonable expectations among the poor, and
a general fear and sense of insecurity among the rich?
This “state of nature,” moreover, in his
view, could be reached only by going backward and
destroying all civilization, and it was
civilization which he ever decried, a very
pleasant doctrine to vagabonds, but likely to be treated
with derisive mockery by all those who have something
to conserve.
Another and most dangerous principle
which was advocated in the “Social Contract”
was that religion has nothing to do with the affairs
of civil and political life; that religious obligations
do not bind a citizen; that Christianity, in fact,
ignores all the great relations of man in society.
This is distinct from the Puritan doctrine of the separation
of the Church from the State, by which is simply meant
that priests ought not to interfere in matters purely
political, nor the government meddle with religious
affairs, a prime doctrine in a free State.
But no body of men were ever more ardent defenders
of the doctrine that all religious ideas ought to
bear on the social and political fabric than the Puritans,
They would break up slavery, if it derogated from the
doctrine of the common brotherhood of man as declared
by Christ; they would use their influence as Christians
to root out all evil institutions and laws, and bring
the sublime truths of the Master to bear on all the
relations of life, on citizens at the ballot-box,
at the helm of power, and in legislative bodies.
Christianity was to them the supreme law, with which
all human laws must harmonize. But Rousseau would
throw out Christianity altogether, as foreign to the
duties and relations of both citizens and rulers,
pretending that it ignored all connection with mundane
affairs and had reference only to the salvation of
the soul, as if all Christ’s teachings
were not regulative of the springs of conduct between
man and man, as indicative of the relations between
man and God! Like Voltaire, Rousseau had the excuse
of a corrupt ecclesiasticism to be broken into; but
the Church and Christianity are two different things.
This he did not see. No one was more impatient
of all restraints than Rousseau; yet he maintained
that men, if calling themselves Christians, must submit
to every wrong and injustice, looking for a remedy
in the future world, thus pouring contempt
on those who had no right, according to his view of
their system, to complain of injustice or strive to
rise above temporal evils. Christianity, he said,
inculcates servitude and dependence; its spirit is
favorable to tyrants; true Christians are formed to
be slaves, and they know it, and never trouble themselves
about conspiracies and insurrections, since this transitory
world has no value in their eyes. He denied that
Christians could be good soldiers, a falsehood
rebuked for us by the wars of the Reformation, by
the troops of Cromwell and Gustavus Adolphus, by our
American soldiers in the late Civil War. Thus
he would throw away the greatest stimulus to heroism, even
the consciousness of duty, and devotion to great truths
and interests.
I cannot follow out the political
ideas of Rousseau in his various other treatises,
in which he prepared the way for revolution and for
the excesses of the Reign of Terror. The truth
is, Rousseau’s feelings were vastly superior
to his thinking. Whatever of good is to result
from his influence will arise out of the impulse he
gave toward the search for ideals that should embrace
the many as well as the few in their benefits; when
he himself attempted to apply this impulse to philosophic
political thought, his unregulated mind went all astray.
Let us now turn to consider a moment
his doctrines pertaining to education, as brought
out in his greatest and most unexceptionable work,
his “Emile.”
In this remarkable book everything
pertaining to human life appears to be discussed.
The duties of parents, child-management, punishments,
perception and the beginning of thinking; toys, games,
catechisms, all passions and sentiments, religion,
friendship, love, jealousy, pity; the means of happiness,
the pleasures and profits of travel, the principles
of virtue, of justice and liberty; language, books;
the nature of man and of woman, the arts of conventional
life, politeness, riches, poverty, society, marriage, on
all these and other questions he discourses with great
sagacity and good sense, and with unrivalled beauty
of expression, often rising to great eloquence, never
dull or uninstructive, aiming to present virtue and
vice in their true colors, inspiring exalted sentiments,
and presenting happiness in simple pleasures and natural
life.
This treatise is both full and original.
The author supposes an imaginary pupil, named Emile,
and he himself, intrusted with the care of the boy’s
education, attends him from his cradle to his manhood,
assists him with the necessary directions for his
general improvement, and finally introduces him to
an amiable and unsophisticated girl, whose love he
wins by his virtues and whom he honorably marries;
so that, although a treatise, the work is invested
with the fascination of a novel.
In reading this book, which made so
great a noise in Europe, with so much that is admirable
I find but little to criticise, except three things,
which mar its beauty and make it both dangerous and
false, in which the unsoundness of Rousseau’s
mind and character the strange paradoxes
of his life in mixing up good with evil are
brought out, and that so forcibly that the author
was hunted and persecuted from one part of Europe
to another on account of it.
The first is that he makes all natural
impulses generous and virtuous, and man, therefore,
naturally good instead of perverse, thus
throwing not only Christianity but experience entirely
aside, and laying down maxims which, logically carried
out, would make society perfect if only Nature were
always consulted. This doctrine indirectly makes
all the treasures of human experience useless, and
untutored impulse the guide of life. It would
break the restraints which civilization and a knowledge
of life impose, and reduce man to a primitive state.
In the advocacy of this subtle falsehood, Rousseau
pours contempt on all the teachings of mankind, on
all schools and colleges, on all conventionalities
and social laws, yea, on learning itself. He always
stigmatizes scholars as pedants.
Secondly, he would reduce woman to
insignificance, having her rule by arts and small
devices; making her the inferior of man, on whom she
is dependent and to whose caprice she is bound to
submit, a sort of toy or slave, engrossed
only with domestic duties, like the woman of antiquity.
He would give new rights and liberties to man, but
none to woman as man’s equal, thus
keeping her in a dependence utterly irreconcilable
with the bold freedom which he otherwise advocates.
The dangerous tendency of his writings is somewhat
checked, however, by the everlasting hostility with
which women of character and force of will such
as they call “strong-minded” will
ever pursue him. He will be no oracle to them.
But a still more marked defect weakens
“Emile” as one of the guide-books of the
world, great as are its varied excellencies. The
author undermines all faith in Christianity as a revelation,
or as a means of man’s communion with the Divine,
for guidance, consolation, or inspiration. Nor
does he support one of his moral or religious doctrines
by an appeal to the Sacred Scriptures, which have been
so deep a well of moral and spiritual wisdom for so
many races of men. Practically, he is infidel
and pagan, although he professes to admire some of
the moral truths which he never applies to his system.
He is a pure Theist or Deist, recognizing, like the
old Greeks, no religion but that of Nature, and valuing
no attainments but such as are suggested by Nature
and Reason, which are the gods he worships from first
to last in all his writings. The Confession of
Faith by the Savoyard Vicar introduced into the fourth
of the six “Books” of this work, which,
having nothing to do with his main object, he unnecessarily
drags in, is an artful and specious onslaught on all
doctrines and facts revealed in the Bible, on
all miracles, all prophecies, and all supernatural
revelation, thus attacking Christianity
in its most vital points, and making it of no more
authority than Buddhism or Mohammedanism. Faith
is utterly extinguished. A cold reason is all
that he would leave to man, no consolation
but what the mind can arrive at unaided, no knowledge
but what can be reached by original scientific investigation.
He destroys not only all faith but all authority,
by a low appeal to prejudices, and by vulgar wit such
as the infidels of a former age used in their heartless
and flippant controversies. I am not surprised
at the hostility displayed even in France against
him by both Catholics and Protestants. When he
advocated his rights of man, from which Thomas Paine
and Jefferson himself drew their maxims, he appealed
to the self-love of the great mass of men ground down
by feudal injustices and inequalities, to
the sense of justice, sophistically it is true, but
in a way which commanded the respect of the intellect.
When he assailed Christianity in its innermost fortresses,
while professing to be a Christian, he incurred the
indignation of all Christians and the contempt of
all infidels, for he added hypocrisy to
scepticism, which they did not. Diderot, D’Alembert,
and others were bold unbelievers, and did not veil
their hostilities under a weak disguise. I have
never read a writer who in spirit was more essentially
pagan than Rousseau, or who wrote maxims more entirely
antagonistic to Christianity.
Aside from these great falsities, the
perfection of natural impulse, the inferiority of
woman, and the worthlessness of Christianity, as
inculcated in this book, “Emile” must certainly
be ranked among the great classics of educational
literature. With these expurgated it confirms
the admirable methods inspired by its unmethodical
suggestions. Noting the oppressiveness of the
usual order of education through books and apparatus,
he scorns all tradition, and cries, “Let the
child learn direct from Nature!” Himself sensitive
and humane, having suffered as a child from the tyranny
of adults, he demands the tenderest care and sympathy
for children, a patient study of their characteristics,
a gentle, progressive leading of them to discover
for themselves rather than a cramming of them with
facts. The first moral education should be negative, no
preaching of virtue and truth, but shielding from vice
and error. He says: “Take the very
reverse of the current practice, and you will almost
always do right.” This spirit, indeed, is
the key to his entire plan. His ideas were those
of the nineteenth, not the eighteenth century.
Free play to childish vitality; punishment the natural
inconvenience consequent on wrong-doing; the incitement
of the desire to learn; the training of sense-activity
rather than reflection, in early years; the acquirement
of the power to learn rather than the acquisition
of learning, in short, the natural and scientifically
progressive rather than the bookish and analytically
literary method was the end and aim of “Emile.”
Actually, this book accomplished little
in its own time, chiefly because of its attack on
established religion. Influentially, it reappeared
in Pestalozzi, the first practical reformer of methods;
in Froebel, the inventor of the Kindergarten; in Spencer,
the great systematizer of the philosophy of development;
and through these its spirit pervades the whole world
of education at the present time.
In Rousseau’s “New Heloise”
there are the same contradictions, the same paradoxes,
the same unsoundness as in his other works, but it
is more eloquent than any. It is a novel in which
he paints all the aspirations of the soul, all its
unrest, all its indefinite longings, its raptures,
and its despair; in which he unfetters the imagination
and sanctifies every impulse, not only of affection,
but of passion. This novel was the pioneer of
the sentimental romances which rapidly followed in
France and England and Germany, worse than
our sensational literature, since the author veiled
his immoralities by painting the transports of passion
under the guise of love, which ever has its seat in
the affections and is sustained only by respect.
Here Rousseau was a disguised seducer, a poisoner
of the moral sentiments, a foe to what is most sacred;
and he was the more dangerous from his irresistible
eloquence. His sophistries in regard to political
and social rights may be met by reason, but not his
attacks on the heart, with his imaginary sorrows and
joys, his painting of raptures which can never be
found. Here he undermines virtue as he had undermined
truth and law. Here reprobation must become unqualified,
and he appears one of the very worst men who ever exercised
a commanding influence on a wicked and perverse generation.
And this view of the man is rather
confirmed by his own “Confessions,” a
singularly attractive book, yet from which, after the
perusal of the long catalogue of his sorrows, joys,
humiliations, triumphs, ecstasies and miseries, glories
and shame, one rises with great disappointment, since
no great truths, useful lessons, or even ennobling
sentiments are impressed upon the mind to make us wiser
or better. The “Confessions” are
only a revelation of that sensibility, excessive and
morbid, which reminds us of Byron and his misanthropic
poetry, showing a man defiant, proud, vain,
unreasonable, unsatisfied, supremely worldly and egotistic.
The first six Books are mere annals of sentimental
debauchery; the last six, a kind of thermometer of
friendship, containing an accurate account of kisses
given and received, with slights, huffs, visits, quarrels,
suspicions, and jealousies, interspersed with grand
sentiments and profound views of life and human nature,
yet all illustrative of the utter vanity of earth,
and the failure of all mortal pleasures to satisfy
the cravings of an immortal mind. The “Confessions”
remind us of “Manfred” and “Ecclesiastes”
blended, exceedingly readable, and often
unexceptionable, where virtue is commended and vice
portrayed in its true light, but on the whole a book
which no unsophisticated or inexperienced person can
read without the consciousness of receiving a moral
taint; a book in no respect leading to repose or lofty
contemplation, or to submission to the evils of life,
which it catalogues with amazing detail; a book not
even conducive to innocent entertainment. It
is the revelation of the inner life of a sensualist,
an egotist, and a hypocrite, with a maudlin although
genuine admiration for Nature and virtue and friendship
and love. And the book reveals one of the most
miserable and dissatisfied men that ever walked the
earth, seeking peace in solitude and virtue, while
yielding to unrestrained impulses; a man of morbid
sensibility, ever yearning for happiness and pursuing
it by impossible and impracticable paths. No sadder
autobiography has ever been written. It is a lame
and impotent attempt at self-justification, revealing
on every page the writer’s distrust of the virtues
which he exalts, and of man whose reason and majesty
he deifies, even of the friendships in
which he sought consolation, and of the retirements
where he hoped for rest.
The book reveals the man. The
writer has no hope or repose or faith. Nothing
pleases him long, and he is driven by his wild and
undisciplined nature from one retreat to another,
by persecution more fancied than real, until he dies,
not without suspicion of having taken his own life.
Such was Rousseau: the greatest
literary genius of his age, the apostle of the reforms
which were attempted in the French Revolution, and
of ideas which still have a wondrous power, some
of which are grand and true, but more of which are
sophistical, false, and dangerous. His theories
are all plausible; and all are enforced with matchless
eloquence of style, but not with eloquence of thought
or true feeling, like the soaring flights of Pascal, in
every respect his superior in genius, because more
profound and lofty. Rousseau’s writings,
like his life, are one vast contradiction, the blending
of truth with error, the truth valuable
even when commonplace, the error subtle and dangerous, so
that his general influence must be considered bad
wherever man is weak or credulous or inexperienced
or perverse. I wish I could speak better of a
man whom so many honestly admire, and whose influence
has been so marked during the last hundred years, and
will be equally great for a hundred years to come;
a man from whom Madame de Stael, Jefferson, and Lamartine
drew so much of their inspiration, whose ideas about
childhood have so helpfully transformed the educational
methods of our own time. But I must speak my honest
conviction, from the light I have, at the same time
hoping that fuller light may justify more leniency
to one of the great oracles whose doctrines are still
cherished by many of the guides of modern thought.