Sec 1
The Massacre of Colleagues
The existence of war in the modern
world is primarily a question for the moral philosopher.
It may be of interest to the anthropologist to consider
war as a gallant survival with an impressive ritual
and a code of honour curiously detached from the social
environment, like the Hindu suttee; or with a procedure
euphemistically disguised, like some chthonic liturgy
of ancient Athens. But it is a problem too broad
for the anthropologist when we consider that we have
reached a stage of civilisation which regards murder
as the most detestable of crimes and deprives the
murderer of all civil rights and often even of the
natural right to live: while in the same community
the organised massacre of our colleagues in civilisation
is not only tolerated but assumed to be necessary
by the principal expositors of law and religion, is
the scientific occupation of the most honoured profession
in the State, and constitutes the real sanction of
all international intercourse.
Sec 2
The Widening Sphere of Morality
The existence of war stimulates the
astonished watcher in the tower of ivory to examine
the development, if any, of human morality; and to
formulate some law of the process whereby political
man has been differentiated from the savage.
Morality being a relation between
two or more contracting parties, he will notice that
the history of mankind is marked by a consistent tendency
to extend this relation, to include in the system of
relationships more numerous and more distant objects,
so that the moral agent is surrounded by a continually
widening sphere of obligations.
This system of relationship, which
may be called the moral sphere, has grown up under
a variety of influences, expediency, custom, religious
emotion and political action; but the moral agents
included in it at any given time are always bound
to each other by a theoretical contract involving
both rights and duties, and leading each to expect
and to apply in all his dealings with the others a
certain standard of conduct which is approximately
fixed by the enlightened opinion of the majority for
the benefit of the totality.
The moral sphere then is a contractual
unit of two or more persons who agree to moderate
their individual conduct for their common good:
and the State itself is only a stage in the growth
of this moral unit from its emergence out of primitive
savagery to its superannuation in ultimate anarchy,
commonly called the Millennium. The State indeed
is a moral sphere, a moral unit, which has long been
outgrown by enlightened opinion; and the trouble is
that we are now in a transition stage in which the
boundaries of the State survive as a limitation instead
of setting an ideal of moral conduct.
Sec 3
The Receding God
I don’t know that it is necessary
to drag God into the argument. But if you like
to regard God as the sanction and source of morality,
or if you like to call the moral drift in human affairs
God, it is possible to consider this “Sphere
of Morality” from His point of view. His
“point of view” is precisely what, in
an instructive fable, we may present as the determining
factor in morality. When He walked in the garden
or lurked hardly distinguishable among the sticks
and stones of the forest, morality was just an understanding
between a man and his neighbour, a temporary agreement
entered on by any two hunting savages whom He might
happen to espy between the tree-trunks. When He
dwelt among the peaks of Sinai or Olympus, the sphere
of morality had extended to the whole tribe that occupied
the subjacent valley. It came to include the nation,
all the subjects of each sovereign state, by the time
He had receded to some heavenly throne above the dark
blue sky. And it is to be hoped that He may yet
take a broader view, so that His survey will embrace
the whole of mankind, if only we can banish Him to
a remoter altitude in the frozen depths of space,
whence He can contemplate human affairs without being
near enough to interfere.
The moral of this little myth of the
Receding God may be that the Sphere of Morality is
extended in inverse proportion to the intensity of
theological interference. Not that theology necessarily
or always deliberately limits the domain of morality:
but because the extension of moral relations and the
relegation of anthropomorphic theology are co-ordinate
steps in human advancement.
Sec 4
The Philosopher looks at Society
The philosopher is apt to explain
the growth and interrelation of ideas by tabulating
them in an historical form, which may not be narrowly,
chronologically, or “historically” true.
The notion of the Social Contract may be philosophically
true, though we are not to imagine the citizens of
Rousseau’s State coming together on a certain
day to vote by show of hands, like the members of
the Bognor Urban District Council. So we may
illustrate a theory of moral or social evolution by
a sort of historical pageant, which will not be journalistically
exact, but will give a true picture of an ideal development,
every scene of which can be paralleled by some actually
known or inferred form of human life.
Sec 5
Homo Homini Lupus
Our imagination, working subconsciously
on a number of laboriously accumulated hints, a roomful
of chipped or polished stones, the sifted debris of
Swiss palafittes, a few pithecoid jawbones, some painted
rocks from Salamanca, produces a fairly definite picture
of the earliest essentially human being on earth:
and we recognise a man not unlike one of ourselves;
with a similar industry interrupted from time to time
by the arbitrary stirrings of a similar artistic impulse;
so close to us indeed that some of his habits still
survive among us. Some of us at least have made
a recreation of his necessity, and still go hunting
wild or hypothetically wild animals for food.
But when this primeval hunter emerged from his lair
in the forest or his valley-cave, he was prepared
to attack at sight any man he happened to meet:
and he thought himself a fine fellow if he succeeded
in cracking the skull of a possible rival in love
or venery. This was the age of preventive aggression
with a vengeance. We still feel a certain satisfaction
in a prompt and crushing blow, and in the simplicity
of violence. But we no longer attack our neighbour
in the street, as dogs fight over a bone or over nothing
at all: though some of us reserve the right to
snarl.
Sec 6
Tribe against Tribe
But this fighter’s paradise
was too exciting to last long; and indeed it is hard
to visualise steadily the feral solitary man who lived
without any social organisation at all. Consideration
like an angel came and did not indeed drive the offending
devil out of him but taught him to guide it into more
profitable channels, by co-operating with his neighbour.
When a man first made peace with the hunter in the
next cave in order to go out with him against the
bear at the head of the valley, or even to have his
assistance in carrying off a couple of women from
the family down by the lake, on that day the social
and moral unit was constituted, the sphere of morality,
destined, who knows how soon, to include the whole
of mankind in one beneficent alliance, began with what
Professor McDougal has called “the replacement
of individual by collective pugnacity.”
The first clear stage in this progress is the tribe
or clan, the smallest organised community, sometimes
no larger than the self-contained village or camp,
which can still be found in the wild parts of the
earth. Tribe against tribe is the formula of this
order of civilisation. Within the limits of the
community man inhibits his natural impulses and settles
his personal disputes according to the rules laid
down by the headman or chief. But once outside
the stockade he can kill and plunder at will, though
owing to the similarly strong organisation of the
next village he will usually reserve his predatory
exploits for the official and collective raids of village
against village and tribe against tribe.
Of course the family is a step leading
up to the tribal stage of morality, and it may be
that the idea of incest marks the social stage in
which the moral sphere was conterminous with the family,
corresponding to the institution of exogamy in the
moral system of the tribe.
It may be added that even in the modern
family the feeling which unites the members often
consists less, very much less, of affection than of
a sort of obligation to hang together for mutual defence.
Sec 7
The City State
The City State, self-contained, self-supporting,
truly democratic, is marked by a similar pugnacity.
Only full citizenship conferred full moral rights,
and any ferocity could be justified in war against
another city. Athens wore herself out in the
long struggle with Sparta, and Greece was lured to
destruction by the devil of Imperialism, whose stock
argument is to suggest that a State can extend its
rights without extending its obligations. But
the limitation of the moral sphere by the boundaries
of the city is less apparent in the Greek States, because
in the historical period at least they were already
in transition to a larger view, and enlightened opinion
certainly believed in a moral system which should
include all Greek States, to the exclusion of course
of all “barbarians”: but this larger
view was even more definitely limited, and the demarcation
of those within from those outside the moral sphere
was never more sharply conceived, than in the difference
commonly held to exist between Greeks and Barbarians.
Yet even so Greece can maintain her pre-eminence in
thought; for Plato and Euripides at least glimpsed
the conception, by which we do not yet consent to be
guided, of the moral equality of all mankind.
For all these reasons the City State
as a limited moral sphere is better seen perhaps in
Mediaeval Italy, where, I imagine, a Florentine might
kill a native of Pisa whenever he liked; whereas if
he killed a fellow Florentine he risked at least the
necessity of putting himself outside the moral sphere,
of having that is to leave Florence and stay in Pisa
till the incident was forgotten.
Sec 8
The Nations of Europe ferae naturae
In the next and latest stage in the
expansion of the moral system we find it again conterminous
with the frontiers of the State. But it is now
no longer the small city state of Ancient Greece and
Mediaeval Italy, but the large political unit, roughly
and hypothetically national, which constitutes
the modern State, whether Kingdom, Republic, or Empire.
I have called this the latest stage in the extension
of the sphere of morality because it is the one which
actually prevails and limits our national conduct.
For the paradox of legal murder and massacre in the
modern world is resolved as soon as we realise that
war is a conflict between two or more isolated moral
systems, each of which only regards violence as a
crime to be suppressed within the limits of its own
validity. International warfare in its crudest
form is only a manifestation of the original wolfish
state of man, the “state of nature” which
exists between two moral agents who have no moral
obligation to each other (but only to themselves).
The fact that the primitive savage was an individual
moral agent having no moral obligation to anyone but
himself, while the modern fighting nation is a moral
agent of who knows how many millions, does not alter
the essential character of the conflict.
Sec 9
The Convenience of Diplomacy
As a matter of fact this original
wolfish attitude of nations is already obsolete, if
it ever existed. The expansion and growth of political
and moral relations is a gradual process, and the
fact that for the sake of brevity and clearness we
fix and describe certain arbitrary points in that
process must not be taken to imply that it is discontinuous.
Anyhow there is no doubt that the specifically wolfish
attitude of one nation to another can hardly be found
in its pure state, being already tempered and mitigated
by the practice and custom of diplomacy: and this
diplomatic mitigation, however superficial, does something
to break down that windowless isolation which is the
essential cause of violence between two independent
moral entities. Pacificists of the democratic
school sometimes present a fallacious view of international
diplomacy, and almost imply that the present war was
made inevitable by the fact that Viscount Grey was
educated at Harrow, or that peace could have been
preserved with Germany if only Sir Edward Goschen had
begun life as a coal heaver, or had at least been
elected by the National Union of Boilermakers.
Their panacea they vaguely call the democratic control
of Foreign Affairs, though it is not clear why we
should expect twenty million still ignorant voters
to be more enlightened than one educated representative
who is, as a matter of fact, usually so much oppressed
by a due sense of his responsibility that he is in
danger of bungling only from excessive timidity.
The experience of the Law Courts shows that twelve
men, be they never so good and true, cannot at present
be trusted to weigh and discriminate as nicely as
one; and the fact that the Daily Mail has
the largest circulation of any morning paper is a
sufficient mark of the present capacity and inclination
of the majority to control public affairs more directly
than they do. It is said that the secrecy of
diplomatic affairs breeds an atmosphere of suspicion;
and it might be said with equal truth that all secrecy
of every kind is always and everywhere the most unnecessary
thing in the world. But the fundamental fallacy
of all these arguments is that they treat diplomacy
as an essential of international relations, whereas
it is only an accident, a trapping, a convenience,
or a common form. Its defects are the result
and the reflection of national opinion. Diplomatists
are no more responsible for the defects of international
relationship than seconds are responsible for the
practice of duelling: and we may note incidentally
that duels are if anything more frequent when the place
of the seconds in estimating their necessity is taken
by a democratic court of honour.
Sec 10
A Note on Democracy
The outcry for “democratic”
control demands, I think, a note, if not a volume,
on the limitations of democracy. We are all, I
suppose, agreed nowadays that the government of the
future must be democratic, in the sense that every
adult has a right to full citizenship, and every
citizen can claim a vote. But it is obviously
impossible for a modern State to be governed directly
by the voices of say fifty or a hundred million citizens:
there must always be a small legislative and a still
smaller executive body; and these bodies should obviously
be composed of the finest and most capable citizens.
If then Aristocracy means, as it does mean, a government
of the whole by the best elements, it follows that
we are all equally agreed that the government of the
future must be aristocratic. The solution of
this antinomy is of course that democracy is not an
end in itself, but only a means for the selection and
sanction of aristocracy. The best elements in the
population can only come to the top if every man has
an opportunity of using his voice and his intelligence.
We may note in passing that a common objection, raised
by writers like Emile Faguet, to the effect that democracy
puts a premium on incompetence by choosing its officials
almost fortuitously from the mob, is the exact opposite
of the truth. It is our present regime that leaves
the selection of our rulers to the chances of birth
or wealth or forensic success. Real democracy
will stimulate the selection of the best, just as
trade union standardisation of wages encourages the
employment of the better workmen.
Sec 11
Diplomacy not bad in itself
The real importance of diplomacy,
as I have said, is in the fact that it is a mitigation
of primary ferocity, a symptom of readiness to negotiate,
a recognition of the fact that disputes need not be
settled by immediate violence: and as such it
points to a time when war may be superseded, as personal
combat has been superseded by litigation. The
man who puts a quarrel with his neighbour into the
hands of a legal representative is a stage higher
in social civilisation than the man who fights it
out at sight. Diplomats are the legal representatives
of nations only there is no supernational
court before which they can state their case.
Of course, it is perfectly true that
the ultimate sanction of diplomacy is always force,
that international negotiations may always be resolved
into a series of polite threats, and that the envoy
of the small and weak nation rarely has any influence.
Indeed there are few less enviable situations than
that of the minister of a very small State at the court
of a very large one. But the mere fact that force
is their sanction does not ipso facto dispose
of diplomatic and arbitrational methods. We all
know that the force at the disposal of the Sovereign
is the ultimate sanction of Law. But that force
never has to be fully exerted because there is a common
consent to respect the Law and its officers.
Sec 12
Manners no Substitute for Morals
The real difference between legal
methods and the methods of diplomacy (in which I here
include international conversations of every sort)
is that the latter take place, as it were, in a vacuum.
There is no Sovereign, no common denominator, no unifying
system in which both parties are related by their
common obligations. They exist and act in two
separate moral spheres, and no real intercourse is
possible between them. For all their ambassadors
and diplomatic conferences the nations of Europe are
only wolves with good manners. And manners, as
we all know, are no substitute for morals.
Sec 13
War a Moral Anachronism
Thus we come back to our thesis that
war is not only possible but inevitable so long as
the extent of the moral sphere is conterminous with
the frontiers of the State. But merely to explain
laboriously that all this organised killing is not
really a paradox but the natural accompaniment of
a certain stage of moral development, and to leave
it at that, would be rather to exaggerate our philosophic
detachment. The point is that we are long past
the stage of regarding any but our fellow-subjects
as moral outlaws. For some years, to say the least,
it has been generally received that the sphere of
morality is co-extensive with mankind. In spite
of certain lingering exceptions, it is to-day a commonplace
of thought that every human being on the earth is our
colleague in civilisation; is a member that is of the
human race, which finding itself on this earth has
got somehow to make the best of it; is a shareholder
in the human asset of self-consciousness which we are
called upon to exploit. It would certainly be
hard to find a man of what we have called enlightened
opinions who would not profess, whatever his private
feelings, that it is as great a crime to kill a Hottentot
or a Jew as to kill an Englishman. With certain
lingering exceptions then we already regard the foreigner
as a member of our own moral system. The moral
sphere has already extended or is at least in course
of extension to its ultimate limits: and war
is a survival from the penultimate stage of morality.
War, to put it mildly, is a moral anachronism.
War between European nations is civil war. Logically
all war should be recognised at once, at any rate
by enlightened opinion, as the crime, the disaster,
the ultimate disgrace that it obviously is. Why
then do we cling to the implications of a system that
we have grown out of? Why do we affect the limitation
of boundaries that have been already extended?
Or is our prison so lovely that though the walls fall
down we refuse to walk out into the air?