Nunquamne
reponam,
Vexatus toties rauci Theseide Codri?
Historians are only too fond of insisting
on the effect of the French Revolution in checking
English reform. One of the latest of them dwells
on the fatal influence of this great event in our own
country, in checking, blighting, and distorting the
natural progress of things. But for that influence,
he says, the closing years of the century would probably
have seen the abolition of the English Slave Trade,
the reform of Parliament, and the repeal of the Test
Act. The question of the precise degree of vitality
in sectarian pride, and of tenacity in a great material
interest, a hundred years ago or at any time, is not
very easy to settle. It is quite possible that
the Slave Trade and the Test Act might have died nearly
as hard, if there had been no French Revolution.
In any case, it is a curious implication that underlies
all writing in this familiar vein, that France ought
to have gone on with a bad government, in order to
secure to England the advantages of a good one.
As to one disservice, however, there
can be no doubt. The French Revolution has furnished
the enemies of each successive proposal of reform
with a boundless supply of prejudicial analogies, appalling
parallels, and ugly nicknames, which are all just as
conclusive with the unwise as if they were the aptest
arguments. Sydney Smith might well put “the
awful example of a neighbouring nation” among
the standing topics of the Noodle’s Oration.
The abolition of rotten boroughs brought down a thousand
ominous references to noyades, fusillades, and
guillotines. When Sir Robert Peel took the duty
off corn, Croker warned him with great solemnity that
he was breaking up the old interests, dividing the
great families, and beginning exactly such a castastrophe
as did the Noailles and the Montmorencis in 1789.
Cobden and Bright were promiscuously likened to Baboeuf,
Chaumette, and Anacharsis Clootz. Baboeuf, it
is true, was for dividing up all property, and Chaumette
was an aggressive atheist; but these were mere nuances,
not material to the purposes of obloquy. Robespierre,
Danton, Marat have been mercilessly trotted forth in
their sanguinary shrouds, and treated as the counterparts
and precursors of worthies so obviously and exactly
like them as Mr. Beales and Mr. Odger; while an innocent
caucus for the registration of voters recalls to some
well-known writers lurid visions of the Cordeliers
and the Jacobin Club.
A recent addition has been made to
the stock of nicknames drawn from the terrible melodrama
of the last century. The Chancellor of the Exchequer
at Dublin described the present very humble writer
as “the Saint-Just of our Revolution.”
The description was received with lively applause.
It would be indelicate to wonder how many in a hundred,
even in that audience of the elect, had ever heard
of Saint-Just, how many in five hundred could have
spelt his name, and how many in a thousand could have
told any three facts in his career. But let us
muse for a moment upon the portrait. I take down
the first picture of Saint-Just that comes to my hand,
M. Taine is the artist:
“Among these energetic nullities
we see gradually rising a young monster with
face handsome and tranquil Saint-Just!
A sort of precocious Sulla, who at five-and-twenty
suddenly springs from the ranks, and by force
of atrocity wins his place! Six years before,
he began life by an act of domestic robbery: while
on a visit at his mother’s, he ran away
in the night with her plate and jewels; for that
he was locked up for six months. On his release,
he employed his leisure in the composition of an
odious poem. Then he flung himself head foremost
into the revolution. Blood calcined by study,
a colossal pride, a conscience completely unhinged,
an imagination haunted by the bloody recollections
of Rome and Sparta, an intelligence falsified
and twisted until it found itself most at its
ease in the practice of enormous paradox, barefaced
sophism, and murderous lying all these perilous
ingredients, mixed in a furnace of concentrated
ambition, boiled and fermented long and silently
in his breast.”
It is, no doubt, hard to know ourselves.
One may entertain demons unawares, and have calcined
blood without being a bit the wiser. Still, I
do not find the likeness striking. It would have
done just as well to call me Nero, Torquemada, Iago,
or Bluebeard.
Whether the present writer does or
does not deserve all the compliments that history
has paid to Saint-Just, is a very slight and trivial
question, with which the public will naturally not
much concern itself. But as some use is from
time to time made of the writer’s imputed delinquencies
to prejudice an important cause, it is perhaps worth
while to try in a page or two to give a better account
of things. It is true that he has written on revolutionists
like Robespierre, and destructive thinkers like Rousseau
and Voltaire. It is true that he believes the
two latter to have been on the whole, when all deductions
are made, on the side of human progress. But what
sort of foundation in this for the inference that he
“finds his models in the heroes of the French
Revolution,” and “looks for his methods
in the Reign of Terror”? It would be equally
logical to infer that because I have written, not
without sympathy and appreciation, of Joseph de Maistre,
I therefore find my model in a hero of the Catholic
Reaction, and look for my methods in the revived supremacy
of the Holy See over all secular and temporal authorities.
It would be just as fair to say that because I pointed
out, as it was the critic’s business to do,
the many admirable merits, and the important moral
influences on the society of that time, of the New
Heloisa, therefore I am bound to think Saint Preux
a very fine fellow, particularly fit to be a model
and a hero for young Ireland. Only on the principle
that who drives fat oxen must himself be fat, can it
be held that who writes on Danton must be himself
in all circumstances a Dantonist.
The most insignificant of literary
contributions have a history and an origin; and the
history of these contributions is short and simple
enough. Carlyle with all the force of his humoristic
genius had impressed upon his generation an essentially
one-sided view both of the eighteenth century as a
whole, and of the French thinkers of that century
in particular. His essay on Diderot, his lecture
on Rousseau, his chapters on Voltaire, with all their
brilliance, penetration, and incomparable satire,
were the high-water mark in this country of the literary
reaction against the French school of Revolution.
Everybody knows the famous diatribes against the Bankrupt
Century and all its men and all its works. Voltaire’s
furies, Diderot’s indigestions, Rousseau’s
nauseous amours, and the odd tricks and shifts of the
whole of them and their company, offered ready material
for the boisterous horseplay of the transcendental
humourist. Then the tide began to turn.
Mr. Buckle’s book on the history of civilisation
had something to do with it. But it was the historical
chapters in Comte’s Positive Philosophy that
first opened the minds of many of us, who, five-and-twenty
years ago, were young men, to a very different judgment
of the true place of those schools in the literary
and social history of Western Europe. We learnt
to perceive that though much in the thought and the
lives of the literary precursors of the Revolution
laid them fairly open to Carlyle’s banter, yet
banter was not all, and even grave condemnation was
not all. In essays, like mine, written from this
point of view, and with the object of trying to trim
the balance rather more correctly, it may well have
been that the better side of the thinkers concerned
was sometimes unduly dwelt upon, and their worse side
unduly left in the background. It may well have
been that an impression of personal adhesion was conveyed
which only very partially existed, or even where it
did not exist at all: that is a risk of misinterpretation
which it is always hard for the historical critic
to escape. There may have been a too eager tone;
but to be eager is not a very bad vice at any age
under the critical forty. There were some needlessly
aggressive passages, and some sallies which ought
to have been avoided, because they gave pain to good
people. There was perhaps too much of the particular
excitement of the time. It was the date when
Essays and Reviews was still thought a terrible
explosive; when Bishop Colenso’s arithmetical
tests as to the flocks and herds of the children of
Israel were believed to be sapping not only the inspiration
of the Pentateuch but the foundations of the Faith
and the Church; and when Darwin’s scientific
speculations were shaking the civilised world.
Some excitement was to be pardoned in days like those,
and I am quite sure that one side needed pardon at
least as much as the other. For the substantial
soundness of the general views winch I took of the
French revolutionary thinkers at that time, I feel
no apprehension; nor some possible occasional
phrases or sentences excepted and apart do
I see the smallest reason to shrink or to depart from
any one of them. So far as one particular reference
may serve to illustrate the tenour of the whole body
of criticism, the following lines, which close my chapter
on the “Encyclopædia,” will answer the
purpose as well as any others, and I shall perhaps
be excused for transcribing them:
“An urgent social task lay before
France and before Europe: it could not be
postponed until the thinkers had worked out a scheme
of philosophic completeness. The thinkers
did not seriously make any effort after this completeness.
The Encyclopædia was the most serious attempt,
and it did not wholly fail. As I replace in my
shelves this mountain of volumes, ’dusky
and huge, enlarging on the sight,’ I have
a presentiment that their pages will seldom again
be disturbed by me or by others. They served a
great purpose a hundred years ago. They are
now a monumental ruin, clothed with all the profuse
associations of history. It is no Ozymandias of
Egypt, king of kings, whose wrecked shape of stone
and sterile memories we contemplate. We think
rather of the grey and crumbling walls of an ancient
stronghold, reared by the endeavour of stout hands
and faithful, whence in its own day and generation
a band once went forth against barbarous hordes,
to strike a blow for humanity and truth."
It is gratifying to find that the
same view of the work of these famous men, and of
its relation to the social necessities of the time,
commends itself to Mr. Lecky, who has since gone diligently
and with a candid mind over the same ground. Then
where is the literary Jacobin?
Of course, it is easy enough to fish
out a sentence or a short passage here and there which,
if taken by itself, may wear a very sinister look,
and carry the most alarming impressions. Not many
days ago a writer addressed a letter to the Times
which furnishes a specimen of this kind of controversy.
He gave himself the ambiguous designation of “Catholicus”;
but his style bore traces of the equivocally Catholic
climate of Munich. His aim was the lofty and magnanimous
one of importing theological prejudice into the great
political dispute of the day; in the interest, strange
to say, of the Irish party who have been for ages
the relentless oppressors of the Church to which he
belongs, and who even now hate and despise it with
all the virulence of a Parisian Red. This masked
assailant conveys to the mind of the reader that I
applaud and sympathise with the events of the winter
of 1793, and more particularly with the odious procession
of the Goddess of Reason at Notre Dame. He says,
moreover, that I have “the effrontery to imply
that the horrible massacres of the Revolution ...
were ’a very mild story compared with the atrocities
of the Jews or the crimes of Catholicism.’”
No really honest and competent disputant would have
hit on “effrontery” as the note of the
passage referred to, if he had had its whole spirit
and drift before him. The reader shall, if he
pleases, judge for himself. After the words just
quoted, I go on to say:
“Historical recriminations, however,
are not edifying. It is perfectly fair, when
Catholics talk of the atheist Terror, to rejoin
that the retainers of Anjou and Montpensier slew more
men and women on the first day of the Saint Bartholomew,
than perished in Paris through the Years I. and
II. But the retort does us no good beyond
the region of dialectic. Some of the opinions
of Chaumette were full of enlightenment and hope.
But it would be far better to share the superstitious
opinions of a virtuous and benignant priest, like
the Bishop in Victor Hugo’s Miserables,
than to hold these good opinions of Chaumette,
as he held them, with a rancorous intolerance,
a reckless disregard of the rights and feelings
of others, and a shallow forgetfulness of all that
great and precious part of our nature that lies
out of the domain of the logical understanding....
In every family where a mother sought to have
her child baptised, or where sons and daughters sought
to have the dying spirit of the old consoled by the
last sacrament, there sprang up a bitter enemy
to the government which had closed the churches
and proscribed the priests. How could a society
whose spiritual life had been nourished in the solemn
mysticism of the Middle Ages suddenly turn to embrace
a gaudy paganism? The common self-respect
of humanity was outraged by apostate priests ...
as they filed before the Convention, led by the
Archbishop of Paris, and accompanied by rude acolytes
bearing piles of the robes and the vessels of
silver and gold with which they had once served
their holy office."
Where is the effrontery, the search
for methods in the Reign of Terror, the applause for
revolutionary models? Such inexcusable perversion
of a writer’s meaning for an evanescent political
object and a very shabby object too is
enough to make one think that George III. knew what
he was talking about, when he once delivered himself
of the saying that “Politics are a trade for
a rascal, not for a gentleman.”
Let me cite another more grotesque
piece of irrelevancy with a similar drift. Some
months ago the present writer chanced to express an
opinion upon Welsh Disestablishment. Wales, at
any rate, would seem to be far enough away from Emile,
Candide, the Law of Prairial, and the Committee
of Public Safety. The Times, however, instantly
said that it would be affectation to express any
surprise, because my unfortunate “theories and
principles, drawn from French sources and framed on
French models, all tend to the disintegration of comprehensive
political organisations and the encouragement of arrangements
based on the minor peculiarities of race or dialect.”
Was there ever in the world such prodigious nonsense?
What French sources, what French models? If French
models point in any one direction rather than another,
it is away from disintegration and straight towards
centralisation. Everybody knows that this is one
of the most notorious facts of French history from
the days of Lewis XI. or Cardinal Richelieu down to
Napoleon Bonaparte. So far from French models
encouraging “arrangements based on the minor
peculiarities of race and dialect,” France is
the first great example in modern history, for good
or for evil, of a persevering process of national unification,
and the firm suppression of all provincial particularismus.
This is not only true of French political leaders
in general: it is particularly true of the Jacobin
leaders. Rousseau himself, I admit, did in one
place point in the direction of confederation; but
only in the sense that for freedom on the one hand,
and just administration on the other, the unit should
not be too large to admit of the participation of
the persons concerned in the management of their own
public affairs. If the Jacobins had not been overwhelmed
by the necessity of keeping out the invaders, they
might have developed the germ of truth in Rousseau’s
loose way of stating the expediency of decentralisation.
As it was, above all other French schools, the Jacobins
dealt most sternly with particularist pretensions.
Of all men, these supposed masters, teachers, and
models of mine are least to be called Separatists.
To them more than to any other of the revolutionary
parties the great heresy of Federalism was most odious;
and if I were a faithful follower of the Jacobin model,
I should have least patience with nationalist sentiment
whether in Ireland, Scotland, or Wales, and should
most rigorously insist on that cast-iron incorporation
which, as it happens, in the case of Ireland I believe
to be equally hopeless and undesirable. This explanation,
therefore, of my favour for Welsh Disestablishment
is as absurdly ignorant as it is far-fetched and irrelevant.
The logical process is worth an instant’s
examination. The position is no less than this, that
to attempt truly to appreciate the place and the value
in the history of thought and social movements of men
who have been a hundred years in their graves, and
to sympathise with certain sides and certain effects
of their activity under the peculiar circumstances
in which French society then found itself, is the same
thing as binding yourself to apply their theories and
to imitate their activity, under an entirely heterogeneous
set of circumstances, in a different country, and
in a society with wholly dissimilar requirements.
That is the argument if we straighten it out.
The childishness of any such contention is so obvious,
that I should be ashamed of reproducing it, were it
not that this very contention has made its appearance
at my expense several times a month for the last two
years in all sorts of important and respectable prints.
For instance, it appears that I once
said somewhere that Danton looked on at the doings
of his bloodier associates with “sombre acquiescence.”
Argal, it was promptly pointed out and
I espy the dark phrase constantly adorning leading
articles to this day the man who said that
Danton sombrely acquiesced in the doings of Billaud,
Collet, and the rest, must of necessity, being of a
firm and logical mind, himself sombrely acquiesce
in moonlighting and cattle-houghing in Ireland.
Apart from the curious compulsion of the reasoning,
what is the actual state of the case? Acquiescence
is hardly a good description of the mood of a politician
who scorns delights and lives laborious days in actively
fighting for a vigorous policy and an effective plan
which, as he believes, would found order in Ireland
on a new and more hopeful base. He may be wrong,
but where is the acquiescence, whether sombre or serene?
The equally misplaced name of Fatalism
is sometimes substituted for acquiescence, in criticisms
of this stamp. In any such sense anybody is a
fatalist who believes in a relation between cause and
effect. If it is fatalism to assume that, given
a certain chain of social or political antecedents,
they will inevitably be followed by a certain chain
of consequences, then every sensible observer of any
series of events is a fatalist. Catholic Emancipation,
the extension of the franchise, and secret ballot,
have within the last sixty years completely shifted
the balance of political power in Ireland. Land
legislation has revolutionised the conditions of ownership.
These vast and vital changes in Ireland have been
accompanied by the transfer of decisive power from
aristocracy to numbers in Great Britain, and Great
Britain is arbiter. Is it fatalism, or is it common
sense, to perceive that one new effect of new causes
so potent must be the necessity of changing the system
of Irish government? To dream that you could
destroy the power of the old masters without finding
new, and that having invited the nation to speak you
could continue to ignore the national sentiment was
and is the very height of political folly, and the
longer the dream is persisted in the ruder will be
the awakening. Surely the stupidest fatalism
is far more truly to be ascribed to those who insist
that Ireland was eternally predestined to turmoil,
confusion, and torment; that there alone the event
defies calculation; and that, however wisely, carefully
and providently you modify or extinguish causes, in
Ireland, though nowhere else, effects will still survive
with shape unaltered and force unabated.
No author has a right to assume that
anybody has read all his books or any of them, but
he may reasonably claim that he shall not be publicly
classified, labelled, catalogued, and placed In the
shelves, on the strength of half of his work, and
that half arbitrarily selected. If it be permitted
to me without excess of egotism to name the masters
to whom I went to school in the days of early manhood,
so far from being revolutionists and terrorists, they
belonged entirely to the opposite camp. Austin’s
Jurisprudence and Mill’s Logic
and Utilitarianism were everything, and Rousseau’s
Social Contract was nothing. To the best
of my knowledge and belief, I never said a word about
“Natural Rights” in any piece of practical
public business in all my life; and when that famous
phrase again made its naked appearance on the platform
three or four years ago, it gave me as much surprise
and dismay as if I were this afternoon to meet a Deinotherium
shambling down Parliament Street. Mill was the
chief influence for me, as he was for most of my contemporaries
in those days. Experience of life and independent
use of one’s mind which he would have
been the most ready of men to applaud have
since, as is natural, led to many important corrections
and deductions in Mill’s political and philosophical
teaching. But then we were disciples, and not
critics; and nobody will suppose that the admirer
of Wordsworth, the author of the Essay on Coleridge,
and of the treatise on Representative Government, the
administrator in the most bureaucratic and authoritative
of public services, was a terrorist or an unbridled
democrat, or anything else but the most careful and
rationalistic of political theorisers. It was
Mill who first held up for my admiration the illustrious
man whom Austin enthusiastically called the “godlike
Turgot,” and it was he who encouraged me to
write a study on that great and inspiring character.
I remember the suspicion and the murmurings with which
Louis Blanc, then living in brave and honourable exile
in London, and the good friend of so many of us, and
who was really a literary Jacobin to the tips of his
fingers, remonstrated against that piece of what he
thought grievously misplaced glorification. Turgot
was, indeed, a very singular hero with whom to open
the career of literary Jacobin. So was Burke, the
author of those wise sentences that still ring in
our ears: “The question with me is, not
whether you have a right to render your people miserable,
but whether it is not your interest to make them happy.
It is not what a lawyer tells me I may do, but what
humanity, reason, and justice tell me I ought to do.
Nobody shall persuade me, where a whole people are
concerned, that acts of lenity are not means of conciliation.”
Burke, Austin, Mill, Turgot, Comte what
strange sponsors for the “theories and principles
of the Terror”!
What these opinions came to, roughly
speaking, was something to this effect: That
the power alike of statesmen and of publicists over
the course of affairs is strictly limited; that institutions
and movements are not capable of immediate or indefinite
modification by any amount of mere will; that political
truths are always relative, and never absolute; that
the test of practical, political, and social proposals
is not their conformity to abstract ideals, but to
convenience, utility, expediency, and occasion; that
for the reformer, considerations of time and place
may be paramount; and finally, as Mill himself has
put it, that government is always either in the hands,
or passing into the hands, of whatever is the strongest
power in society, and that what this power is, and
shall be, depends less on institutions than institutions
depend upon it. If I were pressed for an illustration
of these principles at work, inspiring the minds and
guiding the practice of responsible statesmen in great
transactions of our own day and generation, I should
point to the sage, the patient, the triumphant action
of Abraham Lincoln in the emancipation of the negro
slaves. However that may be, contrast a creed
of this kind with the abstract, absolute, geometric,
unhistoric, peremptory notions and reasonings that
formed the stock in trade of most, though not quite
all, of the French revolutionists, alike in action
and in thought. It is plain that they are the
direct opposite and contradictory of one another.
To clench the matter by chapter and
verse, I should like to recall what, I have said of
these theories and principles in their most perfect
and most important literary version. How have
I described Rousseau’s Social Contract?
It placed, I said, the centre of social activity elsewhere
than in careful and rational examination of social
conditions, and careful and rational effort to modify
them. It substituted a retrograde aspiration
for direction, and emotion for the discovery of law.
It overlooked the crucial difficulty namely,
how to summon new force, without destroying the sound
parts of a structure which it has taken many generations
to erect. Its method was geometric instead of
being historic, and hence its “desperate absurdity.”
Its whole theory was constructed with an imperfect
consideration of the qualities of human nature, and
with too narrow a view of society. It ignored
the great fact that government is the art of wisely
dealing with huge groups of conflicting interests,
of hostile passions, of hardly reconcilable aims,
of vehemently opposed forces. It “gives
us not the least help towards the solution of any
of the problems of actual government.”
Such language as all this is hardly
that of a disciple to a master, in respect of theories
and principles which he is making his own for the
use of a lifetime. “There has been no attempt”
[in these pages], I said in winding up, “to
palliate either the shallowness or the practical mischievousness
of the Social Contract. But there is another
side to its influence. We should be false to our
critical principle, if we do not recognise the historical
effect of a speculation scientifically valueless.”
Any writer would have stamped himself as both unfit
for the task that I had undertaken, and entirely below
the level of the highest critical standard of the day,
if he had for a moment dreamed of taking any other
point of view.
As for historical hero-worship, after
Carlyle’s fashion, whether with Jacobin idols
or any other, it is a mood of mind that must be uncongenial
to anybody who had ever been at all under the influence
of Mill. Without being so foolish as to disparage
the part played by great men in great crises, we could
have no sympathy with the barbaric and cynical school,
who make greatness identical with violence, force,
and mere iron will. Cromwell said, in vindication
of himself, that England had need of a constable,
and it was true. The constable, the soldier,
the daring counsellor at the helm, are often necessities
of the time. It is often a necessity of the time
that the energy of a nation or of a movement should
gather itself up in a resolute band or a resolute
chief; as the revolutionary energy of France gathered
itself up in the greater Jacobins, or that of England
in Oliver Cromwell. Goethe says that nature bids
us “Take all, but pay.” Revolutions
and heroes may give us all, but not without price.
This is at the best, and the best is the exception.
The grandiose types mostly fail. In our own day,
people talk, for example, with admiration of Cromwell’s
government in Ireland, as if it were a success,
instead of being one of the worst chapters in the
whole history of Irish failure. It was force
carried to its utmost. Hundreds were put to the
sword, thousands were banished to be slaves of the
planters in the West Indies, and the remnant were
driven miserably off into the desolate wilds of Connaught.
But all this only prepared the way for further convulsions
and deadlier discontent.
It is irrational to contrast Carlyle’s
heroes, Cromwell, Mirabeau, Frederick, Napoleon, with
men like Washington or Lincoln. The circumstances
were different. The conditions of public use and
of personal greatness were different. But if
we are to talk of ideals, heroes, and models, I, for
one, should hardly look to France at all. Jefferson
was no flatterer of George Washington; but his character
of Washington comes far nearer to the right pattern
of a great ruler than can be found in any of Carlyle’s
splendid dithyrambs, and it is no waste of time to
recall and to transcribe it:
“His mind was great and powerful,
without being of the very first order; his penetration
strong, though not so acute as that of a Newton,
Bacon, or Locke; and as far as he saw, no judgment
was ever sounder. It was slow in operation,
being little aided by invention or imagination,
but sure in conclusion. Hence the common remark
of his officers, of the advantage he derived from councils
of war, where, hearing all suggestions, he selected
whatever was best; and certainly no general ever
planned his battles more judiciously. But
if deranged during the course of the action, if any
member of his plan was dislocated by sudden circumstances,
he was slow in a readjustment. He was incapable
of fear, meeting personal dangers with the calmest
unconcern. Perhaps the strongest feature
in his character was prudence, never acting until
every circumstance, every consideration, was maturely
weighed; refraining if he saw a doubt, but when
once decided, going through with his purpose,
whatever obstacles opposed. His integrity was
most pure, his justice the most inflexible I have
ever known; no motives of interest or consanguinity,
of friendship or hatred, being able to bias his
decision. He was, indeed, in every sense of
the word, a wise, a good, and a great man. His
temper was naturally irritable and high toned;
but reflection and resolution had obtained a firm
and habitual ascendency over it.”
In conclusion, the plain truth is
that all parallels, analogies, and similitudes
between the French Revolution, or any part or phase
of it, and our affairs in Ireland are moonshine.
For the practical politician his problem is always
individual. For his purposes history never repeats
itself. Human nature, doubtless, has a weakness
for a precedent; it is a weakness to be respected.
But there is no such thing as an essential reproduction
of social and political combinations of circumstance.
To talk about Robespierre in connection with Ireland
is just as idle as it was in Robespierre to harangue
about Lycurgus and Brutus in Paris. To compare
the two is to place Ireland under a preposterous magnifying-glass
of monstrous dimension. Nor is disparity of scale
the only difference, vital as that is. In no
one of the leading characteristics of a community in
a state of ferment, save the odium that surrounds
the landlords, and that not universal, does Ireland
to-day really resemble the France of a hundred years
ago. Manners, ideas, beliefs, traditions, crumbling
institutions, rising aspirations, the ordering of castes
and classes, the rivalry of creeds, the relations
with the governing power all constitute
elements of such radical divergence as to make comparison
between modern Ireland and revolutionary France for
any more serious purpose than giving a conventional
and familiar point to a sentence, entirely worthless.
It is pure dilettantism, again, to
seek the moral of Irish commotions in the insurrection
of La Vendée. That, as somebody has said, was
like a rising of the ancient Gauls at the voice of
the Druids, and led by their great chiefs. It
will be time enough to compare La Vendée with Ireland
when the peasantry take the field against the British
Government with Beresfords, Fitzgeralds, and Bourkes
at their head. If the Vendeans had risen to drive
out the Charettes, the Bonchamps, the Larochejacquelins,
the parallel would have been nearer the mark.
The report of the Devon Commission, the green pamphlet
containing an account of the famous three days’
discussion between O’Connell and Butt in the
Dublin Corporation In 1843, or half a dozen of Lord
Clare’s speeches between 1793 and 1800, will
give a clearer insight into the Irish problem than
a bushel of books about the Vendean or any other episode
of the Revolution.
Equally frivolous is it, for any useful
purpose of practical enlightenment, to draw parallels
between the action of the Catholic clergy in Ireland
to-day and that of the French clergy on the eve of
the Revolution. There is no sort of force in the
argument that because the French clergy fared ill
at the Revolution, therefore the Irish clergy will
fare ill when self-government is bestowed on Ireland.
Such talk is mere ingenious guess-work at best, without
any of the foundations of a true historical analogy.
The differences between the two cases are obvious,
and they go to the heart of the matter. For instance,
the men who came to the top of affairs in France were
saturated both with speculative unbelief for one thing,
and with active hatred of the Church for another.
In Ireland, on the contrary, there is no speculative
unbelief, as O’Connell used so constantly to
boast; and the Church being poor, voluntary, and intensely
national and popular, has nourished none of those
gross and swollen abuses which provoked the not unreasonable
animosity of revolutionary France. In truth,
it is with precisely as much or as little reason that
most of the soothsayers and prognosticators of evil
take the directly opposite line. Instead of France
these persons choose, as they have an equally good
right to do, to look for precedents to Spain, Belgium,
or South America. Why not? They assure us,
in their jingling phrase, that Home Rule means Rome
Rule, that the priests will be the masters, and that
Irish autonomy is only another name for the reign of
bigotry, superstition, and obscurantism. One
of these two mutually destructive predictions has
just as much to say for itself as the other, and no
more. We may leave the prophets to fight it out
between them while we attend to our business, and
examine facts and probabilities as they are, without
the aid of capriciously adopted precedents and fantastical
analogies.
Parallels from France, or anywhere
else, may supply literary amusement; they may furnish
a weapon in the play of controversy. They shed
no light and do no service as we confront the solid
facts of the business to be done. Lewis the Fourteenth
was the author of a very useful and superior commonplace
when he wrote: “No man who is badly informed
can avoid reasoning badly. I believe that whoever
is rightly instructed, and rightly persuaded of all
the facts, would never do anything else but what
he ought.” Another great French ruler, who,
even more than Lewis, had a piercing eye for men and
the world of action, said that the mind of a general
ought to be like a field-glass, and as clear; to see
things exactly as they are, et jamais se faire
des tableaux, never to compose the objects
before him into pictures. The same maxim is nearly
as good for the man who has to conquer difficulties
in the field of government; and analogies and parallels
are one way of substituting pictures for plans and
charts. Just because the statesman’s problem
is individual, history can give him little help.
I am not so graceless as to depreciate history or
literature either for public or for private persons.
“You are a man,” Napoleon said to Goethe;
and there is no reason why literature should prevent
the reader of books from being a man; why it should
blind him to the great practical truths that the end
of life is not to think but to will; that everything
in the world has its decisive moment, which statesmen
know and seize; that the genius of politics, as a
great man of letters truly wrote, has not “All
or Nothing” for its motto, but seeks on the
contrary to extract the greatest advantage from situations
the most compromised, and never flings the helve after
the hatchet. Like literature the use of history
in politics is to refresh, to open, to make the mind
generous and hospitable; to enrich, to impart flexibility,
to quicken and nourish political imagination and invention,
to instruct in the common difficulties and the various
experiences of government; to enable a statesman to
place himself at a general and spacious standpoint.
All this, whether it be worth much or little, and
it is surely worth much, is something wholly distinct
from directly aiding a statesman in the performance
of a specific task. In such a case an analogy
from history, if he be not sharply on his guard, is
actually more likely than not to mislead him.
I certainly do not mean the history of the special
problem itself. Of that he cannot possibly know
too much, nor master its past course and foregone
bearings too thoroughly. Ireland is a great standing
instance. There is no more striking example of
the disastrous results of trying to overcome political
difficulties without knowing how they came into existence,
and where they have their roots. The only history
that furnishes a clue in Irish questions is the history
of Ireland and the people who have lived in it or have
been driven out of it.