The present number of the Review marks
the close of a task which was confided to me no less
than fifteen years ago grande mortalis
cevi spatium, a long span of one’s mortal
days. Fifteen years are enough to bring a man
from youth to middle age, to test the working value
of convictions, to measure the advance of principles
and beliefs, and, alas! to cut off many early associates
and to extinguish many lights. It is hardly possible
that a Review should have been conducted for so considerable
a time without the commission of some mistakes; articles
admitted which might as well have been left out, opinions
expressed which have a crudish look in the mellow
light of years, phrases dropped in the heat or hurry
of the moment which one would fain obliterate.
Many a regret must rise in men’s minds on any
occasion that compels them to look back over a long
reach of years. The disparity between aim and
performance, the unfulfilled promise, the wrong turnings
taken at critical points as an accident
of the hour draws us to take stock of a complete period
of our lives, all these things rise up in private
and internal judgment against anybody who is not either
too stupid or too fatuously complacent to recognise
facts when he sees them. But the mood passes.
Time, happily, is merciful, and men’s memories
are benignly short.
More painful is the recollection of
those earlier contributors of ours who have vanished
from the world. Periodical literature is like
the manna in the wilderness; it quickly loses its
freshness, and to turn over thirty volumes of old
Reviews can hardly be exhilarating at the best:
least of all so, when it recalls friends and coadjutors
who can give their help no more. George Henry
Lewes, the founder of the Review, and always cordially
interested in its fortunes, has not survived to see
the end of the reign of his successor, His vivacious
intelligence had probably done as much as he was competent
to do for his generation, but there were other important
contributors, now gone, of whom this could not be
said. In the region of political theory, the
loss of J.E. Cairnes was truly lamentable and
untimely. He had, as Mill said of him, “that
rare qualification among writers on political and
social subjects a genuine scientific intellect.”
Not a month passes in which one does not feel how
great an advantage it would have been to be able to
go down to Blackheath, and discuss the perplexities
of the time in that genial and manly companionship,
where facts were weighed with so much care, where
conclusions were measured with such breadth and comprehension,
and where even the great stolid idols of the Cave
and the Market Place were never too rudely buffeted.
Of a very different order of mind from Cairnes, but
not less to be permanently regretted by all of us
who knew him, was Mr. Bagehot, whose books on the
English Constitution, on Physics and Politics, and
the fragment on the Postulates of Political Economy,
were all published in these pages. He wrote,
in fact, the first article in the first number.
Though himself extremely cool and sceptical about
political improvement of every sort, he took abundant
interest in more ardent friends. Perhaps it was
that they amused him; in return his good-natured ironies
put them wholesomely on their mettle. As has been
well said of him, he had a unique power of animation
without combat; it was all stimulus and yet no contest;
his talk was full of youth, yet had all the wisdom
of mature judgment (R.H. Hutton).
Those who were least willing to assent to Bagehot’s
practical maxims in judging current affairs, yet were
well aware how much they profited by his Socratic
objections, and knew, too, what real acquaintance with
men and business, what honest sympathy and friendliness,
and what serious judgment and interest all lay under
his playful and racy humour.
More untimely, in one sense, than
any other was the death of Professor Clifford, whose
articles in this Review attracted so much attention,
and I fear that I may add, gave for a season so much
offence six or seven years ago. Cairnes was scarcely
fifty when he died, and Bagehot was fifty-one, but
Clifford was only four-and-thirty. Yet in this
brief space he had not merely won a reputation as a
mathematician of the first order, but had made a real
mark on his time, both by the substance of his speculations
in science, religion, and ethics, and by the curious
audacity with which he proclaimed at the pitch of his
voice on the housetops religious opinions that had
hitherto been kept among the family secrets of the
domus Socratica. It is melancholy to think
that exciting work, done under pressure of time of
his own imposing, should have been the chief cause
of his premature decline. How intense that pressure
was the reader may measure by the fact that a paper
of his on The Unseen Universe, which filled
eighteen pages of the Review, was composed at a single
sitting that lasted from a quarter to ten in the evening
till nine o’clock the following morning.
As one revolves these and other names of eminent men
who actively helped to make the Review what it has
been, it would be impossible to omit the most eminent
of them all. Time has done something to impair
the philosophical reputation and the political celebrity
of J.S. Mill; but it cannot alter the affectionate
memory in which some of us must always hold his wisdom
and goodness, his rare union of moral ardour with
a calm and settled mind. He took the warmest interest
In this Review from the moment when I took it up,
partly from the friendship with which he honoured
me, but much more because he wished to encourage what
was then though it is now happily no longer the
only attempt to conduct a periodical on the principles
of free discussion and personal responsibility.
While recalling these and others who are no more,
it was naturally impossible for me to forget the constant
and valuable help that has been so freely given to
me, often at much sacrifice of their own convenience,
by those friends and contributors who are still with
us. No conductor ever laid down his baton
with a more cordial and sincere sense of gratitude
to those who took their several parts in his performance.
One chief experiment which the Review
was established to try was that of signed articles.
When Mr. Lewes wrote his Farewell Causerie, as I am
doing now, he said: “That we have been enabled
to bring together men so various in opinion and so
distinguished in power has been mainly owing to the
principle adopted of allowing each writer perfect
freedom; which could only have been allowed under the
condition of personal responsibility. The question
of signing articles had long been debated; it has
now been tested. The arguments in favour of it
were mainly of a moral order; the arguments against
it, while admitting the morality, mainly asserted
its inexpediency. The question of expediency
has, I venture to say, been materially enlightened
by the success of the Review.” The success
of other periodicals, conducted still more rigorously
on the principle that every article ought to bear
its writer’s signature, leaves no further doubt
on the subject; so that it is now almost impossible
to realise that only fifteen or sixteen years ago
scarcely anybody of the class called practical could
believe that the sacred principle of the Anonymous
was doomed. One of the shrewdest publishers in
Edinburgh, and also himself the editor of a famous
magazine, once said to me while Mr. Lewes was still
editor of this Review, that he had always thought highly
of our friend’s judgment “until he had
taken up the senseless notion of a magazine with signed
articles and open to both sides of every question.”
Nobody will call the notion senseless any longer.
The question is rather how long the exclusively anonymous
periodicals will resist the innovation.
Personally I have attached less stern
importance to signature as an unvarying rule than
did my predecessor; though, even he was compelled
by obvious considerations of convenience to make his
chronique of current affairs anonymous.
Our practice has been signature as the standing rule,
occasionally suspended in favour of anonymity when
there seemed to be sufficient reason. On the whole
it may be said that the change from anonymous to signed
articles has followed the course of most changes.
It has not led to one-half either of the evils or of
the advantages that its advocates and its opponents
foretold. That it has produced some charlatanry,
can hardly be denied. Readers are tempted to
postpone serious and persistent interest in subjects,
to a semi-personal curiosity about the casual and
unconnected deliverances of the literary or social
star of the hour. That this conception has been
worked out with signal ability in more cases than one;
that it has made periodical literature full of actuality;
that it has tickled and delighted the palate is
all most true. The obvious danger is lest we
should be tempted to think more of the man who speaks
than of the precise value of what he says.
One indirect effect that is not unworthy
of notice in the new system is its tendency to narrow
the openings for the writer by profession. If
an article is to be signed, the editor will naturally
seek the name of an expert of special weight and competence
on the matter in hand. A reviewer on the staff
of a famous journal once received for his week’s
task, General Hamley on the Art of War, a three-volume
novel, a work on dainty dishes, and a translation
of Pindar. This was perhaps taxing versatility
and omniscience over-much, and it may be taken for
granted that the writer made no serious contribution
to tactics, cookery, or scholarship. But being
a man of a certain intelligence, passably honest,
and reasonably painstaking, probably he produced reviews
sufficiently useful and just to answer their purpose.
On the new system we should have an article on General
Hamley’s work by Sir Garnet Wolseley, and one
on the cookery-book from M. Trompette. It
is not certain that this is all pure gain. There
is a something to be said for the writer by profession,
who, without being an expert, will take trouble to
work up his subject, to learn what is said and thought
about it, to penetrate to the real points, to get the
same mastery over it as an advocate or a judge does
over a patent case or a suit about rubrics and vestments.
He is at least as likely as the expert to tell the
reader all that he wants to know, and at least as likely
to be free from bias and injurious prepossession.
Nor does experience, so far as it
has yet gone, quite bear out Mr. Lewes’s train
of argument that the “first condition of all
writing is sincerity, and that one means of securing
sincerity is to insist on personal responsibility,”
and that this personal responsibility can only be
secured by signing articles. The old talk of “literary
bravoes,” “men in masks,” “anonymous
assassins,” and so forth, is out of date.
Longer experience has only confirmed the present writer’s
opinion, expressed here from the very beginning:
“Everybody who knows the composition of any
respectable journal in London knows very well that
the articles which those of our own way of thinking
dislike most intensely are written by men whom to
call bravoes in any sense whatever would be simply
monstrous. Let us say, as loudly as we choose,
if we see good reason, that they are half informed
about some of the things which they so authoritatively
discuss; that they are under strong class feeling;
that they have not mastered the doctrines which they
are opposing; that they have not sufficiently meditated
their subject; that they have not given themselves
time to do justice even to their scanty knowledge.
Journalists are open to charges of this kind; but
to think of them as a shameless body, thirsting for
the blood of better men than themselves, or ready
to act as an editor’s instrument for money,
involves a thoroughly unjust misconception.”
As to the comparative effects of the
two systems on literary quality, no prudent observer
with adequate experience will lay down an unalterable
rule. Habit no doubt counts for a great deal,
but apart from habit there are differences of temperament
and peculiar sensibilities. Some men write best
when they sign what they write; they find impersonality
a mystification and an incumbrance; anonymity makes
them stiff, pompous, and over-magisterial. With
others, however, the effect is just the reverse.
If they sign, they become self-conscious, stilted,
and even pretentious; it is only when they are anonymous
that they recover simplicity and ease. It is as
if an actor who is the soul of what is natural under
the disguises of his part, should become extremely
artificial if he were compelled to come upon the stage
in his own proper clothes and speaking only in his
ordinary voice.
The newspaper press has not yet followed
the example of the new Reviews, but we are probably
not far from the time when here, too, the practice
of signature will make its way. There was a silly
cry at one time for making the disuse of anonymity
compulsory by law. But we shall no more see this
than we shall see legal penalties imposed for publishing
a book without an index, though that also has been
suggested. The same end will be reached by other
ways. Within the last few years a truly surprising
shock has been given to the idea of a newspaper, “as
a sort of impersonal thing, coming from nobody knows
where, the readers never thinking of the writer, nor
caring whether he thinks what he writes, so long as
they think what he writes.” Of course
it is still true, and will most likely always remain
true, that, like the Athenian Sophist, great newspapers
will teach the conventional prejudices of those who
pay for it. A writer will long be able to say
that, like the Sophist, the newspaper reflects the
morality, the intelligence, the tone of sentiment,
of its public, and if the latter is vicious, so is
the former. But there is infinitely less of this
than there used to be. The press is more and more
taking the tone of a man speaking to a man. The
childish imposture of the editorial We is already
thoroughly exploded. The names of all important
journalists are now coming to be as publicly known
as the names of important members of parliament.
There is even something over and above this.
More than one editor has boldly aspired to create
and educate a public of his own, and he has succeeded.
The press is growing to be much more personal, in
the sense that its most important directors are taking
to themselves the right of pursuing an individual
line of their own, with far less respect than of old
to the supposed exigencies of party or the communiques
of political leaders. The editor of a Review
of great eminence said to the present writer (who,
for his own part, took a slightly more modest view)
that he regarded himself as equal in importance to
seventy-five Members of Parliament. It is not
altogether easy to weigh and measure with this degree
of precision. But what is certain is that there
are journalists on both sides in politics to whom
the public looks for original suggestion, and from
whom leading politicians seek not merely such mechanical
support as they expect from their adherents in the
House of Commons, nor merely the uses of the vane
to show which way the wind blows, but ideas, guidance,
and counsel, as from persons of co-equal authority
with themselves. England is still a long way from
the point at which French journalism has arrived in
this matter. We cannot count an effective host
of Girardins, Lemoinnes, Abouts, or even Cassagnacs
and Rocheforts, each recognised as the exponent of
his own opinions, and each read because the opinions
written are known to be his own. But there is
a distinctly nearer approach to this as the general
state of English journalism than there was twenty
years ago.
Of course nobody of sense supposes
that any journalist, however independent and however
possessed by the spirit of his personal responsibility,
tries to form his opinions out of his own head, without
reference to the view of the men practically engaged
in public affairs, the temper of Parliament and the
feeling of constituencies, and so forth. All
these are part of the elements that go to the formation
of his own judgment, and he will certainly not neglect
to find out as much about them as he possibly can.
Nor, again, does the increase of the personal sentiment
about our public prints lessen the general working
fidelity of their conductors to a party. It is
their duty, no doubt, to discuss the merits of measures
as they arise. In this respect any one can see
how radically they differ from the Member of Parliament,
whose business is not only to discuss but to act.
The Member of Parliament must look at the effect of
his vote in more lights than one. Besides the
merits of the given measure, it is his duty to think
of the wishes of those who chose him to represent them;
and if, moreover, the effect of voting against a measure
of which he disapproves would be to overthrow a whole
Ministry of which he strongly approves, then, unless
some very vital principle indeed were involved, to
give such a vote would be to prefer a small object
to a great one, and would indicate a very queasy monkish
sort of conscience. The journalist is not in
the same position. He is an observer and a critic,
and can afford, and is bound, to speak the truth.
But even in his case, the disagreement, as Burke said,
“will be only enough to indulge freedom, without
violating concord or disturbing arrangement.”
There is a certain “partiality which becomes
a well-chosen friendship.” “Men thinking
freely will, in particular instances, think differently.
But still as the greater part of the measures which
arise in the course of public business are related
to, or dependent on, some great leading general principles
in government, a man must be peculiarly unfortunate
in the choice of his political company if he does
not agree with them at least nine times in ten.”
The doctrine that was good enough for Burke in this
matter may be counted good enough for most of us.
Some of the current talk about political independence
is mere hypocrisy; some of it is mere vanity.
For the new priest of Literature is quite as liable
to the defects of spiritual pride and ambition as
the old priest of the Church, and it is quite as well
for him that he should be on his guard against these
scarlet and high-crested sins.
The success of Reviews, of which our
own was the first English type, marks a very considerable
revolution in the intellectual habits of the time.
They have brought abstract discussion from the library
down to the parlour, and from the serious student
down to the first man in the street. We have
passed through a perfect cyclone of religious polemics.
The popularity of such Reviews means that really large
audiences, lé gros public, are eagerly interested
In the radical discussion of propositions which twenty
years ago were only publicly maintained, and then
in their crudest, least true, and most repulsive form,
in obscure debating societies and little secularist
clubs. Everybody, male or female, who reads anything
serious at all, now reads a dozen essays a year to
show, with infinite varieties of approach and of demonstration,
that we can never know whether there be a Supreme
Being or not, whether the soul survives the body, or
whether mind is more and other than a mere function
of matter. No article that has appeared in any
periodical for a generation back excited so profound
a sensation as Mr. Huxley’s memorable paper On
the Physical Basis of Life, published in this Review
in February 1869. It created just the same kind
of stir that, in a political epoch, was made by such
a pamphlet as the Conduct of the Allies or the
Reflections on the French Revolution.
This excitement was a sign that controversies which
had hitherto been confined to books and treatises were
now to be admitted to popular periodicals, and that
the common man of the world would now listen and have
an opinion of his own on the bases of belief, just
as he listens and judges in politics or art, or letters.
The clergy no longer have the pulpit to themselves,
for the new Reviews became more powerful pulpits,
in which heretics were at least as welcome as orthodox.
Speculation has become entirely democratised.
This is a tremendous change to have come about in little
more than a dozen years. How far it goes, let
us not be too sure. It is no new discovery that
what looks like complete tolerance may be in reality
only complete indifference. Intellectual fairness
is often only another name for indolence and inconclusiveness
of mind, just as love of truth is sometimes a fine
phrase for temper. To be piquant counts for much,
and the interest of seeing on the drawing-room tables
of devout Catholics and high-flying Anglicans article
after article, sending divinities, creeds, and Churches
all headlong into limbo, was indeed piquant.
Much of all this elegant dabbling in infidelity has
been a caprice of fashion. The Agnostic has had
his day with the fine ladies, like the black footboy
of other times, or the spirit-rapper and table-turner
of our own. What we have been watching, after
all, was perhaps a tournament, not a battle.
It would not be very easy for us now,
and perhaps it would not be particularly becoming
at any time, to analyse the position that has been
assigned to this Review in common esteem. Those
who have watched it from without can judge better
than those who have worked within. Though it
has been open, so far as editorial goodwill was concerned,
to opinions from many sides, the Review has unquestionably
gathered round it some of the associations of sect.
What that sect is, people have found it difficult
to describe with anything like precision. For
a long time it was the fashion to label the Review
as Comtist, and it would be singularly ungrateful
to deny that it has had no more effective contributors
than some of the best-known disciples of Comte.
By-and-by it was felt that this was too narrow.
It was nearer the truth to call it the organ of Positivists
in the wider sense of that designation. But even
this would not cover many directly political articles
that have appeared in our pages, and made a mark in
their time. The memorable programme of Free Labour,
Free Land, Free Schools, Free Church had nothing at
all Positivist about it. Nor could that programme
and many besides from the same pen and others be compressed
under the nickname of Academic Liberalism. There
was too strong a flavour of action for the academic
and the philosophic. This passion for a label,
after all, is an infirmity. Yet people justly
perceived that there seemed to be a certain undefinable
concurrence among writers coming from different schools
and handling very different subjects. Perhaps
the instinct was right which fancied that it discerned
some common drift, a certain pervading atmosphere,
and scented a subtle connection between speculations
on the Physical Basis of Life and the Unseen Universe,
and articles on Trades Unions and National Education.
So far as the Review has been more
specially identified with one set of opinions than
another, it has been due to the fact that a certain
dissent from received theologies has been found in
company with new ideas of social and political reform.
This suspicious combination at one time aroused considerable
anger. The notion of anything like an intervention
of the literary and scientific class in political affairs
touched a certain jealousy which is always to be looked
for in the positive and practical man. They think
as Napoleon thought of men of letters and savans: “Ce
sont des coquettes avec lesquelles
il faut entretenir un commerce
de galanterie, et dont il
ne faut jamais songer a faire
ni sa femme ni son ministre.”
Men will listen to your views about the Unknowable
with a composure that instantly disappears if your
argument comes too near to the Rates and Taxes.
It is amusing, as we read the newspapers to-day, to
think that Mr. Harrison’s powerful defence of
Trades Unions fifteen years ago caused the Review to
be regarded as an incendiary publication. Some
papers that appeared here on National Education were
thought to indicate a deliberate plot for suppressing
the Holy Scriptures in the land. Extravagant misjudgment
of this kind has passed away. But it was far from
being a mistake to suppose that the line taken here
by many writers did mean that there was a new Radicalism
in the air, which went a good deal deeper than fidgeting
about an estimate or the amount of the Queen’s
contribution to her own taxes. Time has verified
what was serious in those early apprehensions.
Principles and aims are coming into prominence in the
social activity of to-day which would hardly have found
a hearing twenty years ago, and it would be sufficient
justification for the past of our Review if some writers
in it have been instrumental in the process of showing
how such principles and aims meet the requirements
of the new time. Reformers must always be open
to the taunt that they find nothing in the world good
enough for them. “You write,” said
a popular novelist to one of this unthanked tribe,
“as if you believed that everything is bad.”
“Nay,” said the other, “but I do
believe that everything might be better.”
Such a belief naturally breeds a spirit which the
easy-goers of the world resent as a spirit of ceaseless
complaint and scolding. Hence our Liberalism here
has often been taxed with being ungenial, discontented,
and even querulous. But such Liberals will wrap
themselves in their own virtue, remembering the cheering
apophthegm that “those who are dissatisfied are
the sole benefactors of the world.”
This will not be found, I think, too
lofty, or too thrasonical an estimate of what has
been attempted. A certain number of people have
been persuaded to share opinions that fifteen years
ago were more unpopular than they are now. A
certain resistance has been offered to the stubborn
influence of prejudice and use and wont. The original
scheme of the Review, even if there had been no other
obstacle, prevented it from being the organ of a systematic
and constructive policy. There is not, in fact,
a body of systematic political thought at work in
our own day. The Liberals of the Benthamite school
surveyed society and institutions as a whole; they
connected their advocacy of political and legal changes
with carefully formed theories of human nature; they
considered the great art of Government in connection
with the character of man, his proper education, his
potential capacities. Yet, as we then said, it
cannot be pretended that we are less in need of systematic
politics than our fathers were sixty years since, or
that general principles are now more generally settled
even among members of the same party than they were
then. The perplexities of to-day are as embarrassing
as any in our history, and they may prove even more
dangerous. The renovation of Parliamentary government;
the transformation of the conditions of the ownership
and occupation of land; the relations between the
Government at home and our adventurers abroad in contact
with inferior races; the limitations on free contract
and the rights of majorities to restrict the private
acts of minorities; these are only some of the questions
that time and circumstances are pressing upon us.
These are in the political and legislative sphere
alone. In Education, in Economics, the problems
are as many. Yet ideas are hardly ripe for realisation.
We shall need to see great schools before we can make
sure of powerful parties. Meanwhile, whatever
gives freedom and variety to thought, and earnestness
to men’s interest in the world, must contribute
to a good end.