OF THE DIVISION OF ARTS
November, 1870.
1. If, as is commonly believed,
the subject of study which it is my special function
to bring before you had no relation to the great interests
of mankind, I should have less courage in asking for
your attention to-day, than when I first addressed
you; though, even then, I did not do so without painful
diffidence. For at this moment, even supposing
that in other places it were possible for men to pursue
their ordinary avocations undisturbed by indignation
or pity, here, at least, in the midst of
the deliberative and religious influences of England,
only one subject, I am well assured, can seriously
occupy your thoughts the necessity, namely,
of determining how it has come to pass that, in these
recent days, iniquity the most reckless and monstrous
can be committed unanimously, by men more generous
than ever yet in the world’s history were deceived
into deeds of cruelty; and that prolonged agony of
body and spirit, such as we should shrink from inflicting
willfully on a single criminal, has become the appointed
and accepted portion of unnumbered multitudes of innocent
persons, inhabiting the districts of the world which,
of all others, as it seemed, were best instructed
in the laws of civilization, and most richly invested
with the honor, and indulged in the felicity, of peace.
Believe me, however, the subject of
Art instead of being foreign to these deep
questions of social duty and peril, is so
vitally connected with them, that it would be impossible
for me now to pursue the line of thought in which
I began these lectures, because so ghastly an emphasis
would be given to every sentence by the force of passing
events. It is well, then, that in the plan I
have laid down for your study, we shall now be led
into the examination of technical details, or abstract
conditions of sentiment; so that the hours you spend
with me may be times of repose from heavier thoughts.
But it chances strangely that, in this course of minutely
detailed study, I have first to set before you the
most essential piece of human workmanship, the plow,
at the very moment when (you may see the
announcement in the journals either of yesterday or
the day before) the swords of your soldiers
have been sent for to be sharpened, and not
at all to be beaten into plowshares. I permit
myself, therefore, to remind you of the watchword of
all my earnest writings “Soldiers
of the Plowshare, instead of Soldiers of the Sword,” and
I know it my duty to assert to you that the work we
enter upon to-day is no trivial one, but full of solemn
hope; the hope, namely, that among you there may be
found men wise enough to lead the national passions
towards the arts of peace, instead of the arts of war.
I say, the work “we enter upon,”
because the first four lectures I gave in the spring
were wholly prefatory; and the following three only
defined for you methods of practice. To-day we
begin the systematic analysis and progressive study
of our subject.
2. In general, the three great,
or fine, Arts of Painting, Sculpture, and Architecture,
are thought of as distinct from the lower and more
mechanical formative arts, such as carpentry or pottery.
But we cannot, either verbally, or with any practical
advantage, admit such classification. How are
we to distinguish painting on canvas from painting
on china? or painting on china from painting
on glass? or painting on glass from infusion
of color into any vitreous substance, such as enamel? or
the infusion of color into glass and enamel from the
infusion of color into wool or silk, and weaving of
pictures in tapestry, or patterns in dress? You
will find that although, in ultimately accurate use
of the word, painting must be held to mean only the
laying of a pigment on a surface with a soft instrument;
yet, in broad comparison of the functions of Art,
we must conceive of one and the same great artistic
faculty, as governing every mode of disposing colors
in a permanent relation on, or in, a solid substance;
whether it be by tinting canvas, or dyeing stuffs;
inlaying metals with fused flint, or coating walls
with colored stone.
3. Similarly, the word ’Sculpture,’ though
in ultimate accuracy it is to be limited to the development
of form in hard substances by cutting away portions
of their mass in broad definition, must
be held to signify the reduction of any shapeless
mass of solid matter into an intended shape, whatever
the consistence of the substance, or nature of the
instrument employed; whether we carve a granite mountain,
or a piece of box-wood, and whether we use, for our
forming instrument, ax, or hammer, or chisel, or our
own hands, or water to soften, or fire to fuse; whenever
and however we bring a shapeless thing into shape,
we do so under the laws of the one great art of Sculpture.
4. Having thus broadly defined
painting and sculpture, we shall see that there is,
in the third place, a class of work separated from
both, in a specific manner, and including a great
group of arts which neither, of necessity, tint,
nor for the sake of form merely, shape the
substances they deal with; but construct or arrange
them with a view to the resistance of some external
force. We construct, for instance, a table with
a flat top, and some support of prop, or leg, proportioned
in strength to such weights as the table is intended
to carry. We construct a ship out of planks,
or plates of iron, with reference to certain forces
of impact to be sustained, and of inertia to be overcome;
or we construct a wall or roof with distinct reference
to forces of pressure and oscillation, to be sustained
or guarded against; and, therefore, in every case,
with especial consideration of the strength of our
materials, and the nature of that strength, elastic,
tenacious, brittle, and the like.
Now although this group of arts nearly
always involves the putting of two or more separate
pieces together, we must not define it by that accident.
The blade of an oar is not less formed with reference
to external force than if it were made of many pieces;
and the frame of a boat, whether hollowed out of a
tree-trunk, or constructed of planks nailed together,
is essentially the same piece of art; to be judged
by its buoyancy and capacity of progression.
Still, from the most wonderful piece of all architecture,
the human skeleton, to this simple one, the plowshare,
on which it depends for its subsistence, the putting
of two or more pieces together is curiously necessary
to the perfectness of every fine instrument; and the
peculiar mechanical work of Daedalus, inlaying, becomes
all the more delightful to us in external aspect,
because, as in the jawbone of a Saurian, or the wood
of a bow, it is essential to the finest capacities
of tension and resistance.
5. And observe how unbroken the
ascent from this, the simplest architecture, to the
loftiest. The placing of the timbers in a ship’s
stem, and the laying of the stones in a bridge buttress,
are similar in art to the construction of the plowshare,
differing in no essential point, either in that they
deal with other materials, or because, of the three
things produced, one has to divide earth by advancing
through it, another to divide water by advancing through
it, and the third to divide water which advances against
it. And again, the buttress of a bridge differs
only from that of a cathedral in having less weight
to sustain, and more to resist. We can find no
term in the gradation, from the plowshare to the cathedral
buttress, at which we can set a logical distinction.
6. Thus then we have simply three
divisions of Art one, that of giving colors
to substance; another, that of giving form to it without
question of resistance to force; and the third, that
of giving form or position which will make it capable
of such resistance. All the fine arts are embraced
under these three divisions. Do not think that
it is only a logical or scientific affectation to
mass them together in this manner; it is, on the contrary,
of the first practical importance to understand that
the painter’s faculty, or masterhood over color,
being as subtle as a musician’s over sound,
must be looked to for the government of every operation
in which color is employed; and that, in the same manner,
the appliance of any art whatsoever to minor objects
cannot be right, unless under the direction of a true
master of that art. Under the present system,
you keep your Academician occupied only in producing
tinted pieces of canvas to be shown in frames, and
smooth pieces of marble to be placed in niches; while
you expect your builder or constructor to design colored
patterns in stone and brick, and your china-ware merchant
to keep a separate body of workwomen who can paint
china, but nothing else. By this division of
labor, you ruin all the arts at once. The work
of the Academician becomes mean and effeminate, because
he is not used to treat color on a grand scale and
in rough materials; and your manufactures become base,
because no well-educated person sets hand to them.
And therefore it is necessary to understand, not merely
as a logical statement, but as a practical necessity,
that wherever beautiful color is to be arranged, you
need a Master of Painting; and wherever noble form
is to be given, a Master of Sculpture; and wherever
complex mechanical force is to be resisted; a Master
of Architecture.
7. But over this triple division
there must rule another yet more important. Any
of these three arts may be either imitative of natural
objects or limited to useful appliance. You may
either paint a picture that represents a scene, or
your street door, to keep it from rotting; you may
mold a statue, or a plate; build the resemblance of
a cluster of lotus stalks, or only a square pier.
Generally speaking, Painting and Sculpture will be
imitative, and Architecture merely useful; but there
is a great deal of Sculpture as this crystal
ball, for instance, which is not imitative, and
a great deal of architecture which, to some extent,
is so, as the so-called foils of Gothic apertures;
and for many other reasons you will find it necessary
to keep distinction clear in your minds between the
arts of whatever kind which
are imitative, and produce a resemblance or image of
something which is not present; and those which are
limited to the production of some useful reality,
as the blade of a knife, or the wall of a house.
You will perceive also, as we advance, that sculpture
and painting are indeed in this respect only one art;
and that we shall have constantly to speak and think
of them as simply graphic, whether with chisel
or color, their principal function being to make us,
in the words of Aristotle, “”, “having
capacity and habit of contemplation of the beauty that
is in material things;” while architecture,
and its correlative arts, are to be practiced under
quite other conditions of sentiment.
8. Now it is obvious that so
far as the fine arts consist either in imitation or
mechanical construction, the right judgment of them
must depend on our knowledge of the things they imitate,
and forces they resist: and my function of teaching
here would (for instance) so far resolve itself, either
into demonstration that this painting of a peach
does resemble a peach, or explanation of the way in
which this plowshare (for instance) is shaped so as
to throw the earth aside with least force of thrust.
And in both of these methods of study, though of course
your own diligence must be your chief master, to a
certain extent your Professor of Art can always guide
you securely, and can show you, either that the image
does truly resemble what it attempts to resemble,
or that the structure is rightly prepared for the service
it has to perform. But there is yet another virtue
of fine art which is, perhaps, exactly that about
which you will expect your Professor to teach you
most, and which, on the contrary, is exactly that about
which you must teach yourselves all that it is essential
to learn.
9. I have here in my hand one
of the simplest possible examples of the union of
the graphic and constructive powers, one
of my breakfast plates. Since all the finely
architectural arts, we said, began in the shaping
of the cup and the platter, we will begin, ourselves,
with the platter.
Why has it been made round? For
two structural reasons: first, that the greatest
holding surface may be gathered into the smallest space;
and secondly, that in being pushed past other things
on the table, it may come into least contact with
them.
Next, why has it a rim? For two
other structural reasons: first, that it is convenient
to put salt or mustard upon; but secondly, and chiefly,
that the plate may be easily laid hold of. The
rim is the simplest form of continuous handle.
Farther, to keep it from soiling the
cloth, it will be wise to put this ridge beneath,
round the bottom; for as the rim is the simplest possible
form of continuous handle, so this is the simplest
form of continuous leg. And we get the section
given beneath the figure for the essential one of
a rightly made platter.
10. Thus far our art has been
strictly utilitarian, having respect to conditions
of collision, of carriage, and of support. But
now, on the surface of our piece of pottery, here
are various bands and spots of color which are presumably
set there to make it pleasanter to the eye. Six
of the spots, seen closely, you discover are intended
to represent flowers. These then have as distinctly
a graphic purpose as the other properties of the plate
have an architectural one, and the first critical
question we have to ask about them is, whether they
are like roses or not. I will anticipate what
I have to say in subsequent Lectures so far as to
assure you that, if they are to be like roses at all,
the liker they can be, the better. Do not suppose,
as many people will tell you, that because this is
a common manufactured article, your roses on it are
the better for being ill-painted, or half-painted.
If they had been painted by the same hand that did
this peach, the plate would have been all the better
for it; but, as it chanced, there was no hand such
as William Hunt’s to paint them, and their graphic
power is not distinguished. In any case, however,
that graphic power must have been subordinate to their
effect as pink spots, while the band of green-blue
round the plate’s edge, and the spots of gold,
pretend to no graphic power at all, but are meaningless
spaces of color or metal. Still less have they
any mechanical office: they add nowise to the
serviceableness of the plate; and their agreeableness,
if they possess any, depends, therefore, neither on
any imitative, nor any structural, character; but
on some inherent pleasantness in themselves, either
of mere colors to the eye, (as of taste to the tongue,)
or in the placing of those colors in relations which
obey some mental principle of order, or physical principle
of harmony.
11. These abstract relations
and inherent pleasantnesses, whether in space, number,
or time, and whether of colors or sounds, form what
we may properly term the musical or harmonic element
in every art; and the study of them is an entirely
separate science. It is the branch of art-philosophy
to which the word ‘aesthetics’ should be
strictly limited, being the inquiry into the nature
of things that in themselves are pleasant to the human
senses or instincts, though they represent nothing,
and serve for nothing, their only service being
their pleasantness. Thus it is the province of
aesthetics to tell you, (if you did not know it before,)
that the taste and color of a peach are pleasant,
and to ascertain, if it be ascertainable, (and you
have any curiosity to know,) why they are so.
12. The information would, I
presume, to most of you, be gratuitous. If it
were not, and you chanced to be in a sick state of
body in which you disliked peaches, it would be, for
the time, to you false information, and, so far as
it was true of other people, to you useless. Nearly
the whole study of aesthetics is in like manner either
gratuitous or useless. Either you like the right
things without being recommended to do so, or, if
you dislike them, your mind cannot be changed by lectures
on the laws of taste. You recollect the story
of Thackeray, provoked, as he was helping himself
to strawberries, by a young coxcomb’s telling
him that “he never took fruit or sweets.”
“That,” replied, or is said to have replied,
Thackeray, “is because you are a sot, and a glutton.”
And the whole science of aesthetics is, in the depth
of it, expressed by one passage of Goethe’s
in the end of the second part of Faust; the
notable one that follows the song of the Lemures,
when the angels enter to dispute with the fiends for
the soul of Faust. They enter singing “Pardon
to sinners and life to the dust.” Méphistophélès
hears them first, and exclaims to his troop, “Discord
I hear, and filthy jingling” “Mis-toene
hoere ich: garstiges Geklimper.”
This, you see, is the extreme of bad taste in music.
Presently the angelic host begin strewing roses, which
discomfits the diabolic crowd altogether. Méphistophélès
in vain calls to them “What do you
duck and shrink for is that proper hellish
behavior? Stand fast, and let them strew” “Was
duckt und zuckt ihr; ist das Hellen-brauch?
So haltet stand, und lässt sie
streuen.” There you have also, the
extreme, of bad taste in sight and smell. And
in the whole passage is a brief embodiment for you
of the ultimate fact that all aesthetics depend on
the health of soul and body, and the proper exercise
of both, not only through years, but generations.
Only by harmony of both collateral and successive lives
can the great doctrine of the Muses be received which
enables men “,” “to
have pleasure rightly;” and there is no other
definition of the beautiful, nor of any subject of
delight to the aesthetic faculty, than that it is
what one noble spirit has created, seen and felt by
another of similar or equal nobility. So much
as there is in you of ox, or of swine, perceives no
beauty, and creates none: what is human in you,
in exact proportion to the perfectness of its humanity,
can create it, and receive.
13. Returning now to the very
elementary form in which the appeal to our aesthetic
virtue is made in our breakfast-plate, you notice that
there are two distinct kinds of pleasantness attempted.
One by hues of color; the other by proportions of
space. I have called these the musical elements
of the arts relating to sight; and there are indeed
two complete sciences, one of the combinations of
color, and the other of the combinations of line and
form, which might each of them separately engage us
in as intricate study as that of the science of music.
But of the two, the science of color is, in the Greek
sense, the more musical, being one of the divisions
of the Apolline power; and it is so practically educational,
that if we are not using the faculty for color to
discipline nations, they will infallibly use it themselves
as a means of corruption. Both music and color
are naturally influences of peace; but in the war
trumpet, and the war shield, in the battle song and
battle standard, they have concentrated by beautiful
imagination the cruel passions of men; and there is
nothing in all the Divina Commedia of history more
grotesque, yet more frightful, than the fact that,
from the almost fabulous period when the insanity
and impiety of war wrote themselves in the symbols
of the shields of the Seven against Thebes, colors
have been the sign and stimulus of the most furious
and fatal passions that have rent the nations:
blue against green, in the decline of the Roman Empire;
black against white, in that of Florence; red against
white, in the wars of the Royal houses in England;
and at this moment, red against white, in the contest
of anarchy and loyalty, in all the world.
14. On the other hand, the directly
ethical influence of color in the sky, the trees,
flowers, and colored creatures round us, and in our
own various arts massed under the one name of painting,
is so essential and constant that we cease to recognize
it, because we are never long enough altogether deprived
of it to feel our need; and the mental diseases induced
by the influence of corrupt color are as little suspected,
or traced to their true source, as the bodily weaknesses
resulting from atmospheric miasmata.
15. The second musical science
which belongs peculiarly to sculpture, (and to painting,
so far as it represents form,) consists in the disposition
of beautiful masses. That is to say, beautiful
surfaces limited by beautiful lines. Beautiful
surfaces, observe; and remember what is noted
in my Fourth Lecture of the difference between a space
and a mass. If you have at any time examined
carefully, or practiced from, the drawings of shells
placed in your copying series, you cannot but have
felt the difference in the grace between the aspects
of the same line, when inclosing a rounded or unrounded
space. The exact science of sculpture is that
of the relations between outline and the solid form
it limits; and it does not matter whether that relation
be indicated by drawing or carving, so long as the
expression of solid form is the mental purpose; it
is the science always of the beauty of relation in
three dimensions. To take the simplest possible
line of continuous limit the circle:
the flat disk inclosed by it may indeed be made an
element of decoration, though a very meager one; but
its relative mass, the ball, being gradated in three
dimensions, is always delightful. Here is
at once the simplest, and, in mere patient mechanism,
the most skillful, piece of sculpture I can possibly
show you, a piece of the purest rock-crystal,
chiseled, (I believe, by mere toil of hand,) into
a perfect sphere. Imitating nothing, constructing
nothing; sculpture for sculpture’s sake of purest
natural substance into simplest primary form.
16. Again. Out of the nacre
of any mussel or oyster shell you might cut, at your
pleasure, any quantity of small flat circular disks
of the prettiest color and luster. To some extent,
such tinsel or foil of shell is used pleasantly
for decoration. But the mussel or oyster becoming
itself an unwilling modeler, agglutinates its juice
into three dimensions, and the fact of the surface
being now geometrically gradated, together with the
savage instinct of attributing value to what is difficult
to obtain, make the little boss so precious in men’s
sight, that wise eagerness of search for the kingdom
of heaven can be likened to their eagerness of search
for it; and the gates of Paradise can be no
otherwise rendered so fair to their poor intelligence,
as by telling them that every gate was of “one
pearl.”
17. But take note here.
We have just seen that the sum of the perceptive faculty
is expressed in these words of Aristotle’s, “to
take pleasure rightly” or straightly. Now, it is not possible to
do the direct opposite of that, to take
pleasure iniquitously or obliquely or, more
than you do in enjoying a thing because your neighbor
cannot get it. You may enjoy a thing legitimately
because it is rare, and cannot be seen often (as you
do a fine aurora, or a sunset, or an unusually lovely
flower); that is Nature’s way of stimulating
your attention. But if you enjoy it because your
neighbor cannot have it, and, remember,
all value attached to pearls more than glass beads,
is merely and purely for that cause, then
you rejoice through the worst of idolâtries,
covetousness; and neither arithmetic, nor writing,
nor any other so-called essential of education, is
now so vitally necessary to the population of Europe,
as such acquaintance with the principles of intrinsic
value, as may result in the iconoclasm of jewelry;
and in the clear understanding that we are not, in
that instinct, civilized, but yet remain wholly savage,
so far as we care for display of this selfish kind.
You think, perhaps, I am quitting
my subject, and proceeding, as it is too often with
appearance of justice alleged against me, into irrelevant
matter. Pardon me; the end, not only of these
Lectures, but of my whole Professorship, would be
accomplished, and far more than that, if
only the English nation could be made to understand
that the beauty which is indeed to be a joy forever,
must be a joy for all; and that though the idolatry
may not have been wholly divine which sculptured gods,
the idolatry is wholly diabolic, which, for vulgar
display, sculptures diamonds.
18. To go back to the point under
discussion. A pearl, or a glass bead, may owe
its pleasantness in some degree to its luster as well
as to its roundness. But a mere and simple ball
of unpolished stone is enough for sculpturesque value.
You may have noticed that the quatrefoil used in the
Ducal Palace of Venice owes its complete loveliness
in distant effect to the finishing of its cusps.
The extremity of the cusp is a mere ball of Istrian
marble; and consider how subtle the faculty of sight
must be, since it recognizes at any distance, and is
gratified by, the mystery of the termination of cusp
obtained by the gradated light on the ball.
In that Venetian tracery this simplest
element of sculptured form is used sparingly, as the
most precious that can be employed to finish the façade.
But alike in our own, and the French, central Gothic,
the ball-flower is lavished on every line and
in your St. Mary’s spire, and the Salisbury
spire, and the towers of Notre Dame of Paris, the rich
pleasantness of decoration, indeed, their
so-called ’decorative style,’ consists
only in being daintily beset with stone balls.
It is true the balls are modified into dim likeness
of flowers; but do you trace the resemblance to the
rose in their distant, which is their intended, effect?
19. But, farther, let the ball
have motion; then the form it generates will be that
of a cylinder. You have, perhaps, thought that
pure early English architecture depended for its charm
on visibility of construction. It depends for
its charm altogether on the abstract harmony of groups
of cylinders, arbitrarily bent into moldings, and
arbitrarily associated as shafts, having no real
relation to construction whatsoever, and a theoretical
relation so subtle that none of us had seen it till
Professor Willis worked it out for us.
20. And now, proceeding to analysis
of higher sculpture, you may have observed the importance
I have attached to the porch of San Zenone, at Verona,
by making it, among your standards, the first of the
group which is to illustrate the system of sculpture
and architecture founded on faith in a future life.
That porch, fortunately represented in the photograph under a clear
and pleasant light, furnishes you with examples of
sculpture of every kind, from the flattest incised
bas-relief to solid statues, both in marble and bronze.
And the two points I have been pressing upon you are
conclusively exhibited here, namely, (1)
that sculpture is essentially the production of a
pleasant bossiness or roundness of surface; (2) that
the pleasantness of that bossy condition to the eye
is irrespective of imitation on one side, and of structure
on the other.
21. (1.) Sculpture is essentially
the production of a pleasant bossiness or roundness
of surface.
If you look from some distance at
these two engravings of Greek coins, you will find the relief on each
of them simplifies itself into a pearl-like portion
of a sphere, with exquisitely gradated light on its
surface. When you look at them nearer, you will
see that each smaller portion into which they are
divided cheek, or brow, or leaf, or tress
of hair resolves itself also into a rounded
or undulated surface, pleasant by gradation of light.
Every several surface is delightful in itself, as
a shell, or a tuft of rounded moss, or the bossy masses
of distant forest would be. That these intricately
modulated masses present some resemblance to a girl’s
face, such as the Syracusans imagined that of the
water-goddess Arethusa, is entirely a secondary matter;
the primary condition is that the masses shall be
beautifully rounded, and disposed with due discretion
and order.
22. (2.) It is difficult for you,
at first, to feel this order and beauty of surface,
apart from the imitation. But you can see there
is a pretty disposition of, and relation between,
the projections of a fir-cone, though the studded
spiral imitates nothing. Order exactly the same
in kind, only much more complex; and an abstract beauty
of surface rendered definite by increase and decline
of light (for every curve of surface has
its own luminous law, and the light and shade on a
parabolic solid differs, specifically, from that on
an elliptical or spherical one) it is the
essential business of the sculptor to obtain; as it
is the essential business of a painter to get good
color, whether he imitates anything or not. At
a distance from the picture, or carving, where the
things represented become absolutely unintelligible,
we must yet be able to say, at a glance, “That
is good painting, or good carving.”
And you will be surprised to find,
when you try the experiment, how much the eye must
instinctively judge in this manner. Take the front
of San Zenone. You will find
it impossible, without a lens, to distinguish in the
bronze gates, and in great part of the wall, anything
that their bosses represent. You cannot tell whether
the sculpture is of men, animals, or trees; only you
feel it to be composed of pleasant projecting masses;
you acknowledge that both gates and wall are, somehow,
delightfully roughened; and only afterwards, by slow
degrees, can you make out what this roughness means;
nay, though here one of
the bronze plates of the gate to a scale, which gives
you the same advantage as if you saw it quite close,
in the reality, you may still be obliged
to me for the information that this boss represents
the Madonna asleep in her little bed; and this smaller
boss, the Infant Christ in His; and this at the top,
a cloud with an angel coming out of it; and these
jagged bosses, two of the Three Kings, with their
crowns on, looking up to the star, (which is intelligible
enough, I admit); but what this straggling, three-legged
boss beneath signifies, I suppose neither you nor I
can tell, unless it be the shepherd’s dog, who
has come suddenly upon the Kings with their crowns
on, and is greatly startled at them.
23. Farther, and much more definitely,
the pleasantness of the surface decoration is independent
of structure; that is to say, of any architectural
requirement of stability. The greater part of
the sculpture here is exclusively ornamentation of
a flat wall, or of door-paneling; only a small portion
of the church front is thus treated, and the sculpture
has no more to do with the form of the building than
a piece of lace veil would have, suspended beside
its gates on a festal day: the proportions of
shaft and arch might be altered in a hundred different
ways without diminishing their stability; and the pillars
would stand more safely on the ground than on the backs
of these carved animals.
24. I wish you especially to
notice these points, because the false theory that
ornamentation should be merely decorated structure
is so pretty and plausible, that it is likely to take
away your attention from the far more important abstract
conditions of design. Structure should never
be contradicted, and in the best buildings it is pleasantly
exhibited and enforced: in this very porch the
joints of every stone are visible, and you will find
me in the Fifth Lecture insisting on this clearness
of its anatomy as a merit; yet so independent is the
mechanical structure of the true design, that when
I begin my Lectures on Architecture, the first building
I shall give you as a standard will be one in which
the structure is wholly concealed. It will be
the Baptistery of Florence, which is, in reality,
as much a buttressed chapel with a vaulted roof, as
the Chapter House of York; but round it,
in order to conceal that buttressed structure, (not
to decorate, observe, but to conceal,) a flat
external wall is raised; simplifying the whole to
a mere hexagonal box, like a wooden piece of Tunbridge
ware, on the surface of which the eye and intellect
are to be interested by the relations of dimension
and curve between pieces of incrusting marble of different
colors, which have no more to do with the real make
of the building than the diaper of a Harlequin’s
jacket has to do with his bones.
25. The sense of abstract proportion,
on which the enjoyment of such a piece of art entirely
depends, is one of the aesthetic faculties which nothing
can develop but time and education. It belongs
only to highly trained nations; and, among them, to
their most strictly refined classes, though the germs
of it are found, as part of their innate power, in
every people capable of art. It has for the most
part vanished at present from the English mind, in
consequence of our eager desire for excitement, and
for the kind of splendor that exhibits wealth, careless
of dignity; so that, I suppose, there are very few
now even of our best trained Londoners who know the
difference between the design of Whitehall and that
of any modern club-house in Pall Mall. The order
and harmony which, in his enthusiastic account of
the Theater of Epidaurus, Pausanias insists on before
beauty, can only be recognized by stern order and
harmony in our daily lives; and the perception of them
is as little to be compelled, or taught suddenly,
as the laws of still finer choice in the conception
of dramatic incident which regulate poetic sculpture.
26. And now, at last, I think,
we can sketch out the subject before us in a clear
light. We have a structural art, divine and human,
of which the investigation comes under the general
term Anatomy; whether the junctions or joints be in
mountains, or in branches of trees, or in buildings,
or in bones of animals. We have next a musical
art, falling into two distinct divisions one
using colors, the other masses, for its elements of
composition; lastly, we have an imitative art, concerned
with the representation of the outward appearances
of things. And, for many reasons, I think it
best to begin with imitative Sculpture; that being
defined as the art which, by the musical disposition
of masses, imitates anything of which the imitation
is justly pleasant to us; and does so in accordance
with structural laws having due reference to the materials
employed.
So that you see our task will involve
the immediate inquiry what the things are of which
the imitation is justly pleasant to us: what,
in few words, if we are to be occupied
in the making of graven images, we ought
to like to make images of. Secondly, after
having determined its subject, what degree of imitation
or likeness we ought to desire in our graven image;
and, lastly, under what limitations demanded by structure
and material, such likeness may be obtained.
These inquiries I shall endeavor to
pursue with you to some practical conclusion, in my
next four Lectures; and in the sixth, I will briefly
sketch the actual facts that have taken place in the
development of sculpture by the two greatest schools
of it that hitherto have existed in the world.
27. The tenor of our next Lecture,
then, must be an inquiry into the real nature of Idolatry;
that is to say, the invention and service of Idols:
and, in the interval, may I commend to your own thoughts
this question, not wholly irrelevant, yet which I
cannot pursue; namely, whether the God to whom we
have so habitually prayed for deliverance “from
battle, murder, and sudden death,” is
indeed, seeing that the present state of Christendom
is the result of a thousand years’ praying to
that effect, “as the gods of the heathen who
were but idols;” or whether (and
observe, one or other of these things must be
true) whether our prayers to Him have been,
by this much, worse than Idolatry; that
heathen prayer was true prayer to false gods; and our
prayers have been false prayers to the True One?