LIKENESS
November, 1870.
109. You were probably vexed,
and tired, towards the close of my last Lecture, by
the time it took us to arrive at the apparently simple
conclusion that sculpture must only represent organic
form, and the strength of life in its contest with
matter. But it is no small thing to have that
“” fixed in
your minds, as the one necessary sign by which you
are to recognize right sculpture; and, believe me,
you will find it the best of all things, if you can
take for yourselves the saying from the lips of the
Athenian maids, in its entirety, and say also. I proceed to-day
into the practical appliance of this apparently speculative,
but in reality imperative, law.
110. You observe, I have hitherto
spoken of the power of Athena, as over painting no
less than sculpture. But her rule over both arts
is only so far as they are zoographic; representative,
that is to say, of animal life, or of such order and
discipline among other elements, as may invigorate
and purify it. Now there is a speciality of the
art of painting beyond this, namely, the representation
of phenomena of color and shadow, as such, without
question of the nature of the things that receive
them. I am now accordingly obliged to speak of
sculpture and painting as distinct arts: but
the laws which bind sculpture, bind no less the painting
of the higher schools, which has, for its main purpose,
the showing beauty in human or animal form; and which
is therefore placed by the Greeks equally under the
rule of Athena, as the Spirit, first, of Life, and
then of Wisdom in conduct.
111. First, I say, you are to
‘see Pallas’ in all such work, as the
Queen of Life; and the practical law which follows
from this, is one of enormous range and importance,
namely, that nothing must be represented by sculpture,
external to any living form, which does not help to
enforce or illustrate the conception of life.
Both dress and armor may be made to do this, by great
sculptors, and are continually so used by the greatest.
One of the essential distinctions between the Athenian
and Florentine schools is dependent on their treatment
of drapery in this respect; an Athenian always sets
it to exhibit the action of the body, by flowing with
it, or over it, or from it, so as to illustrate both
its form and gesture; a Florentine, on the contrary,
always uses his drapery to conceal or disguise the
forms of the body, and exhibit mental emotion; but
both use it to enhance the life, either of the body
or soul; Donatello and Michael Angelo, no less than
the sculptors of Gothic chivalry, ennoble armor in
the same way; but base sculptors carve drapery and
armor for the sake of their folds and picturesqueness
only, and forget the body beneath. The rule is
so stern, that all delight in mere incidental beauty,
which painting often triumphs in, is wholly forbidden
to sculpture; for instance, in painting
the branch of a tree, you may rightly represent and
enjoy the lichens and moss on it, but a sculptor must
not touch one of them: they are inessential to
the tree’s life, he must give the
flow and bending of the branch only, else he does
not enough ‘see Pallas’ in it.
Or, to take a higher instance, here
is an exquisite little painted poem, by Edward Frere;
a cottage interior, one of the thousands which within
the last two months have been laid desolate in
unhappy France. Every accessory in the painting
is of value the fireside, the tiled floor,
the vegetables lying upon it, and the basket hanging
from the roof. But not one of these accessories
would have been admissible in sculpture. You
must carve nothing but what has life. “Why?”
you probably feel instantly inclined to ask me. You
see the principle we have got, instead of being blunt
or useless, is such an edged tool that you are startled
the moment I apply it. “Must we refuse every
pleasant accessory and picturesque detail, and petrify
nothing but living creatures?” Even so:
I would not assert it on my own authority. It
is the Greeks who say it, but whatever they say of
sculpture, be assured, is true.
112. That then is the first law you
must see Pallas as the Lady of Life; the second is,
you must see her as the Lady of Wisdom; or and this is the chief matter
of all. I cannot but think that, after the considerations
into which we have now entered, you will find more
interest than hitherto in comparing the statements
of Aristotle, in the Ethics, with those of Plato in
the Polity, which are authoritative as Greek definitions
of goodness in art, and which you may safely hold
authoritative as constant definitions of it. You
remember, doubtless, that the,
or, for the sake of
which Phidias is called as
a sculpture, and Polyclitus as an image-maker, Eth
6. 7. (the opposition is both between ideal and portrait
sculpture, and between working in stone and bronze),
consists in the “,” “the mental apprehension
of the things that are most honorable in their nature.”
Therefore, what is indeed most lovely, the true image-maker
will most love; and what is most hateful, he will
most hate; and in all things discern the best and
strongest part of them, and represent that essentially,
or, if the opposite of that, then with manifest detestation
and horror. That is his art wisdom; the knowledge
of good and evil, and the love of good, so that you
may discern, even in his representation of the vilest
thing, his acknowledgment of what redemption is possible
for it, or latent power exists in it; and, contrariwise,
his sense of its present misery. But, for the
most part, he will idolize, and force us also to idolize,
whatever is living, and virtuous, and victoriously
right; opposing to it in some definite mode the image
of the conquered.
113. This is generally true of
both the great arts; but in severity and precision,
true of sculpture. To return to our illustration:
this poor little girl was more interesting to Edward
Frere, he being a painter, because she was poorly
dressed, and wore these clumsy shoes, and old red
cap, and patched gown. May we sculpture her so?
No We may sculpture her naked, if we like; but
not in rags.
But if we may not put her into marble
in rags, may we give her a pretty frock with ribbons
and flounces to it, and put her into marble in that?
No We may put her simplest peasant’s dress,
so it be perfect and orderly, into marble; anything
finer than that would be more dishonorable in the
eyes of Athena than rags. If she were a French
princess, you might carve her embroidered robe and
diadem; if she were Joan of Arc, you might carve her
armor for then these also would be “,” not otherwise.
114. Is not this an edge-tool
we have got hold of, unawares? and a subtle one too;
so delicate and cimeter-like in decision. For
note that even Joan of Arc’s armor must
be only sculptured, if she has it on; it is
not the honorableness or beauty of it that are enough,
but the direct bearing of it by her body. You
might be deeply, even pathetically, interested by
looking at a good knight’s dinted coat of mail,
left in his desolate hall. May you sculpture
it where it hangs? No; the helmet for his pillow,
if you will no more.
You see we did not do our dull work
for nothing in last Lecture. I define what we
have gained once more, and then we will enter on our
new ground.
115. The proper subject of sculpture,
we have determined, is the spiritual power seen in
the form of any living thing, and so represented as
to give evidence that the sculptor has loved the good
of it and hated the evil.
“So represented,”
we say; but how is that to be done? Why should
it not be represented, if possible, just as it is
seen? What mode or limit of representation may
we adopt? We are to carve things that have life; shall
we try so to imitate them that they may indeed seem
living, or only half living, and like stone
instead of flesh?
It will simplify this question if
I show you three examples of what the Greeks actually
did: three typical pieces of their sculpture,
in order of perfection.
116. And now, observe that in
all our historical work, I will endeavor to do, myself,
what I have asked you to do in your drawing exercises;
namely, to outline firmly in the beginning, and then
fill in the detail more minutely. I will give
you first, therefore, in a symmetrical form, absolutely
simple and easily remembered, the large chronology
of the Greek school; within that unforgettable scheme
we will place, as we discover them, the minor relations
of arts and times.
I number the nine centuries before
Christ thus, upwards, and divide them into three groups
of three each.
{
A. ARCHAIC. {
{7
-----
{
B. BEST. {
{4
-----
{
C. CORRUPT. {
{1
Then the ninth, eighth, and seventh
centuries are the period of archaic Greek art, steadily
progressive wherever it existed.
The sixth, fifth, and fourth are the
period of Central Greek art; the fifth, or central,
century producing the finest. That is easily
recollected by the battle of Marathon. And the
third, second, and first centuries are the period
of steady decline.
Learn this A B C thoroughly, and mark,
for yourselves, what you, at present, think the vital
events in each century. As you know more, you
will think other events the vital ones; but the best
historical knowledge only approximates to true thought
in that matter; only be sure that what is truly vital
in the character which governs events, is always expressed
by the art of the century; so that if you could interpret
that art rightly, the better part of your task in reading
history would be done to your hand.
117. It is generally impossible
to date with precision art of the archaic period often
difficult to date even that of the central three hundred
years. I will not weary you with futile minor
divisions of time; here are three coins
roughly, but decisively, characteristic of the three
ages. The first is an early coin of Tarentum.
The city was founded, as you know, by the Spartan Phalanthus,
late in the eighth century. I believe the head
is meant for that of Apollo Archegetes; it may however
be Taras, the son of Poseidon; it is no matter to
us at present whom it is meant for, but the fact that
we cannot know, is itself of the greatest import.
We cannot say, with any certainty, unless by discovery
of some collateral evidence, whether this head is
intended for that of a god, or demigod, or a mortal
warrior. Ought not that to disturb some of your
thoughts respecting Greek idealism? Farther,
if by investigation we discover that the head is meant
for that of Phalanthus, we shall know nothing of the
character of Phalanthus from the face; for there is
no portraiture at this early time.
118. The second coin is of AEnus
in Macedonia; probably of the fifth or early fourth
century, and entirely characteristic of the central
period. This we know to represent the face of
a god Hermes. The third coin is a
king’s, not a city’s. I will not tell
you, at this moment, what king’s; but only that
it is a late coin of the third period, and that it
is as distinct in purpose as the coin of Tarentum
is obscure. We know of this coin, that it represents
no god nor demigod, but a mere mortal; and we know
precisely, from the portrait, what that mortal’s
face was like.
119. A glance at the three coins,
as they are set side by side, will now show you the
main differences in the three great Greek styles.
The archaic coin is sharp and hard; every line decisive
and numbered, set unhesitatingly in its place; nothing
is wrong, though everything incomplete, and, to us
who have seen finer art, ugly. The central coin
is as decisive and clear in arrangement of masses,
but its contours are completely rounded and finished.
There is no character in its execution so prominent
that you can give an epithet to the style. It
is not hard, it is not soft, it is not delicate, it
is not coarse, it is not grotesque, it is not beautiful;
and I am convinced, unless you had been told that
this is fine central Greek art, you would have seen
nothing at all in it to interest you. Do not
let yourselves be anywise forced into admiring it;
there is, indeed, nothing more here than an approximately
true rendering of a healthy youthful face, without
the slightest attempt to give an expression of activity,
cunning, nobility, or any other attribute of the Mercurial
mind. Extreme simplicity, unpretending vigor
of work, which claims no admiration either for minuteness
or dexterity, and suggests no idea of effort at all;
refusal of extraneous ornament, and perfectly arranged
disposition of counted masses in a sequent order,
whether in the beads, or the ringlets of hair; this
is all you have to be pleased with; neither will you
ever find, in the best Greek Art, more. You might
at first suppose that the chain of beads round the
cap was an extraneous ornament; but I have little
doubt that it is as definitely the proper fillet for
the head of Hermes, as the olive for Zeus, or corn
for Triptolemus. The cap or petasus cannot have
expanded edges; there is no room for them on the coin;
these must be understood, therefore; but the nature
of the cloud-petasus is explained by edging it with
beads, representing either dew or hail. The shield
of Athena often bears white pellets for hail, in like
manner.
120. The third coin will, I think,
at once strike you by what we moderns should call
its ‘vigor of character.’ You may
observe also that the features are finished with great
care and subtlety, but at the cost of simplicity and
breadth. But the essential difference between
it and the central art, is its disorder in design you
see the locks of hair cannot be counted any longer they
are entirely disheveled and irregular. Now the
individual character may, or may not, be a sign of
decline; but the licentiousness, the casting loose
of the masses in the design, is an infallible one.
The effort at portraiture is good for art if the men
to be portrayed are good men, not otherwise. In
the instance before you, the head is that of Mithridates
VI. of Pontus, who had, indeed, the good qualities
of being a linguist and a patron of the arts; but,
as you will remember, murdered, according to report,
his mother, certainly his brother, certainly his wives
and sisters, I have not counted how many of his children,
and from a hundred to a hundred and fifty thousand
persons besides; these last in a single day’s
massacre. The effort to represent this kind of
person is not by any means a method of study from
life ultimately beneficial to art.
121. This, however, is not the
point I have to urge to-day. What I want you
to observe is, that though the master of the great
time does not attempt portraiture, he does
attempt animation. And as far as his means will
admit, he succeeds in making the face you
might almost think vulgarly animated; as
like a real face, literally, ’as it can stare.’
Yes: and its sculptor meant it to be so; and that
was what Phidias meant his Jupiter to be, if he could
manage it. Not, indeed, to be taken for Zeus
himself; and yet, to be as like a living Zeus as art
could make it. Perhaps you think he tried to make
it look living only for the sake of the mob, and would
not have tried to do so for connoisseurs. Pardon
me; for real connoisseurs he would, and did; and herein
consists a truth which belongs to all the arts, and
which I will at once drive home in your minds, as
firmly as I can.
122. All second-rate artists (and
remember, the second-rate ones are a loquacious multitude,
while the great come only one or two in a century;
and then, silently) all second-rate artists
will tell you that the object of fine art is not resemblance,
but some kind of abstraction more refined than reality.
Put that out of your heads at once. The object
of the great Resemblant Arts is, and always has been,
to resemble; and to resemble as closely as possible.
It is the function of a good portrait to set the man
before you in habit as he lived, and I would we had
a few more that did so. It is the function of
a good landscape to set the scene before you in its
reality; to make you, if it may be, think the clouds
are flying, and the streams foaming. It is the
function of the best sculptor the true
Daedalus to make stillness look like breathing,
and marble look like flesh.
123. And in all great times of
art, this purpose is as naively expressed as it is
steadily held. All the talk about abstraction
belongs to periods of decadence. In living times,
people see something living that pleases them; and
they try to make it live forever, or to make something
as like it as possible, that will last forever.
They paint their statues, and inlay the eyes with
jewels, and set real crowns on the heads; they finish,
in their pictures, every thread of embroidery, and
would fain, if they could, draw every leaf upon the
trees. And their only verbal expression of conscious
success is that they have made their work ‘look
real.’
124. You think all that very
wrong. So did I, once; but it was I that was
wrong. A long time ago, before ever I had seen
Oxford, I painted a picture of the Lake of Como, for
my father. It was not at all like the Lake of
Como; but I thought it rather the better for that.
My father differed with me; and objected particularly
to a boat with a red and yellow awning, which I had
put into the most conspicuous corner of my drawing.
I declared this boat to be ‘necessary to the
composition.’ My father not the less objected,
that he had never seen such a boat, either at Como
or elsewhere; and suggested that if I would make the
lake look a little more like water, I should be under
no necessity of explaining its nature by the presence
of floating objects. I thought him at the time
a very simple person for his pains; but have since
learned, and it is the very gist of all practical
matters, which, as Professor of Fine Art, I have now
to tell you, that the great point in painting a lake
is to get it to look like water.
125. So far, so good. We
lay it down for a first principle that our graphic
art, whether painting or sculpture, is to produce something
which shall look as like Nature as possible. But
now we must go one step farther, and say that it is
to produce what shall look like Nature to people who
know what Nature is like! You see this is at once
a great restriction, as well as a great exaltation
of our aim. Our business is not to deceive the
simple; but to deceive the wise! Here, for instance,
is a modern Italian print, representing, to the best
of its power, St. Cecilia, in a brilliantly realistic
manner. And the fault of the work is not in its
earnest endeavor to show St. Cecilia in habit as she
lived, but in that the effort could only be successful
with persons unaware of the habit St. Cecilia lived
in. And this condition of appeal only to the
wise increases the difficulty of imitative resemblance
so greatly, that, with only average skill or materials,
we must surrender all hope of it, and be content with
an imperfect representation, true as far as it reaches,
and such as to excite the imagination of a wise beholder
to complete it; though falling very far short of what
either he or we should otherwise have desired.
For instance, here is a suggestion, by Sir Joshua
Reynolds, of the general appearance of a British Judge, requiring
the imagination of a very wise beholder indeed to fill
it up, or even at first to discover what it is meant
for. Nevertheless, it is better art than the
Italian St. Cecilia, because the artist, however little
he may have done to represent his knowledge, does,
indeed, know altogether what a Judge is like, and appeals
only to the criticism of those who know also.
126. There must be, therefore,
two degrees of truth to be looked for in the good
graphic arts; one, the commonest, which, by any partial
or imperfect sign, conveys to you an idea which you
must complete for yourself; and the other, the finest,
a representation so perfect as to leave you nothing
to be farther accomplished by this independent exertion;
but to give you the same feeling of possession and
presence which you would experience from the natural
object itself. For instance of the first, in
this representation of a rainbow, the artist has
no hope that, by the black lines of engraving, he
can deceive you into any belief of the rainbow’s
being there, but he gives indication enough of what
he intends, to enable you to supply the rest of the
idea yourself, providing always you know beforehand
what a rainbow is like. But in this drawing of
the falls of Terni, the painter has strained his
skill to the utmost to give an actually deceptive
resemblance of the iris, dawning and fading among
the foam. So far as he has not actually deceived
you, it is not because he would not have done so if
he could; but only because his colors and science
have fallen short of his desire. They have fallen
so little short, that, in a good light, you may all
but believe the foam, and the sunshine are drifting
and changing among the rocks.
127. And after looking a little
while, you will begin to regret that they are not
so: you will feel that, lovely as the drawing
is, you would like far better to see the real place,
and the goats skipping among the rocks, and the spray
floating above the fall. And this is the true
sign of the greatest art to part voluntarily
with its greatness; to make itself
poor and unnoticed; but so to exalt and set forth its
theme, that you may be fain to see the theme instead
of it. So that you have never enough admired
a great workman’s doing, till you have begun
to despise it. The best homage that could be
paid to the Athena of Phidias would be to desire rather
to see the living goddess; and the loveliest Madonnas
of Christian art fall short of their due power, if
they do not make their beholders sick at heart to
see the living Virgin.
128. We have then, for our requirement
of the finest art, (sculpture, or anything else,)
that it shall be so like the thing it represents as
to please those who best know or can conceive the
original; and, if possible, please them deceptively its
final triumph being to deceive even the wise; and
(the Greeks thought) to please even the Immortals,
who were so wise as to be undeceivable. So that
you get the Greek, thus far entirely true, idea of
perfectness in sculpture, expressed to you by what
Phalaris says, at first sight of the bull of Perilaus,
“It only wanted motion and bellowing to seem
alive; and as soon as I saw it, I cried out, it ought
to be sent to the god,” to Apollo,
for only he, the undeceivable, could thoroughly understand
such sculpture, and perfectly delight in it.
129. And with this expression
of the Greek ideal of sculpture, I wish you to join
the early Italian, summed in a single line by Dante “non
vide me’ di me, chi vide ’l vero.”
Read the twelfth canto of the Purgatory, and learn
that whole passage by heart; and if ever you chance
to go to Pistoja, look at La Robbia’s colored
porcelain bas-reliefs of the seven works of Mercy
on the front of the hospital there; and note especially
the faces of the two sick men one at the
point of death, and the other in the first peace and
long-drawn breathing of health after fever and
you will know what Dante meant by the preceding line,
“Morti li morti, e i vivi paren vivi.”
130. But now, may we not ask
farther, is it impossible for art such as
this, prepared for the wise, to please the simple also?
Without entering on the awkward questions of degree,
how many the wise can be, or how much men should know,
in order to be rightly called wise, may we not conceive
an art to be possible, which would deceive everybody,
or everybody worth deceiving? I showed you at
my First Lecture, a little ringlet of Japan ivory,
as a type of elementary bas-relief touched with color;
and in your rudimentary series you have a drawing,
by Mr. Burgess, of one of the little fishes enlarged,
with every touch of the chisel facsimiled on the more
visible scale; and showing the little black bead inlaid
for the eye, which in the original is hardly to be
seen without a lens. You may, perhaps, be surprised
when I tell you that (putting the question of subject
aside for the moment, and speaking only of the mode
of execution and aim at resemblance,) you have there
a perfect example of the Greek ideal of method in
sculpture. And you will admit that, to the simplest
person whom we could introduce as a critic, that fish
would be a satisfactory, nay, almost a deceptive, fish;
while, to any one caring for subtleties of art, I
need not point out that every touch of the chisel
is applied with consummate knowledge, and that it
would be impossible to convey more truth and life with
the given quantity of workmanship.
131. Here is, indeed, a drawing by Turner, in which, with some fifty times
the quantity of labor, and far more highly educated
faculty of sight, the artist has expressed some qualities
of luster and color which only very wise persons indeed
could perceive in a John Dory; and this piece of paper
contains, therefore, much more, and more subtle, art,
than the Japan ivory; but are we sure that it is therefore
greater art? or that the painter was better
employed in producing this drawing, which only one
person can possess, and only one in a hundred enjoy,
than he would have been in producing two or three pieces
on a larger scale, which should have been at once
accessible to, and enjoyable by, a number of simpler
persons? Suppose, for instance, that Turner,
instead of faintly touching this outline, on white
paper, with his camel’s-hair pencil, had struck
the main forms of his fish into marble, thus, and instead of coloring the white paper so delicately
that, perhaps, only a few of the most keenly observant
artists in England can see it at all, had, with his
strong hand, tinted the marble with a few colors,
deceptive to the people, and harmonious to the initiated;
suppose that he had even conceded so much to the spirit
of popular applause as to allow of a bright glass bead
being inlaid for the eye, in the Japanese manner;
and that the enlarged, deceptive, and popularly pleasing
work had been carved on the outside of a great building, say
Fishmongers’ Hall, where everybody
commercially connected with Billingsgate could have
seen it, and ratified it with a wisdom of the market; might
not the art have been greater, worthier, and kinder
in such use?
132. Perhaps the idea does not
at once approve itself to you of having your public
buildings covered with ornaments; but, pray remember
that the choice of subject is an ethical question,
not now before us. All I ask you to decide is
whether the method is right, and would be pleasant,
in giving the distinctiveness to pretty things, which
it has here given to what, I suppose it may be assumed,
you feel to be an ugly thing. Of course, I must
note parenthetically, such realistic work is impossible
in a country where the buildings are to be discolored
by coal-smoke; but so is all fine sculpture whatsoever;
and the whiter, the worse its chance. For that
which is prepared for private persons, to be kept under
cover, will, of necessity, degenerate into the copyism
of past work, or merely sensational and sensual forms
of present life, unless there be a governing school
addressing the populace, for their instruction, on
the outside of buildings. So that, as I partly
warned you in my Third Lecture, you can simply have
no sculpture in a coal country. Whether
you like coals or carvings best, is no business of
mine. I merely have to assure you of the fact
that they are incompatible.
But, assuming that we are again, some
day, to become a civilized and governing race, deputing
ironmongery, coal-digging, and lucre-digging, to our
slaves in other countries, it is quite conceivable
that, with an increasing knowledge of natural history,
and desire for such knowledge, what is now done by
careful, but inefficient, wood-cuts, and in ill-colored
engravings, might be put in quite permanent sculptures,
with inlay of variegated precious stones, on the outside
of buildings, where such pictures would be little
costly to the people; and in a more popular manner
still, by Robbia ware and Palissy ware, and inlaid
majolica, which would differ from the housewife’s
present favorite decoration of plates above her kitchen
dresser, by being every piece of it various, instructive,
and universally visible.
133. You hardly know, I suppose,
whether I am speaking in jest or earnest. In
the most solemn earnest, I assure you; though such
is the strange course of our popular life that all
the irrational arts of destruction are at once felt
to be earnest; while any plan for those of instruction
on a grand scale, sounds like a dream, or jest.
Still, I do not absolutely propose to decorate our
public buildings with sculpture wholly of this character;
though beast, and fowl, and creeping things, and fishes,
might all find room on such a building as the Solomon’s
House of a New Atlantis; and some of them might even
become symbolic of much to us again. Passing
through the Strand, only the other day, for instance,
I saw four highly finished and delicately colored pictures
of cock-fighting, which, for imitative quality, were
nearly all that could be desired, going far beyond
the Greek cock of Himera; and they would have delighted
a Greek’s soul, if they had meant as much as
a Greek cock-fight; but they were only types of the
“,” and
of the spirit of home contest, which has been so fatal
lately to the Bird of France; and not of the defense
of one’s own barnyard, in thought of which the
Olympians set the cock on the pillars of their chariot
course; and gave it goodly alliance in its battle,
as you may see here, in what is left of the angle
of moldering marble in the chair of the priest of
Dionusos. The cast of it, from the center of
the theater under the Acropolis, is in the British
Museum; and I wanted its spiral for you, and this
kneeling Angel of Victory; it is late Greek
art, but nobly systematic flat bas-relief. So
I set Mr. Burgess to draw it; but neither he nor I,
for a little while, could make out what the Angel
of Victory was kneeling for. His attitude is an
ancient and grandly conventional one among the Egyptians;
and I was tracing it back to a kneeling goddess of
the greatest dynasty of the Pharaohs a goddess
of Evening, or Death, laying down the sun out of her
right hand; when, one bright day, the shadows
came out clear on the Athenian throne, and I saw that
my Angel of Victory was only backing a cock at a cock-fight.
134. Still, as I have said, there
is no reason why sculpture, even for simplest persons,
should confine itself to imagery of fish, or fowl,
or four-footed things.
We go back to our first principle:
we ought to carve nothing but what is honorable.
And you are offended, at this moment, with my fish,
(as I believe, when the first sculptures appeared
on the windows of this museum, offense was taken at
the unnecessary introduction of cats,) these dissatisfactions
being properly felt by your “.” For indeed, in all cases,
our right judgment must depend on our wish to give
honor only to things and creatures that deserve it.
135. And now I must state to
you another principle of veracity, both in sculpture,
and all following arts, of wider scope than any hitherto
examined. We have seen that sculpture is to be
a true representation of true internal form.
Much more is it to be a representation of true internal
emotion. You must carve only what you yourself
see as you see it; but, much more, you must carve
only what you yourself feel, as you feel it.
You may no more endeavor to feel through other men’s
souls, than to see with other men’s eyes.
Whereas generally now, in Europe and America, every
man’s energy is bent upon acquiring some false
emotion, not his own, but belonging to the past, or
to other persons, because he has been taught that
such and such a result of it will be fine. Every
attempted sentiment in relation to art is hypocritical;
our notions of sublimity, of grace, or pious serenity,
are all secondhand: and we are practically incapable
of designing so much as a bell-handle or a door-knocker,
without borrowing the first notion of it from those
who are gone where we shall not wake them
with our knocking. I would we could.
136. In the midst of this desolation
we have nothing to count on for real growth but what
we can find of honest liking and longing, in ourselves
and in others. We must discover, if we would healthily
advance, what things are verily
among us; and if we delight to honor the dishonorable,
consider how, in future, we may better bestow our
likings. Now it appears to me, from all our popular
declarations, that we, at present, honor nothing so
much as liberty and independence; and no person so
much as the Free man and Self-made man, who will be
ruled by no one, and has been taught, or helped, by
no one. And the reason I chose a fish for you
as the first subject of sculpture, was that in men
who are free and self-made, you have the nearest approach,
humanly possible, to the state of the fish, and finely
organized. You get the
exact phrase in Habakkuk, if you take the Septuagint
text, “.”
“Thou wilt make men as the fishes of the sea,
and as the reptile things, that have no ruler over
them.” And it chanced that as I was
preparing this Lecture, one of our most able and popular
prints gave me a wood-cut of the ‘self-made
man,’ specified as such, so vigorously drawn,
and with so few touches, that Phidias or Turner himself
could scarcely have done it better; so that I had only
to ask my assistant to enlarge it with accuracy, and
it became comparable with my fish at once. Of
course it is not given by the caricaturist as an admirable
face; only, I am enabled by his skill to set before
you, without any suspicion of unfairness on my
part, the expression to which the life we profess
to think most honorable, naturally leads. If
we were to take the hat off, you see how nearly the
profile corresponds with that of the typical fish.
137. Such, then, being the definition,
by your best popular art, of the ideal of feature
at which we are gradually arriving by self-manufacture:
when I place opposite to it the profile
of a man not in anywise self-made, neither by the
law of his own will, nor by the love of his own interest nor
capable, for a moment, of any kind of ‘Independence,’
or of the idea of independence; but wholly dependent
upon, and subjected to, external influence of just
law, wise teaching, and trusted love and truth, in
his fellow-spirits; setting before you,
I say, this profile of a God-made, instead of a self-made,
man, I know that you will feel, on the instant, that
you are brought into contact with the vital elements
of human art; and that this, the sculpture of the
good, is indeed the only permissible sculpture.
138. A God-made man, I
say. The face, indeed, stands as a symbol of
more than man in its sculptor’s mind. For
as I gave you, to lead your first effort in the form
of leaves, the scepter of Apollo, so this, which I
give you as the first type of rightness in the form
of flesh, is the countenance of the holder of that
scepter, the Sun-God of Syracuse. But there is
nothing in the face (nor did the Greek suppose there
was) more perfect than might be seen in the daily
beauty of the creatures the Sun-God shone upon, and
whom his strength and honor animated. This is
not an ideal, but a quite literally true, face of a
Greek youth; nay, I will undertake to show you that
it is not supremely beautiful, and even to surpass
it altogether with the literal portrait of an Italian
one. It is in verity no more than the form habitually
taken by the features of a well-educated young Athenian
or Sicilian citizen; and the one requirement for the
sculptors of to-day is not, as it has been thought,
to invent the same ideal, but merely to see the same
reality.
Now, you know I told you in my Fourth
Lecture that the beginning of art was in getting
our country clean and our people beautiful, and you
supposed that to be a statement irrelevant to my subject;
just as, at this moment, you perhaps think I am quitting
the great subject of this present Lecture the
method of likeness-making, and letting myself
branch into the discussion of what things we are to
make likeness of. But you shall see hereafter
that the method of imitating a beautiful thing must
be different from the method of imitating an ugly one;
and that, with the change in subject from what is
dishonorable to what is honorable, there will be involved
a parallel change in the management of tools, of lines,
and of colors. So that before I can determine
for you how you are to imitate, you must tell
me what kind of face you wish to imitate. The
best draughtsman in the world could not draw this Apollo
in ten scratches, though he can draw the self-made
man. Still less this nobler Apollo of Ionian
Greece, in which the incisions are softened
into a harmony like that of Correggio’s painting.
So that you see the method itself, the
choice between black incision or fine sculpture, and
perhaps, presently, the choice between color or no
color, will depend on what you have to represent.
Color may be expedient for a glistening dolphin or
a spotted fawn; perhaps inexpedient for
white Poseidon, and gleaming Dian. So that, before
defining the laws of sculpture, I am compelled to
ask you, what you mean to carve; and that,
little as you think it, is asking you how you mean
to live, and what the laws of your State are to be,
for they determine those of your statue.
You can only have this kind of face to study from,
in the sort of state that produced it. And you
will find that sort of state described in the beginning
of the fourth book of the laws of Plato; as founded,
for one thing, on the conviction that of all the evils
that can happen to a state, quantity of money is the
greatest!, “for, to speak shortly, no greater
evil, matching each against each, can possibly happen
to a city, as adverse to its forming just or generous
character,” than its being full of silver and
gold.
139. Of course the Greek notion
may be wrong, and ours right, only you can have Greek sculpture
only on that Greek theory: shortly expressed
by the words put into the mouth of Poverty herself,
in the Plutus of Aristophanes, “,” “I deliver to you better
men than the God of Money can, both in imagination
and feature.” So, on the other hand, this
ichthyoid, reptilian, or monochondyloid ideal of the
self-made man can only be reached, universally, by
a nation which holds that poverty, either of purse
or spirit, but especially the spiritual
character of being, is
the lowest of degradations; and which believes that
the desire of wealth is the first of manly and moral
sentiments. As I have been able to get the popular
ideal represented by its own living art, so I can
give you this popular faith in its own living words;
but in words meant seriously, and not at all as caricature,
from one of our leading journals, professedly aesthetic
also in its very name, the Spectator, of August
6, 1870.
“Mr. Ruskin’s plan,”
it says, “would make England poor, in order that
she might be cultivated, and refined, and artistic.
A wilder proposal was never broached by a man of ability;
and it might be regarded as a proof that the assiduous
study of art emasculates the intellect, and even
the moral sense. Such a theory almost warrants
the contempt with which art is often regarded by essentially
intellectual natures, like Proudhon” (sic).
“Art is noble as the flower of life, and the
creations of a Titian are a great heritage of the
race; but if England could secure high art and Venetian
glory of color only by the sacrifice of her manufacturing
supremacy, and by the acceptance of national poverty,
then the pursuit of such artistic achievements would
imply that we had ceased to possess natures of manly
strength, or to know the meaning of moral aims.
If we must choose between a Titian and a Lancashire
cotton mill, then, in the name of manhood and of morality,
give us the cotton mill. Only the dilettanteism
of the studio; that dilettanteism which loosens the
moral no less than the intellectual fiber, and which
is as fatal to rectitude of action as to correctness
of reasoning power, would make a different choice.”
You see also, by this interesting
and most memorable passage, how completely the question
is admitted to be one of ethics the only
real point at issue being, whether this face or that
is developed on the truer moral principle.
140. I assume, however, for the
present, that this Apolline type is the kind of form
you wish to reach and to represent. And now observe,
instantly, the whole question of manner of imitation
is altered for us. The fins of the fish, the
plumes of the swan, and the flowing of the Sun-God’s
hair are all represented by incisions but
the incisions do sufficiently represent the fin and
feather, they insufficiently represent
the hair. If I chose, with a little more care
and labor, I could absolutely get the surface of the
scales and spines of the fish, and the expression
of its mouth; but no quantity of labor would obtain
the real surface of a tress of Apollo’s hair,
and the full expression of his mouth. So that
we are compelled at once to call the imagination to
help us, and say to it, You know what the Apollo
Chrysocomes must be like; finish all this for
yourself. Now, the law under which imagination
works, is just that of other good workers. “You
must give me clear orders; show me what I have to
do, and where I am to begin, and let me alone.”
And the orders can be given, quite clearly, up to a
certain point, in form; but they cannot be given clearly
in color, now that the subject is subtle. All
beauty of this high kind depends on harmony; let but
the slightest discord come into it, and the finer the
thing is, the more fatal will be the flaw. Now,
on a flat surface, I can command my color to be precisely
what and where I mean it to be; on a round one I cannot.
For all harmony depends, first, on the fixed proportion
of the color of the light to that of the relative
shadow; and therefore if I fasten my color, I must
fasten my shade. But on a round surface the shadow
changes at every hour of the day; and therefore all
coloring which is expressive of form, is impossible;
and if the form is fine, (and here there is nothing
but what is fine,) you may bid farewell to color.
141. Farewell to color; that
is to say, if the thing is to be seen distinctly,
and you have only wise people to show it to; but if
it is to be seen indistinctly, at a distance, color
may become explanatory; and if you have simple people
to show it to, color may be necessary to excite their
imaginations, though not to excite yours. And
the art is great always by meeting its conditions
in the straightest way; and if it is to please a multitude
of innocent and bluntly-minded persons, must express
itself in the terms that will touch them; else it is
not good. And I have to trace for you through
the history of the past, and possibilities of the
future, the expedients used by great sculptors to
obtain clearness, impressiveness, or splendor; and
the manner of their appeal to the people, under various
light and shadow, and with reference to different
degrees of public intelligence: such investigation
resolving itself again and again, as we proceed, into
questions absolutely ethical; as, for instance, whether
color is to be bright or dull, that is
to say, for a populace cheerful or heartless; whether
it is to be delicate or strong, that is
to say, for a populace attentive or careless; whether
it is to be a background like the sky, for a procession
of young men and maidens, because your populace revere
life or the shadow of the vault behind a
corpse stained with drops of blackened blood, for
a populace taught to worship Death. Every critical
determination of rightness depends on the obedience
to some ethic law, by the most rational and, therefore,
simplest means. And you see how it depends most,
of all things, on whether you are working for chosen
persons, or for the mob; for the joy of the boudoir,
or of the Borgo. And if for the mob, whether
the mob of Olympia, or of St. Antoine. Phidias,
showing his Jupiter for the first time, hides behind
the temple door to listen, resolved afterwards “,”
and truly, as your people is, in judgment, and in multitude,
so must your sculpture be, in glory. An elementary
principle which has been too long out of mind.
142. I leave you to consider
it, since, for some time, we shall not again be able
to take up the inquiries to which it leads. But,
ultimately, I do not doubt that you will rest satisfied
in these following conclusions:
1. Not only sculpture, but all
the other fine arts, must be for the people.
2. They must be didactic to the
people, and that as their chief end. The structural
arts, didactic in their manner; the graphic arts, in
their matter also.
3. And chiefly the great representative
and imaginative arts that is to say, the
drama and sculpture are to teach what is
noble in past history, and lovely in existing human
and organic life.
4. And the test of right manner
of execution in these arts, is that they strike, in
the most emphatic manner, the rank of popular minds
to which they are addressed.
5. And the test of utmost fineness
in execution in these arts, is that they make themselves
be forgotten in what they represent; and so fulfill
the words of their greatest Master,
“THE BEST, IN
THIS KIND, ARE BUT SHADOWS.”