THE SCHOOL OF ATHENS.
December, 1870.
181. It can scarcely be needful
for me to tell even the younger members of my present
audience, that the conditions necessary for the production
of a perfect school of sculpture have only twice been
met in the history of the world, and then for a short
time; nor for short time only, but also in narrow
districts, namely, in the valleys and islands
of Ionian Greece, and in the strip of land deposited
by the Arno, between the Apennine crests and the sea.
All other schools, except these two,
led severally by Athens in the fifth century before
Christ, and by Florence in the fifteenth of our own
era, are imperfect; and the best of them are derivative:
these two are consummate in themselves, and the origin
of what is best in others.
182. And observe, these Athenian
and Florentine schools are both of equal rank, as
essentially original and independent. The Florentine,
being subsequent to the Greek, borrowed much from it;
but it would have existed just as strongly and,
perhaps, in some respects more nobly had
it been the first, instead of the latter of the two.
The task set to each of these mightiest of the nations
was, indeed, practically the same, and as hard to
the one as to the other. The Greeks found Phoenician
and Etruscan art monstrous, and had to make them human.
The Italians found Byzantine and Norman art monstrous,
and had to make them human. The original power
in the one case is easily traced; in the other it
has partly to be unmasked, because the change at Florence
was, in many points, suggested and stimulated by the
former school. But we mistake in supposing that
Athens taught Florence the laws of design; she taught
her, in reality, only the duty of truth.
183. You remember that I told
you the highest art could do no more than rightly
represent the human form. This is the simple test,
then, of a perfect school, that it has
represented the human form, so that it is impossible
to conceive of its being better done. And that,
I repeat, has been accomplished twice only: once
in Athens, once in Florence. And so narrow is
the excellence even of these two exclusive schools,
that it cannot be said of either of them that they
represented the entire human form. The Greeks
perfectly drew, and perfectly molded, the body and
limbs; but there is, so far as I am aware, no instance
of their representing the face as well as any great
Italian. On the other hand, the Italian painted
and carved the face insuperably; but I believe there
is no instance of his having perfectly represented
the body, which, by command of his religion, it became
his pride to despise and his safety to mortify.
184. The general course of your
study here renders it desirable that you should be
accurately acquainted with the leading principles of
Greek sculpture; but I cannot lay these before you
without giving undue prominence to some of the special
merits of that school, unless I previously indicate
the relation it holds to the more advanced, though
less disciplined, excellence of Christian art.
In this and the last Lecture of the
present course, I shall endeavor, therefore, to
mass for you, in such rude and diagram-like outline
as may be possible or intelligible, the main characteristics
of the two schools, completing and correcting the
details of comparison afterwards; and not answering,
observe, at present, for any generalization I give
you, except as a ground for subsequent closer and
more qualified statements.
And in carrying out this parallel,
I shall speak indifferently of works of sculpture,
and of the modes of painting which propose to themselves
the same objects as sculpture. And this, indeed,
Florentine, as opposed to Venetian, painting, and
that of Athens in the fifth century, nearly always
did.
185. I begin, therefore, by comparing
two designs of the simplest kind engravings,
or, at least, linear drawings both; one on clay, one
on copper, made in the central periods of each style,
and representing the same goddess Aphrodite.
They are now set beside each other in your Rudimentary
Series. The first is from a patera lately
found at Camirus, authoritatively assigned by Mr.
Newton, in his recent catalogue, to the best period
of Greek art. The second is from one of the series
of engravings executed, probably, by Baccio Bandini,
in 1485, out of which I chose your first practical
exercise the Scepter of Apollo. I cannot,
however, make the comparison accurate in all respects,
for I am obliged to set the restricted type of the
Aphrodite Urania of the Greeks beside the universal
Deity conceived by the Italian as governing the air,
earth, and sea; nevertheless, the restriction in the
mind of the Greek, and expatiation in that of the
Florentine, are both characteristic. The Greek
Venus Urania is flying in heaven, her power over the
waters symbolized by her being borne by a swan, and
her power over the earth by a single flower in her
right hand; but the Italian Aphrodite is rising out
of the actual sea, and only half risen: her limbs
are still in the sea, her merely animal strength filling
the waters with their life; but her body to the loins
is in the sunshine, her face raised to the sky; her
hand is about to lay a garland of flowers on the earth.
186. The Venus Urania of the
Greeks, in her relation to men, has power only over
lawful and domestic love; therefore, she is fully dressed,
and not only quite dressed, but most daintily and
trimly: her feet delicately sandaled, her gown
spotted with little stars, her hair brushed exquisitely
smooth at the top of her head, trickling in minute
waves down her forehead; and though, because there
is such a quantity of it, she can’t possibly
help having a chignon, look how tightly she has fastened
it in with her broad fillet. Of course she is
married, so she must wear a cap with pretty minute
pendent jewels at the border; and a very small necklace,
all that her husband can properly afford, just enough
to go closely round her neck, and no more. On
the contrary, the Aphrodite of the Italian, being
universal love, is pure-naked; and her long hair is
thrown wild to the wind and sea.
These primal differences in the symbolism,
observe, are only because the artists are thinking
of separate powers: they do not necessarily involve
any national distinction in feeling. But the differences
I have next to indicate are essential, and characterize
the two opposed national modes of mind.
187. First, and chiefly.
The Greek Aphrodite is a very pretty person, and the
Italian a decidedly plain one. That is because
a Greek thought no one could possibly love any but
pretty people; but an Italian thought that love could
give dignity to the meanest form that it inhabited,
and light to the poorest that it looked upon.
So his Aphrodite will not condescend to be pretty.
188. Secondly. In the Greek
Venus the breasts are broad and full, though perfectly
severe in their almost conical profile; (you
are allowed on purpose to see the outline of the right
breast, under the chiton;) also the right
arm is left bare, and you can just see the contour
of the front of the right limb and knee; both arm
and limb pure and firm, but lovely. The plant
she holds in her hand is a branching and flowering
one, the seed-vessel prominent. These signs all
mean that her essential function is child-bearing.
On the contrary, in the Italian Venus
the breasts are so small as to be scarcely traceable;
the body strong, and almost masculine in its angles;
the arms meager and unattractive, and she lays a decorative
garland of flowers on the earth. These signs
mean that the Italian thought of love as the strength
of an eternal spirit, forever helpful; and forever
crowned with flowers, that neither know seedtime nor
harvest; and bloom where there is neither death nor
birth.
189. Thirdly. The Greek
Aphrodite is entirely calm, and looks straight forward.
Not one feature of her face is disturbed, or seems
ever to have been subject to emotion. The Italian
Aphrodite looks up, her face all quivering and burning
with passion and wasting anxiety. The Greek one
is quiet, self-possessed, and self-satisfied:
the Italian incapable of rest; she has had no thought
nor care for herself; her hair has been bound by a
fillet like the Greek’s; but it is now all fallen
loose, and clotted with the sea, or clinging to her
body; only the front tress of it is caught by the
breeze from her raised forehead, and lifted, in the
place where the tongues of fire rest on the brows,
in the early Christian pictures of Pentecost, and
the waving fires abide upon the heads of Angelico’s
seraphim.
190. There are almost endless
points of interest, great and small, to be noted in
these differences of treatment. This binding of
the hair by the single fillet marks the straight course
of one great system of art method, from that Greek
head which I showed you on the archaic coin of the
seventh century before Christ, to this of the fifteenth
of our own era; nay, when you look close,
you will see the entire action of the head depends
on one lock of hair falling back from the ear, which
it does in compliance with the old Greek observance
of its being bent there by the pressure of the helmet.
That rippling of it down her shoulders comes from
the Athena of Corinth; the raising of it on her forehead,
from the knot of the hair of Diana, changed into the
vestal fire of the angels. But chiefly, the calmness
of the features in the one face, and their anxiety
in the other, indicate first, indeed, the characteristic
difference in every conception of the schools, the
Greek never representing expression, the Italian primarily
seeking it; but far more, mark for us here the utter
change in the conception of love; from the tranquil
guide and queen of a happy terrestrial domestic life,
accepting its immediate pleasures and natural duties,
to the agonizing hope of an infinite good, and the
ever mingled joy and terror of a love divine in jealousy,
crying, “Set me as a seal upon thine heart, as
a seal upon thine arm; for love is strong as death,
jealousy is cruel as the grave.”
The vast issues dependent on this
change in the conception of the ruling passion of
the human soul, I will endeavor to show you on a future
occasion: in my present Lecture, I shall limit
myself to the definition of the temper of Greek sculpture,
and of its distinctions from Florentine in the treatment
of any subject whatever, be it love or hatred, hope
or despair.
These great differences are mainly the following.
191. First. A Greek never
expresses momentary passion; a Florentine looks to
momentary passion as the ultimate object of his skill.
When you are next in London, look
carefully in the British Museum at the casts from
the statues in the pediment of the Temple of Minerva
at AEgina. You have there Greek work of definite
date about 600 B. C., certainly before
580 of the purest kind; and you have the
representation of a noble ideal subject, the combats
of the AEacidae at Troy, with Athena herself looking
on. But there is no attempt whatever to represent
expression in the features, none to give complexity
of action or gesture; there is no struggling, no anxiety,
no visible temporary exertion of muscles. There
are fallen figures, one pulling a lance out of his
wound, and others in attitudes of attack and defense;
several kneeling to draw their bows. But all inflict
and suffer, conquer or expire, with the same smile.
192.From more advanced art, of true Greek representation;
the subjects being the two contests of leading import
to the Greek heart that of Apollo with the
Python, and of Hercules with the Nemean Lion.
You see that in neither case is there the slightest
effort to represent the, or agony
of contest. No good Greek artist would have you
behold the suffering either of gods, heroes, or men;
nor allow you to be apprehensive of the issue of their
contest with evil beasts, or evil spirits. All
such lower sources of excitement are to be closed
to you; your interest is to be in the thoughts involved
by the fact of the war; and in the beauty or rightness
of form, whether active or inactive. I have to
work out this subject with you afterwards, and to
compare with the pure Greek method of thought that
of modern dramatic passion, ingrafted on it, as typically
in Turner’s contest of Apollo and the Python:
in the meantime, be content with the statement of
this first great principle that a Greek,
as such, never expresses momentary passion.
193. Secondly. The Greek,
as such, never expresses personal character, while
a Florentine holds it to be the ultimate condition
of beauty. You are startled, I suppose, at my
saying this, having had it often pointed out to you,
as a transcendent piece of subtlety in Greek art, that
you could distinguish Hercules from Apollo by his
being stout, and Diana from Juno by her being slender.
That is very true; but those are general distinctions
of class, not special distinctions of personal character.
Even as general, they are bodily, not mental.
They are the distinctions, in fleshly aspect, between
an athlete and a musician, between a matron
and a huntress; but in nowise distinguish the simple-hearted
hero from the subtle Master of the Muses, nor the
willful and fitful girl-goddess from the cruel and
resolute matron-goddess. But judge for yourselves. I show you,
typically represented as the protectresses of nations,
the Argive, Cretan, and Lacinian Hera, the Messenian
Demeter, the Athena of Corinth, the Artemis of Syracuse;
the fountain Arethusa of Syracuse, and the Siren Ligeia
of Terina. Now, of these heads, it is true that
some are more delicate in feature than the rest, and
some softer in expression: in other respects,
can you trace any distinction between the Goddesses
of Earth and Heaven, or between the Goddess of Wisdom
and the Water Nymph of Syracuse? So little can
you do so, that it would have remained a disputed question had
not the name luckily been inscribed on some Syracusan
coins whether the head upon them was meant
for Arethusa at all; and, continually, it becomes
a question respecting finished statues, if without
attributes, “Is this Bacchus or Apollo Zeus
or Poseidon?” There is a fact for you; noteworthy,
I think! There is no personal character in true
Greek art: abstract ideas of youth and
age, strength and swiftness, virtue and vice, yes:
but there is no individuality; and the negative holds
down to the revived conventionalism of the Greek school
by Leonardo, when he tells you how you are to paint
young women, and how old ones; though a Greek would
hardly have been so discourteous to age as the Italian
is in his canon of it, “old women
should be represented as passionate and hasty, after
the manner of Infernal Furies.”
194. “But at least, if
the Greeks do not give character, they give ideal
beauty?” So it is said, without contradiction.
But will you look again at the series of coins of
the best time of Greek art, which I have just set
before you? Are any of these goddesses or nymphs
very beautiful? Certainly the Junos are
not. Certainly the Demeters are not. The
Siren, and Arethusa, have well-formed and regular
features; but I am quite sure that if you look at
them without prejudice, you will think neither reaches
even the average standard of pretty English girls.
The Venus Urania suggests at first the idea of a very
charming person, but you will find there is no real
depth nor sweetness in the contours, looked at closely.
And remember, these are chosen examples, the
best I can find of art current in Greece at the great
time; and if even I were to take the celebrated statues,
of which only two or three are extant, not one of
them excels the Venus of Melos; and she, as I have
already asserted, in the ‘Queen of the Air,’
has nothing notable in feature except dignity and
simplicity. Of Athena I do not know one authentic
type of great beauty; but the intense ugliness which
the Greeks could tolerate in their symbolism of her
will be convincingly proved to you by the coin. You need only look at two or three
vases of the best time to assure yourselves that beauty
of feature was, in popular art, not only unattained,
but unattempted; and, finally, and this
you may accept as a conclusive proof of the Greek insensitiveness
to the most subtle beauty, there is little
evidence even in their literature, and none in their
art, of their having ever perceived any beauty in
infancy, or early childhood.
195. The Greeks, then, do not
give passion, do not give character, do not give refined
or naïve beauty. But you may think that the absence
of these is intended to give dignity to the gods and
nymphs; and that their calm faces would be found,
if you long observed them, instinct with some expression
of divine mystery or power.
I will convince you of the narrow
range of Greek thought in these respects, by showing
you, from the two sides of one and the same coin,
images of the most mysterious of their deities, and
the most powerful, Demeter, and Zeus.
Remember that just as the west coasts
of Ireland and England catch first on their hills
the rain of the Atlantic, so the Western Peloponnese
arrests, in the clouds of the first mountain ranges
of Arcadia, the moisture of the Mediterranean; and
over all the plains of Elis, Pylos, and Messene, the
strength and sustenance of men was naturally felt to
be granted by Zeus; as, on the east coast of Greece,
the greater clearness of the air by the power of Athena.
If you will recollect the prayer of Rhea, in the single
line of Callimachus,”
(compare Pausanias, iv 33, at the beginning,) it
will mark for you the connection, in the Greek mind,
of the birth of the mountain springs of Arcadia with
the birth of Zeus. And the centers of Greek thought
on this western coast are necessarily Elis, and, (after
the time of Epaminondas,) Messene.
196. I show you the coin of Messene,
because the splendid height and form of Mount Ithome
were more expressive of the physical power of Zeus
than the lower hills of Olympia; and also because it
was struck just at the time of the most finished and
delicate Greek art a little after the main
strength of Phidias, but before decadence had generally
pronounced itself. The coin is a silver didrachm,
bearing on one side a head of Demeter; on the other a full figure of Zeus Aietophoros; the two together signifying
the sustaining strength of the earth and heaven.
Look first at the head of Demeter. It is merely
meant to personify fullness of harvest; there is no
mystery in it, no sadness, no vestige of the expression
which we should have looked for in any effort to realize
the Greek thoughts of the Earth Mother, as we find
them spoken by the poets. But take it merely
as personified Abundance, the goddess of
black furrow and tawny grass, how commonplace
it is, and how poor! The hair is grand, and there
is one stalk of wheat set in it, which is enough to
indicate the goddess who is meant; but, in that very
office, ignoble, for it shows that the artist could
only inform you that this was Demeter by such a symbol.
How easy it would have been for a great designer to
have made the hair lovely with fruitful flowers, and
the features noble in mystery of gloom, or of tenderness.
But here you have nothing to interest you, except
the common Greek perfections of a straight nose and
a full chin.
197. We pass, on the reverse
of the die, to the figure of Zeus Aietophoros.
Think of the invocation to Zeus in the Suppliants,
“King of Kings, and Happiest of the Happy, Perfectest of the Perfect in strength, abounding in
all things, Jove hear us, and be with us;”
and then, consider what strange phase of mind it was,
which, under the very mountain-home of the god, was
content with this symbol of him as a well-fed athlete,
holding a diminutive and crouching eagle on his fist.
The features and the right hand have been injured in
this coin, but the action of the arm shows that it
held a thunderbolt, of which, I believe, the twisted
rays were triple. In the presumably earlier coin
engraved by Millingen, however, it is singly pointed
only; and the added inscription “,” in the field, renders the conjecture
of Millingen probable, that this is a rude representation
of the statue of Zeus Ithomates, made by Ageladas,
the master of Phidias; and I think it has, indeed,
the aspect of the endeavor, by a workman of more advanced
knowledge, and more vulgar temper, to put the softer
anatomy of later schools into the simple action of
an archaic figure. Be that as it may, here is
one of the most refined cities of Greece content with
the figure of an athlete as the representative of
their own mountain god; marked as a divine power merely
by the attributes of the eagle and thunderbolt.
198. Lastly. The Greeks
have not, it appears, in any supreme way, given to
their statues character, beauty, or divine strength.
Can they give divine sadness? Shall we find in
their art-work any of that pensiveness and yearning
for the dead which fills the chants of their tragedy?
I suppose, if anything like nearness or firmness of
faith in after-life is to be found in Greek legend,
you might look for it in the stories about the Island
of Leuce, at the mouth of the Danube, inhabited by
the ghosts of Achilles, Patroclus, Ajax the son of
Oileus, and Helen; and in which the pavement of the
Temple of Achilles was washed daily by the sea-birds
with their wings, dipping them in the sea.
Now it happens that we have actually
on a coin of the Locrians the representation of the
ghost of the Lesser Ajax. There is nothing in
the history of human imagination more lovely than
their leaving always a place for his spirit, vacant
in their ranks of battle. But here is their sculptural
representation of the phantom; and I think you will at once agree with me
in feeling that it would be impossible to conceive
anything more completely unspiritual. You might
more than doubt that it could have been meant for the
departed soul, unless you were aware of the meaning
of this little circlet between the feet. On other
coins you find his name inscribed there, but in this
you have his habitation, the haunted Island of Leuce
itself, with the waves flowing round it.
199. Again and again, however,
I have to remind you, with respect to these apparently
frank and simple failures, that the Greek always intends
you to think for yourself, and understand, more than
he can speak. Take this instance at our hands,
the trim little circlet for the Island of Leuce.
The workman knows very well it is not like the island,
and that he could not make it so; that, at its best,
his sculpture can be little more than a letter; and
yet, in putting this circlet, and its encompassing
fretwork of minute waves, he does more than if he had
merely given you a letter L, or written ‘Leuce.’
If you know anything of beaches and sea, this symbol
will set your imagination at work in recalling them;
then you will think of the temple service of the novitiate
sea-birds, and of the ghosts of Achilles and Patroclus
appearing, like the Dioscuri, above the storm-clouds
of the Euxine. And the artist, throughout his
work, never for an instant loses faith in your sympathy
and passion being ready to answer his; if
you have none to give, he does not care to take you
into his counsel; on the whole, would rather that
you should not look at his work.
200. But if you have this sympathy
to give, you may be sure that whatever he does for
you will be right, as far as he can render it so.
It may not be sublime, nor beautiful, nor amusing;
but it will be full of meaning, and faithful in guidance.
He will give you clue to myriads of things that he
cannot literally teach; and, so far as he does teach,
you may trust him. Is not this saying much?
And as he strove only to teach what
was true, so, in his sculptured symbol, he strove
only to carve what was Right. He rules
over the arts to this day, and will forever, because
he sought not first for beauty, not first for passion,
or for invention, but for Rightness; striving to display,
neither himself nor his art, but the thing that he
dealt with, in its simplicity. That is his specific
character as a Greek. Of course every nation’s
character is connected with that of others surrounding
or preceding it; and in the best Greek work you will
find some things that are still false, or fanciful;
but whatever in it is false, or fanciful, is not the
Greek part of it it is the Phoenician, or
Egyptian, or Pelasgian part. The essential Hellenic
stamp is veracity: Eastern nations drew
their heroes with eight legs, but the Greeks drew them
with two; Egyptians drew their deities
with cats’ heads, but the Greeks drew them with
men’s; and out of all fallacy, disproportion,
and indefiniteness, they were, day by day, resolvedly
withdrawing and exalting themselves into restricted
and demonstrable truth.
201. And now, having cut away
the misconceptions which incumbered our thoughts,
I shall be able to put the Greek school into some clearness
of its position for you, with respect to the art of
the world. That relation is strangely duplicate;
for, on one side, Greek art is the root of all simplicity;
and, on the other, of all complexity.
On one side, I say, it is the root
of all simplicity. If you were for some prolonged
period to study Greek sculpture exclusively in the
Elgin room of the British Museum, and were then suddenly
transported to the Hotel de Cluny, or any other museum
of Gothic and barbarian workmanship, you would imagine
the Greeks were the masters of all that was grand,
simple, wise, and tenderly human, opposed to the pettiness
of the toys of the rest of mankind.
202. On one side of their work
they are so. From all vain and mean decoration all
wreak and monstrous error, the Greeks rescue the forms
of man and beast, and sculpture them in the nakedness
of their true flesh, and with the fire of their living
soul. Distinctively from other races, as I have
now, perhaps to your weariness, told you, this is the
work of the Greek, to give health to what was diseased,
and chastisement to what was untrue. So far as
this is found in any other school, hereafter, it belongs
to them by inheritance from the Greeks, or invests
them with the brotherhood of the Greek. And this
is the deep meaning of the myth of Daedalus as the
giver of motion to statues. The literal change
from the binding together of the feet to their separation,
and the other modifications of action which took place,
either in progressive skill, or often, as the mere
consequence of the transition from wood to stone,
(a figure carved out of one wooden log must have necessarily
its feet near each other, and hands at its sides,)
these literal changes are as nothing, in the Greek
fable, compared to the bestowing of apparent life.
The figures of monstrous gods on Indian temples have
their legs separate enough; but they are infinitely
more dead than the rude figures at Branchidae sitting
with their hands on their knees. And, briefly,
the work of Daedalus is the giving of deceptive life,
as that of Prometheus the giving of real life; and
I can put the relation of Greek to all other art,
in this function, before you, in easily compared and
remembered examples.
203. Here, on the right is an Indian bull, colossal, and elaborately
carved, which you may take as a sufficient type of
the bad art of all the earth. False in form,
dead in heart, and loaded with wealth, externally.
We will not ask the date of this; it may rest in the
eternal obscurity of evil art, everywhere, and forever.
Now, beside this colossal bull, here is a bit of Daedalus-work,
enlarged from a coin not bigger than a shilling:
look at the two together, and you ought to know, henceforward,
what Greek art means, to the end of your days.
204. In this aspect of it, then,
I say it is the simplest and nakedest of lovely veracities.
But it has another aspect, or rather another pole,
for the opposition is diametric. As the simplest,
so also it is the most complex of human art.
I told you in my Fifth Lecture, showing you the spotty
picture of Velasquez, that an essential Greek character
is a liking for things that are dappled. And
you cannot but have noticed how often and how prevalently
the idea which gave its name to the Porch of Polygnotus,
“,” occurs to
the Greeks as connected with the finest art.
Thus, when the luxurious city is opposed to the simple
and healthful one, in the second book of Plato’s
Polity, you find that, next to perfumes, pretty ladies,
and dice, you must have in it “,” which observe, both in that place
and again in the third book, is the separate art of
joiners’ work, or inlaying; but the idea of
exquisitely divided variegation or division, both in
sight and sound the “ravishing division
to the lute,” as in Pindar’s “” runs through the
compass of all Greek art-description; and if, instead
of studying that art among marbles, you were to look
at it only on vases of a fine time, your impression of it
would be, instead of breadth and simplicity, one of
universal spottiness and checkeredness, “;” and of the
artist’s delighting in nothing so much as in
crossed or starred or spotted things; which, in right
places, he and his public both do unlimitedly.
Indeed they hold it complimentary even to a trout,
to call him a ‘spotty.’ Do you recollect
the trout in the tributaries of the Ladon, which
Pausanias says were spotted, so that they were like
thrushes, and which, the Arcadians told him, could
speak? In this last, however,
they disappointed him. “I, indeed, saw some
of them caught,” he says, “but I did not
hear any of them speak, though I waited beside the
river till sunset.”
205. I must sum roughly now,
for I have detained you too long.
The Greeks have been thus the origin,
not only of all broad, mighty, and calm conception,
but of all that is divided, delicate, and tremulous;
“variable as the shade, by the light quivering
aspen made.” To them, as first leaders
of ornamental design, belongs, of right, the praise
of glistenings in gold, piercings in ivory, stainings
in purple, burnishings in dark blue steel; of the
fantasy of the Arabian roof, quartering
of the Christian shield, rubric and arabesque
of Christian scripture; in fine, all enlargement,
and all diminution of adorning thought, from the temple
to the toy, and from the mountainous pillars of Agrigentum
to the last fineness of fretwork in the Pisan Chapel
of the Thorn.
And in their doing all this, they stand as masters of human order and
justice, subduing the animal nature, guided by the spiritual one, as you see the
Sicilian Charioteer stands, holding his horse-reins, with the wild lion racing
beneath him, and the flying angel above, on the beautiful coin of early
Syracuse.
And the beginnings of Christian chivalry
were in that Greek bridling of the dark and the white
horses.
206. Not that a Greek never made
mistakes. He made as many as we do ourselves,
nearly; he died of his mistakes at last as
we shall die of them; but so far as he was separated
from the herd of more mistaken and more wretched nations so
far as he was Greek it was by his rightness.
He lived, and worked, and was satisfied with the fatness
of his land, and the fame of his deeds, by his justice,
and reason, and modesty. He became Graeculus
esuriens, little, and hungry, and every man’s
errand-boy, by his iniquity, and his competition, and
his love of talk. But his Graecism was in having
done, at least at one period of his dominion, more
than anybody else, what was modest, useful, and eternally
true; and as a workman, he verily did, or first suggested
the doing of, everything possible to man.
Take Daedalus, his great type of the
practically executive craftsman, and the inventor
of expedients in craftsmanship, (as distinguished from
Prometheus, the institutor of moral order in art).
Daedalus invents, he, or his nephew,
The potter’s wheel,
and all work in clay;
The saw, and all work in wood;
The masts and sails of ships,
and all modes of motion;
(wings only proving
too dangerous!)
The entire art of minute ornament;
And the deceptive life of
statues.
By his personal toil, he involves
the fatal labyrinth for Minos; builds an impregnable
fortress for the Agrigentines; adorns healing baths
among the wild parsley-fields of Selinus; buttresses
the precipices of Eryx, under the temple of Aphrodite;
and for her temple itself finishes in exquisiteness
the golden honeycomb.
207. Take note of that last piece
of his art: it is connected with many things
which I must bring before you when we enter on the
study of architecture. That study we shall begin
at the foot of the Baptistery of Florence, which,
of all buildings known to me, unites the most perfect
symmetry with the quaintest.
Then, from the tomb of your own Edward the Confessor,
to the farthest shrine of the opposite Arabian and
Indian world, I must show you how the glittering and
iridescent dominion of Daedalus prevails; and his ingenuity
in division, interposition, and labyrinthine sequence,
more widely still. Only this last summer I found
the dark red masses of the rough sandstone of Furness
Abbey had been fitted by him, with no less pleasure
than he had in carving them, into wedged hexagons reminiscences
of the honeycomb of Venus Erycina. His ingenuity
plays around the framework of all the noblest things;
and yet the brightness of it has a lurid shadow.
The spot of the fawn, of the bird, and the moth, may
be harmless. But Daedalus reigns no less over
the spot of the leopard and snake. That cruel
and venomous power of his art is marked, in the legends
of him, by his invention of the saw from the serpent’s
tooth; and his seeking refuge, under blood-guiltiness,
with Minos, who can judge evil, and measure, or remit,
the penalty of it, but not reward good; Rhadamanthus
only can measure that; but Minos is essentially
the recognizer of evil deeds “conoscitor delle
peccata,” whom, therefore, you find in Dante
under the form of the. “Cignesi
con la coda tante volte, quantunque
gradi vuol che giú sia messa.”
And this peril of the influence of
Daedalus is twofold; first, in leading us to delight
in glitterings and semblances of things, more than
in their form, or truth; admire the harlequin’s
jacket more than the hero’s strength; and love
the gilding of the missal more than its words; but
farther, and worse, the ingenuity of Daedalus may even
become bestial, an instinct for mechanical labor only,
strangely involved with a feverish and ghastly cruelty: (you
will find this distinct in the intensely Daedal work
of the Japanese); rebellious, finally, against the
laws of nature and honor, and building labyrinths for
monsters, not combs for bees.
208. Gentlemen, we of the rough
northern race may never, perhaps, be able to learn
from the Greek his reverence for beauty; but we may
at least learn his disdain of mechanism: of
all work which he felt to be monstrous and inhuman
in its imprudent dexterities.
We hold ourselves, we English, to
be good workmen. I do not think I speak with
light reference to recent calamity, (for I myself lost
a young relation, full of hope and good purpose, in
the foundered ship London,) when I say that
either an AEginetan or Ionian shipwright built ships
that could be fought from, though they were under water;
and neither of them would have been proud of having
built one that would fill and sink helplessly if the
sea washed over her deck, or turn upside-down if a
squall struck her topsail.
Believe me, gentlemen, good workmanship
consists in continence and common sense, more than
in frantic expatiation of mechanical ingenuity; and
if you would be continent and rational, you had better
learn more of Art than you do now, and less of Engineering.
What is taking place at this very hour, among
the streets, once so bright, and avenues, once so
pleasant, of the fairest city in Europe, may surely
lead us all to feel that the skill of Daedalus, set
to build impregnable fortresses, is not so wisely
applied as in framing the, the
golden honeycomb.