THE GREEK AGE OF REASON.
The conquest of Persia by Alexander
the Great is a most important event in European history.
That adventurer, carrying out the intentions of his
father Philip, commenced his attack with apparently
very insignificant means, having, it is said, at the
most, only thirty-four thousand infantry, four thousand
cavalry, and seventy talents in money. The result
of his expedition was the ruin of the Persian empire,
and also the ruin of Greece. It was not without
reason that his memory was cursed in his native country.
Her life-blood was drained away by his successes.
In view of the splendid fortunes to be made in Asia,
Greece ceased to be the place for an enterprising
man. To such an extent did military emigration
go, that Greek recruits were settled all over the Persian
empire; their number was sufficient to injure irreparably
the country from which they had parted, but not sufficient
to Hellenize the dense and antique populations among
whom they had settled.
Not only was it thus by the drain
of men that the Macedonian expedition was so dreadfully
disastrous to Greece, the political consequences following
those successful campaigns added to the baneful result.
Alexander could not have more effectually ruined Athens
had he treated her as he did Thebes, which he levelled
with the ground, massacring six thousand of her citizens,
and selling thirty thousand for slaves. The founding
of Alexandria was the commercial end of Athens, the
finishing stroke to her old colonial system.
It might have been well for her had he stopped short
in his projects with the downfall of Tyre, destroyed,
not from any vindictive reasons, as is sometimes said,
but because he discovered that that city was an essential
part of the Persian system. It was never his
intention that Athens should derive advantage from
the annihilation of her Phoenician competitor; his
object was effectually carried out by the building
and prosperity of Alexandria.
Though the military celebrity of this
great soldier may be diminished by the history of
the last hundred years, which shows a uniform result
of victory when European armies are brought in contact
with Asiatic, even under the most extraordinary disadvantages,
there cannot be denied to him a profound sagacity
and statesmanship excelled by no other conqueror.
Before he became intoxicated with success, and, unfortunately,
too frequently intoxicated with wine, there was much
that was noble in his character. He had been
under the instruction of Aristotle for several years,
and, on setting out on his expedition, took with him
so many learned men as almost to justify the remark
applied to it, that it was as much a scientific as
a military undertaking. Among those who thus
accompanied him was Callisthenes, a relative and pupil
of Aristotle, destined for an evil end. Perhaps
the assertion that Alexander furnished to his master
250,000_l._ and the services of several thousand men,
for the purpose of obtaining and examining the specimens
required in the composition of his work on the “History
of Animals” may be an exaggeration, but there
can be no doubt that in these transactions was the
real beginning of that policy which soon led to the
institution of the Museum at Alexandria. The importance
of this event, though hitherto little understood,
admits of no exaggeration, so far as the intellectual
progress of Europe is concerned. It gave to the
works of Aristotle their wonderful duration; it imparted
to them not only a Grecian celebrity, but led to their
translation into Syriac by the Nestorians in the fifth
century, and from Syriac by the Arabs into their tongue
four hundred years later. They exercised a living
influence over Christians and Mohammedans indifferently,
from Spain to Mesopotamia.
If the letter quoted by Plutarch as
having been written by Alexander to Aristotle be authentic,
it not only shows how thoroughly the pupil had been
indoctrinated into the wisdom of the master, but warns
us how liable we are to be led astray in the exposition
we are presently to give of the Aristotelian philosophy.
There was then, as unfortunately there has been too
often since, a private as well as a public doctrine.
Alexander upbraids the philosopher for his indiscretion
in revealing things that it was understood should
be concealed. Aristotle defends himself by asserting
that the desired concealment had not been broken.
By many other incidents of a trifling kind the attachment
of the conqueror to philosophy is indicated; thus
Harpalus and Nearchus, the companions of his youth,
were the agents employed in some of his scientific
undertakings, the latter being engaged in sea explorations,
doubtless having in the main a political object, yet
full of interest to science. Had Alexander lived,
Nearchus was to have repeated the circumnavigation
of Africa. Harpalus, while governor of Babylon,
was occupied in the attempt to exchange the vegetation
of Europe and Asia; he intertransplanted the productions
of Persia and Greece, succeeding, as is related, in
his object of making all European plants that he tried,
except the ivy, grow in Mesopotamia. The journey
to the Caspian Sea, the expedition into the African
deserts, indicate Alexander’s personal taste
for natural knowledge; nor is it without significance
that, while on his death-bed, and, indeed, within a
few days of his decease, he found consolation and
amusement in having Nearchus by his side relating
the story of his voyages. Nothing shows more strikingly
how correct was his military perception than the intention
he avowed of equipping a thousand ships for the conquest
of Carthage, and thus securing his supremacy in the
Mediterranean. Notwithstanding all this, there
were many points of his character, and many events
of his life, worthy of the condemnation with which
they have been visited; the drunken burning of Persepolis,
the prisoners he slaughtered in honour of Hephaestion,
the hanging of Callisthenes, were the results of intemperance
and unbridled passion. Even so steady a mind as
his was incapable of withstanding the influence of
such enormous treasures as those he seized at Susa;
the plunder of the Persian empire; the inconceivable
luxury of Asiatic life; the uncontrolled power to which
he attained. But he was not so imbecile as to
believe himself the descendant of Jupiter Ammon; that
was only an artifice he permitted for the sake of
influencing those around him. We must not forget
that he lived in an age when men looked for immaculate
conceptions and celestial descents. These Asiatic
ideas had made their way into Europe. The Athenians
themselves were soon to be reconciled to the appointment
of divine honours to such as Antigonus and Demetrius,
adoring them as gods saviour gods and
instituting sacrifices and priests for their worship.
Great as were the political results
of the Macedonian expedition, they were equalled by
the intellectual. The times were marked by the
ushering in of a new philosophy. Greece had gone
through her age of Credulity, her age of Inquiry,
her age of Faith; she had entered on her age of Reason,
and, had freedom of action been permitted to her, she
would have given a decisive tone to the forthcoming
civilization of Europe. As will be seen in the
following pages, that great destiny did not await
her. From her eccentric position at Alexandria
she could not civilize Europe. In her old age,
the power of Europe, concentrated in the Roman empire,
overthrew her. There are very few histories of
the past of more interest to modern times, and none,
unfortunately, more misunderstood, than this Greek
age of Reason manifested at Alexandria. It illustrates,
in the most signal manner, that affairs control men
more than men control affairs. The scientific
associations of the Macedonian conqueror directly
arose from the contemporaneous state of Greek philosophy
in the act of reaching the close of its age of faith,
and these influences ripened under the Macedonian
captain who became King of Egypt. As it was,
the learning of Alexandria, though diverted from its
most appropriate and desirable direction by the operation
of the Byzantine system, in the course of a few centuries
acting forcibly upon it, was not without an influence
on the future thought of Europe. Even at this
day Europe will not bear to be fully told how great
that influence has been.
The age of Reason, to which Aristotle
is about to introduce us, stands in striking contrast
to the preceding ages. It cannot escape the reader
that what was done by the men of science in Alexandria
resembles what is doing in our own times; their day
was the foreshadowing of ours. And yet a long
and dreary period of almost twenty centuries parts
us from them. Politically, Aristotle, through
his friendship with Alexander and the perpetuation
of the Macedonian influence in Ptolemy, was the connecting
link between the Greek age of Faith and that of Reason,
as he was also philosophically by the nature of his
doctrines. He offers us an easy passage from
the speculative methods of Plato to the scientific
methods of Archimedes and Euclid. The copiousness
of his doctrines, and the obscurity of many of them,
might, perhaps, discourage a superficial student,
unless he steadily bears in mind the singular authority
they maintained for so many ages, and the brilliant
results in all the exact parts of human knowledge
to which they so quickly led. The history of
Aristotle and his philosophy is therefore our necessary
introduction to the grand, the immortal achievements
of the Alexandrian school.
Aristotle was born at Stagira, in
Thrace, B.C. 384. His father was an eminent author
of those times on subjects of Natural History; by
profession he was a physician. Dying while his
son was yet quite young, he bequeathed to him not
only very ample means, but also his own tastes.
Aristotle soon found his way to Athens, and entered
the school of Plato, with whom it is said he remained
for nearly twenty years. During this period he
spent most of his patrimony, and in the end was obliged
to support himself by the trade of a druggist.
At length differences arose between them, for, as
we shall soon find, the great pupil was by no means
a blind follower of the great master. In a fortunate
moment, Philip, the King of Macedon, appointed him
preceptor to his son Alexander, an incident of importance
in the intellectual history of Europe. It was
to the friendship arising through this relation that
Aristotle owed the assistance he received from the
conqueror during his Asiatic expedition for the composition
of “the Natural History,” and also gained
that prestige which gave his name such singular authority
for more than fifteen centuries. He eventually
founded a school in the Lyceum at Athens, and, as
it was his habit to deliver his lectures while walking,
his disciples received the name of Peripatetics, or
walking philosophers. These lectures were of
two kinds, esoteric and exoteric, the former being
delivered to the more advanced pupils only. He
wrote a very large number of works, of which about
one-fourth remain.
The philosophical method of Aristotle
is the inverse of that of Plato, whose starting-point
was universals, the very existence of which was a
matter of faith, and from these he descended to particulars
or details. Aristotle, on the contrary, rose
from particulars to universals, advancing to them
by inductions; and his system, thus an inductive philosophy,
was in reality the true beginning of science.
Plato therefore trusts to the Imagination,
Aristotle to Reason. The contrast between them
is best seen by the attitude in which they stand as
respects the Ideal theory. Plato regards universals,
types, or exemplars as having an actual existence;
Aristotle declares that they are mere abstractions
of reasoning. For the fanciful reminiscences
derived from former experience in another life by Plato,
Aristotle substitutes the reminiscences of our actual
experience in this. These ideas of experience
are furnished by the memory, which enables us not
only to recall individual facts and events witnessed
by ourselves, but also to collate them with one another,
thereby discovering their resemblances and their differences.
Our induction becomes the more certain as our facts
are more numerous, our experience larger. “Art
commences when, from a great number of experiences,
one general conception is formed which will embrace
all similar cases.” “If we properly
observe celestial phenomena, we may demonstrate the
laws which regulate them.” With Plato,
philosophy arises from faith in the past; with Aristotle,
reason alone can constitute it from existing facts.
Plato is analytic, Aristotle synthetic. The philosophy
of Plato arises from the decomposition of a primitive
idea into particulars, that of Aristotle from the
union of particulars into a general conception.
The former is essentially an idealist, the latter
a materialist.
From this it will be seen that the
method of Plato was capable of producing more splendid,
though they were necessarily more unsubstantial results;
that of Aristotle was more tardy in its operation,
but much more solid. It implied endless labour
in the collection of facts, the tedious resort to
experiment and observation, the application of demonstration.
In its very nature it was such that it was impossible
for its author to carry by its aid the structure of
science to completion. The moment that Aristotle
applies his own principles we find him compelled to
depart from them through want of a sufficient experience
and sufficient precision in his facts. The philosophy
of Plato is a gorgeous castle in the air, that of
Aristotle is a solid structure, laboriously, and,
with many failures, founded on the solid rock.
Under Logic, Aristotle treats of the
methods of arriving at general propositions, and of
reasoning from them. His logic is at once the
art of thinking and the instrument of thought.
The completeness of our knowledge depends on the extent
and completeness of our experience. His manner
of reasoning is by the syllogism, an argument consisting
of three propositions, such that the concluding one
follows of necessity from the two premises, and of
which, indeed, the whole theory of demonstration is
only an example. Regarding logic as the instrument
of thought, he introduces into it, as a fundamental
feature, the ten categories. These predicaments
are the genera to which everything may be reduced,
and denote the most general of the attributes which
may be assigned to a thing.
His metaphysics overrides all the
branches of the physical sciences. It undertakes
an examination of the postulates on which each one
of them is founded, determining their truth or fallacy.
Considering that all science must find a support for
its fundamental conditions in an extensive induction
from facts, he puts at the foundation of his system
the consideration of the individual; in relation to
the world of sense, he regards four causes as necessary
for the production of a fact the material
cause, the substantial cause, the efficient cause,
the final cause.
But as soon as we come to the Physics
of Aristotle we see at once his weakness. The
knowledge of his age does not furnish him facts enough
whereon to build, and the consequence is that he is
forced into speculation. It will be sufficient
for our purpose to allude to a few of his statements,
either in this or in his metaphysical branch, to show
how great is his uncertainty and confusion. Thus
he asserts that matter contains a triple form simple
substance, higher substance, which is eternal, and
absolute substance, or God himself; that the universe
is immutable and eternal, and, though in relation
with the vicissitudes of the world, it is unaffected
thereby; that the primitive force which gives rise
to all the motions and changes we see is Nature; it
also gives rise to Rest; that the world is a living
being, having a soul; that, since every thing is for
some particular end, the soul of man is the end of
his body; that Motion is the condition of all nature;
that the world has a definite boundary and a limited
magnitude; that Space is the immovable vessel in which
whatever is may be moved; that Space, as a whole,
is without motion, though its parts may move; that
it is not to be conceived of as without contents;
that it is impossible for a vacuum to exist, and hence
there is not beyond and surrounding the world a void
which contains the world; that there could be no such
thing as Time unless there is a soul, for time being
the number of motion, number is impossible except
there be one who numbers; that, perpetual motion in
a finite right line being impossible, but in a curvilinear
path possible, the world, which is limited and ever
in motion, must be of a spherical form; that the earth
is its central part, the heavens the circumferential:
hence the heaven is nearest to the prime cause of
motion; that the orderly, continuous, and unceasing
movement of the celestial bodies implies an unmoved
mover, for the unchangeable alone can give birth to
uniform motion; that unmoved existence is God; that
the stars are passionless beings, having attained the
end of existence, and worthy above other things of
human adoration; that the fixed stars are in the outermost
heaven, and the sun, moon, and planets beneath:
the former receive their motion from the prime moving
cause, but the planets are disturbed by the stars;
that there are five elements earth, air,
fire, water, and ether; that the earth is in the centre
of the world, since earthy matter settles uniformly
round a central point; that fire seeks the circumferential
region, and intermediately water floats upon the earth,
and air upon water; that the elements are transmutable
into one another, and hence many intervening substances
arise; that each sphere is in interconnection with
the others; the earth is agitated and disturbed by
the sea, the sea by the winds, which are movements
of the air, the air by the sun, moon, and planets.
Each inferior sphere is controlled by its outlying
or superior one, and hence it follows that the earth,
which is thus disturbed by the conspiring or conflicting
action of all above it, is liable to the most irregularities;
that, since animals are nourished by the earth, it
needs must enter into their composition, but that
water is required to hold the earthy matters together;
that every element must be looked upon as living, since
it is pervaded by the soul of the world; that there
is an unbroken chain from the simple element through
the plant and animal up to man, the different groups
merging by insensible shades into one another:
thus zoophytes partake partly of the vegetable
and partly of the animal, and serve as an intermedium
between them; that plants are inferior to animals in
this, that they do not possess a single principle of
life or soul, but many subordinate ones, as is shown
by the circumstance that, when they are cut to pieces,
each piece is capable of perfect or independent growth
or life. Their inferiority is likewise betrayed
by their belonging especially to the earth to which
they are rooted, each root being a true mouth; and
this again displays their lowly position, for the
place of the mouth is ever an indication of the grade
of a creature: thus in man, who is at the head
of the scale, it is in the upper part of the body;
that in proportion to the heat of an animal is its
grade higher; thus those that are aquatic are cold,
and therefore of very little intelligence, and the
same maybe said of plants; but of man, whose warmth
is very great, the soul is much more excellent; that
the possession of locomotion by an organism always
implies the possession of sensation; that the senses
of taste and touch indicate the qualities of things
in contact with the organs of the animal, but that
those of smell, hearing, and sight extend the sphere
of its existence, and indicate to it what is at a
distance: that the place of reception of the
various sensations is the soul, from which issue forth
the motions; that the blood, as the general element
of nutrition, is essential to the support of the body,
though insensible itself: it is also essential
to the activity of the soul; that the brain is not
the recipient of sensations: that function belongs
to the heart; all the animal activities are united
in the last; it contains the principle of life, being
the principle of motion: it is the first part
to be formed and the last to die; that the brain is
a mere appendix to the heart, since it is formed after
the heart, is the coldest of the organs and is devoid
of blood; that the soul is the reunion of all the
functions of the body: it is an energy or active
essence; being neither body nor magnitude, it cannot
have extension, for thought has no parts, nor can it
be said to move in space; it is as a sailor, who is
motionless in a ship which is moving; that, in the
origin of the organism, the male furnishes the soul
and the female the body; that the body being liable
to decay, and of a transitory nature, it is necessary
for its well-being that its disintegration and nutrition
should balance one another; that sensation may be
compared to the impression of a seal on wax, the wax
receiving form only, but no substance or matter; that
imagination arises from impressions thus made, which
endure for a length of time, and that this is the
origin of memory; that man alone possesses recollection,
but animals share with him memory memory
being unintentional or spontaneous, but recollection
implying voluntary exertion or a search; that recollection
is necessary for acting with design. It is doubtful
whether Aristotle believed in the immortality of the
soul, no decisive passage to that effect occurring
in such of his works as are extant.
Aristotle, with a correct and scientific
method, tried to build up a vast system when he was
not in possession of the necessary data. Though
a very learned man, he had not sufficient knowledge;
indeed, there was not sufficient knowledge at that
time in the world. For many of the assertions
I have quoted in the preceding paragraph there was
no kind of proof; many of them also, such as the settling
of the heavy and the rise of the light, imply very
poor cosmic ideas. It is not until he deals with
those branches, such as comparative anatomy and natural
history, of which he had a personal and practical
knowledge, that he begins to write well. Of his
physiological conclusions, some are singularly felicitous;
his views of the connected chain of organic forms,
from the lowest to the highest, are very grand.
His metaphysical and physical speculations for
in reality they are nothing but speculations are
of no kind of value. His successful achievements,
and also his failures, conspicuously prove the excellence
of his system. He expounded the true principles
of science, but failed to apply them merely for want
of materials. His ambition could not brook restraint.
He would rather attempt to construct the universe
without the necessary means than not construct it
at all.
Aristotle failed when he abandoned
his own principles, and the magnitude of his failure
proves how just his principles were; he succeeded when
he adhered to them. If anything were wanting
to vindicate their correctness and illustrate them,
it is supplied by the glorious achievements of the
Alexandrian school, which acted in physical science
as Aristotle had acted in natural history, laying
a basis solidly in observation and experiment, and
accomplishing a like durable and brilliant result.
From Aristotle it is necessary to
turn to Zeno, for the Peripatetics and Stoics stand
in parallel lines. The social conditions existing
in Greece at the time of Epicurus may in some degree
palliate his sentiments, but virtue and honour will
make themselves felt at last. Stoicism soon appeared
as the antagonist of Epicureanism, and Epicurus found
in Zeno of Citium a rival. The passage from Epicurus
to Zeno is the passage from sensual gratification
to self-control.
The biography of Zeno may be dismissed
in a few words. Born about B.C. 300, he spent
the early part of his life in the vocation of his father,
who was a merchant, but, by a fortunate shipwreck,
happily losing his goods during a voyage he was making
to Athens, he turned to philosophy for consolation.
Though he had heretofore been somewhat acquainted with
the doctrines of Socrates, he became a disciple of
the Cynics, subsequently studying in the Megaric school,
and then making himself acquainted with Platonism.
After twenty years of preparation, he opened a school
in the stoa or porch in Athens, from which his doctrine
and disciples have received their name. He presided
over his school for fifty-eight years, numbering many
eminent men among his disciples. When nearly
a hundred years old he chanced to fall and break his
finger, and, receiving this as an admonition that
his time was accomplished, he forthwith strangled
himself. The Athenians erected to his memory a
statue of brass. His doctrines long survived him,
and, in times when there was no other consolation
for man, offered a support in their hour of trial,
and an unwavering guide in the vicissitudes of life,
not only to many illustrious Greeks, but also to some
of the great philosophers, statesmen, generals, and
emperors of Rome.
It was the intention of Zeno to substitute
for the visionary speculations of Platonism a system
directed to the daily practices of life, and hence
dealing chiefly with morals. To make men virtuous
was his aim. But this is essentially connected
with knowledge, for Zeno was persuaded that if we
only know what is good we shall be certain to practise
it. He therefore rejected Plato’s fancies
of Ideas and Reminiscences, leaning to the common-sense
doctrines of Aristotle, to whom he approached in many
details. With him Sense furnishes the data of
knowledge, and Reason combines them: the soul
being modified by external things, and modifying them
in return, he believed that the mind is at first,
as it were, a blank tablet, on which sensation writes
marks, and that the distinctness of sensuous impressions
is the criterion of their truth. The changes
thus produced in the soul constitute ideas; but, with
a prophetic inspiration, he complained that man will
never know the true essence of things.
In his Physics Zeno adopted the doctrine
of Strato, that the world is a living being.
He believed that nothing incorporeal can produce an
effect, and hence that the soul is corporeal.
Matter and its properties he considered to be absolutely
inseparable, a property being actually a body.
In the world there are two things, matter and God,
who is the Reason of the world. Essentially,
however, God and matter are the same thing, which
assumes the aspect of matter from the passive point
of view, and God from the active; he is, moreover,
the prime moving force, Destiny, Necessity, a life-giving
Soul, evolving things as the vital force evolves a
plant out of a seed; the visible world is thus to be
regarded as the material manifestation of God.
The transitory objects which it on all sides presents
will be reabsorbed after a season of time, and reunited
in him. The Stoics pretended to indicate, even
in a more definite manner, the process by which the
world has arisen, and also its future destiny; for,
regarding the Supreme as a vital heat, they supposed
that a portion of that fire, declining in energy, became
transmuted into matter, and hence the origin of the
world; but that that fire, hereafter resuming its
activity, would cause a universal conflagration, the
end of things. During the present state everything
is in a condition of uncertain mutation, decays being
followed by reproductions, and reproductions by decays;
and, as a cataract shows from year to year an invariable
form, though the water composing it is perpetually
changing, so the objects around us are nothing more
than a flux of matter offering a permanent form.
Thus the visible world is only a moment in the life
of God, and after it has vanished away like a scroll
that is burned, a new period shall be ushered in, and
a new heaven and a new earth, exactly like the ancient
ones, shall arise. Since nothing can exist without
its contrary, no injustice unless there was justice,
no cowardice unless there was courage, no lie unless
there was truth, no shadow unless there was light,
so the existence of good necessitates that of evil.
The Stoics believed that the development of the world
is under the dominion of paramount law, supreme law,
Destiny, to which God himself is subject, and that
hence he can only develop the world in a predestined
way, as the vital warmth evolves a seed into the predestined
form of a plant.
The Stoics held it indecorous to offend
needlessly the religious ideas of the times, and,
indeed, they admitted that there might be created
gods like those of Plato; but they disapproved of the
adoration of images and the use of temples, making
amends for their offences in these particulars by
offering a semi-philosophical interpretation of the
legends, and demonstrating that the existence, and
even phenomenal display of the gods was in accordance
with their principles. Perhaps to this exoteric
philosophy we must ascribe the manner in which they
expressed themselves as to final causes expressions
sometimes of amusing quaintness thus, that
the peacock was formed for the sake of his tail, and
that a soul was given to the hog instead of salt, to
prevent his body from rotting; that the final cause
of plants is to be food for brutes, of brutes to be
food for men, though they discreetly checked their
irony in its ascending career, and abstained from saying
that men are food for the gods, and the gods for all.
The Stoics concluded that the soul
is mere warm breath, and that it and the body mutually
interpervade one another. They thought that it
might subsist after death until the general conflagration,
particularly if its energy were great, as in the strong
spirits of the virtuous and wise. Its unity of
action implies that it has a principle of identity,
the I, of which the physiological seat is the heart.
Every appetite, lust, or desire is an imperfect knowledge.
Our nature and properties are forced upon us by Fate,
but it is our duty to despise all our propensities
and passions, and to live so that we may be free,
intelligent, and virtuous.
This sentiment leads us to the great
maxim of Stoical Ethics, “Live according to
Reason;” or, since the world is composed of matter
and God, who is the Reason of the world, “Live
in harmony with Nature.” As Reason is supreme
in Nature, it ought to be so in man. Our existence
should be intellectual, and all bodily pains and pleasures
should be despised. A harmony between the human
will and universal Reason constitutes virtue.
The free-will of the sage should guide his actions
in the same irresistible manner in which universal
Reason controls nature. Hence the necessity of
a cultivation of physics, without which we cannot
distinguish good from evil. The sage is directed
to remember that Nature, in her operations, aims at
the universal, and never spares individuals, but uses
them as means for accomplishing her ends. It is
for him, therefore, to submit to his destiny, endeavouring
continually to establish the supremacy of Reason,
and cultivating, as the things necessary to virtue,
knowledge, temperance, fortitude, justice. He
is at liberty to put patriotism at the value it is
worth when he remembers that he is a citizen of the
world; he must train himself to receive in tranquillity
the shocks of Destiny, and to be above all passion
and all pain. He must never relent and never
forgive. He must remember that there are only
two classes of men, the wise and the fools, as “sticks
can only either be straight or crooked, and very few
sticks in this world are absolutely straight.”
From the account I have given of Aristotle’s
philosophy, it may be seen that he occupied a middle
ground between the speculation of the old philosophy
and the strict science of the Alexandrian school.
He is the true connecting link, in the history of
European intellectual progress, between philosophy
and science. Under his teaching, and the material
tendencies of the Macedonian campaigns, there arose
a class of men in Egypt who gave to the practical
a development it had never before attained; for that
country, upon the breaking up of Alexander’s
dominion, B.C. 323, falling into the possession of
Ptolemy, that general found himself at once the depositary
of spiritual and temporal power. Of the former,
it is to be remembered that, though the conquest by
Cambyses had given it a severe shock, it still not
only survived, but displayed no inconsiderable tokens
of strength. Indeed, it is well known that the
surrender of Egypt to Alexander was greatly accelerated
by hatred to the Persians, the Egyptians welcoming
the Macedonians as their deliverers. In this
movement we perceive at once the authority of the old
priesthood. It is hard to tear up by the roots
an ancient religion, the ramifications of which have
solidly insinuated themselves among a populace.
That of Egypt had already been the growth of more than
three thousand years. The question for the intrusive
Greek sovereigns to solve was how to co-ordinate this
hoary system with the philosophical scepticism that
had issued as the result of Greek thought. With
singular sagacity, they saw that this might be accomplished
by availing themselves of Orientalism, the common
point of contact of the two systems; and that, by
its formal introduction and development, it would
be possible not only to enable the philosophical king,
to whom all the pagan gods were alike equally fictitious
and equally useful, to manifest respect even to the
ultra-heathenish practices of the Egyptian populace,
but, what was of far more moment, to establish an apparent
concord between the old sacerdotal Egyptian party strong
in its unparalleled antiquity; strong in its reminiscences;
strong in its recent persécutions; strong in
its Pharaonic relics, regarded by all men with a superstitious
or reverent awe and the free-thinking and
versatile Greeks. The occasion was like some
others in history, some even in our own times; a small
but energetic body of invaders was holding in subjection
an ancient and populous country.
To give practical force to this project,
a grand state institution was founded at Alexandria.
It became celebrated as the Museum. To it, as
to a centre, philosophers from all parts of the world
converged. It is said that at one time not less
than fourteen thousand students were assembled there.
Alexandria, in confirmation of the prophetic foresight
of the great soldier who founded it, quickly became
an immense metropolis, abounding in mercantile and
manufacturing activity. As is ever the case with
such cities, its higher classes were prodigal and dissipated,
its lower only to be held in restraint by armed force.
Its public amusements were such as might be expected theatrical
shows, music, horse-racing. In the solitude of
such a crowd, or in the noise of such dissipation,
anyone could find a retreat atheists who
had been banished from Athens, devotees from the Ganges,
monotheistic Jews, blasphemers from Asia Minor.
Indeed, it has been said that in this heterogeneous
community blasphemy was hardly looked upon as a crime;
at the worst, it was no more than an unfortunate,
and, it might be, an innocent mistake. But, since
uneducated men need some solid support on which their
thoughts may rest, mere abstract doctrines not meeting
their wants, it became necessary to provide a corporeal
representation for this eclectic philosophical Pantheism,
and hence the Ptolemies were obliged to restore, or,
as some say, to import the worship of the god Serapis.
Those who affirm that he was imported say that he was
brought from Sinope; modern Egyptian scholars,
however, give a different account. As setting
forth the Pantheistic doctrine of which he was the
emblem, his image, subsequently to attain world-wide
fame, was made of all kinds of metals and stones.
“All is God.” But still the people,
with that instinct which other nations and ages have
displayed, hankered after a female divinity, and this
led to the partial restoration of the worship of Isis.
It is interesting to remark how the humble classes
never shake off the reminiscences of early life, leaning
rather to the maternal than to the paternal attachment.
Perhaps it is for that reason that they expect a more
favourable attention to their supplications from
a female divinity than a god. Accordingly, the
devotees of Isis soon out-numbered those of Serapis,
though a magnificent temple had been built for him
at Rhacotis, in the quarter adjoining the Museum,
and his worship was celebrated with more than imperial
splendour. In subsequent ages the worship of
Serapis diffused itself throughout the Roman empire,
though the authorities consuls, senate,
emperors knowing well the idea it foreshadowed,
and the doctrine it was meant to imply, used their
utmost power to put it down.
The Alexandrian Museum soon assumed
the character of a University. In it those great
libraries were collected, the pride and boast of antiquity.
Demetrius Phalareus was instructed to collect all the
writings in the world. So powerfully were the
exertions of himself and his successors enforced by
the government that two immense libraries were procured.
They contained 700,000 volumes. In this literary
and scientific retreat, supported in ease and even
in luxury luxury, for allusions to the
sumptuous dinners have descended to our times the
philosophers spent their time in mental culture by
study, or mutual improvement by debates. The
king himself conferred appointments to these positions;
in later times, the Roman emperors succeeded to the
patronage, the government thereby binding in golden
chains intellect that might otherwise have proved
troublesome. At first, in honour of the ancient
religion, the presidency of the establishment was
committed to an Egyptian priest; but in the course
of time that policy was abandoned. It must not,
however, be imagined that the duties of the inmates
were limited to reading and rhetorical display; a
far more practical character was imparted to them.
A botanical garden, in connection with the Museum,
offered an opportunity to those who were interested
in the study of the nature of plants; a zoological
menagerie afforded like facilities to those interested
in animals. Even these costly establishments were
made to minister to the luxury of the times:
in the zoological garden pheasants were raised for
the royal table. Besides these elegant and fashionable
appointments, another, of a more forbidding and perhaps
repulsive kind, was added; an establishment which,
in the light of our times, is sufficient to confer
immortal glory on those illustrious and high-minded
kings, and to put to shame the ignorance and superstition
of many modern nations: it was an anatomical
school, suitably provided with means for the dissection
of the human body, this anatomical school being the
basis of a medical college for the education of physicians.
For the astronomers Ptolemy Euergetes placed in the
Square Porch an equinoctial and a solstitial armil,
the graduated limbs of these instruments being divided
into degrees and sixths. There were in the observatory
stone quadrants, the precursors of our mural quadrants.
On the floor a meridian line was drawn for the adjustment
of the instruments. There were also astrolabes
and dioptras. Thus, side by side, almost
in the king’s palace, were noble provisions
for the cultivation of exact science and for the pursuit
of light literature. Under the same roof were
gathered together geometers, astronomers, chemists,
mechanicians, engineers. There were also poets,
who ministered to the literary wants of the dissipated
city authors who could write verse, not
only in correct metre, but in all kinds of fantastic
forms trees, hearts, and eggs. Here
met together the literary dandy and the grim theologian.
At their repasts occasionally the king himself would
preside, enlivening the moment with the condescensions
of royal relaxation. Thus, of Philadelphus it
is stated that he caused to be presented to the Stoic
Sphaerus a dish of fruit made of wax, so beautifully
coloured as to be undistinguishable from the natural,
and on the mortified philosopher detecting too late
the fraud that had been practised upon him, inquired
what he now thought of the maxim of his sect that “the
sage is never deceived by appearances.”
Of the same sovereign it is related that he received
the translators of the Septuagint Bible with the highest
honours, entertaining them at his table. Under
the atmosphere of the place their usual religious
ceremonial was laid aside, save that the king courteously
requested one of the aged priests to offer an extempore
prayer. It is naively related that the Alexandrians
present, ever quick to discern rhetorical merit, testified
their estimation of the performance with loud applause.
But not alone did literature and the exact sciences
thus find protection. As if no subjects with which
the human mind has occupied itself can be unworthy
of investigation, in the Museum were cultivated the
more doubtful arts, magic and astrology. Philadelphus,
who, toward the close of his life, was haunted with
an intolerable dread of death, devoted himself with
intense assiduity to the discovery of the elixir of
life and to alchemy. Such a comprehensive organization
for the development of human knowledge never existed
in the world before, and, considering the circumstances,
never has since. To be connected with it was
the passport to the highest Alexandrian society and
to court favour.
To the Museum, and, it has been asserted,
particularly to Ptolemy Philadelphus, the Christian
world is thus under obligation for the ancient version
of the Hebrew Scriptures the Septuagint.
Many idle stories have been related respecting the
circumstances under which that version was made, as
that the seventy-two translators by whom it was executed
were confined each in a separate cell, and, when their
work was finished, the seventy-two copies were found
identically the same, word for word, from this it
was supposed that the inspiration of this translation
was established. If any proof of that kind were
needed, it would be much better found in the fact
that whenever occasion arises in the New Testament
of quoting from the Old, it is usually done in the
words of the Septuagint. The story of the cells
underwent successive improvements among the early
fathers, but is now rejected as a fiction; and, indeed,
it seems probable that the translation was not made
under the splendid circumstances commonly related,
but merely by the Alexandrian Jews for their own convenience.
As the Septuagint grew into credit among the Christians,
it lost favour among the Jews, who made repeated attempts
in after years to supplant it by new versions, such
as those of Aquila, of Theodotion, of Symmachus, and
others. From the first the Syrian Jews had looked
on it with disapproval; they even held the time of
its translation as a day of mourning, and with malicious
grief pointed out its errors, as, for instance, they
affirmed that it made Methusaleh live until after
the Deluge. Ptolemy treated all those who were
concerned in providing books for the library with consideration,
remunerating his translators and transcribers in a
princely manner.
But the modern world is not indebted
to these Egyptian kings only in the particular here
referred to. The Museum made an impression upon
the intellectual career of Europe so powerful and
enduring that we still enjoy its results. That
impression was twofold, theological and physical.
The dialectical spirit and literary culture diffused
among the Alexandrians prepared that people, beyond
all others, for the reception of Christianity.
For thirty centuries the Egyptians had been familiar
with the conception of a triune God. There was
hardly a city of any note without its particular triad.
Here it was Amun, Maut, and Khonso; there Osiris,
Isis, and Horus. The apostolic missionaries, when
they reached Alexandria, found a people ready to appreciate
the profoundest mysteries. But with these advantages
came great evils. The Trinitarian disputes, which
subsequently deluged the world with blood, had their
starting-point and focus in Alexandria. In that
city Arius and Athanasius dwelt. There originated
that desperate conflict which compelled Constantine
the Great to summon the Council of Nicea, to settle,
by a formulary or creed, the essentials of our faith.
But it was not alone as regards theology
that Alexandria exerted a power on subsequent ages;
her influence was as strongly marked in the impression
it gave to science. Astronomical observatories,
chemical laboratories, libraries, dissecting-houses,
were not in vain. There went forth from them
a spirit powerful enough to tincture all future times.
Nothing like the Alexandrian Museum was ever called
into existence in Greece or Rome, even in their palmiest
days. It is the unique and noble memorial of
the dynasty of the Ptolemies, who have thereby laid
the whole human race under obligations, and vindicated
their title to be regarded as a most illustrious line
of kings. The Museum was, in truth, an attempt
at the organization of human knowledge, both for its
development and its diffusion. It was conceived
and executed in a practical manner worthy of Alexander.
And though, in the night through which Europe has
been passing a night full of dreams and
delusions men have not entertained a right
estimate of the spirit in which that great institution
was founded, and the work it accomplished, its glories
being eclipsed by darker and more unworthy things,
the time is approaching when its action on the course
of human events will be better understood, and its
influences on European civilization more clearly discerned.
Thus, then, about the beginning of
the third century before Christ, in consequence of
the Macedonian campaign, which had brought the Greeks
into contact with the ancient civilization of Asia,
a great degree of intellectual activity was manifested
in Egypt. On the site of the village of Rhacotis,
once held as an Egyptian post to prevent the ingress
of strangers, the Macedonians erected that city which
was to be the entrepôt of the commerce of the
East and West, and to transmit an illustrious name
to the latest generations. Her long career of
commercial prosperity, her commanding position as respects
the material interests of the world, justified the
statesmanship of her founder, and the intellectual
glory which has gathered round her has given an enduring
lustre to his name.
There can be no doubt that the philosophical
activity here alluded to was the direct issue of the
political and military event to which we have referred
it. The tastes and genius of Alexander were manifested
by his relations to Aristotle, whose studies in natural
history he promoted by the collection of a menagerie;
and in astronomy, by transmitting to him, through
Callisthenes, the records of Babylonian observations
extending over 1903 years. His biography, as we
have seen, shows a personal interest in the cultivation
of such studies. In this particular other great
soldiers have resembled him; and perhaps it may be
inferred that the practical habit of thought and accommodation
of theory to the actual purposes of life pre-eminently
required by their profession, leads them spontaneously
to decline speculative uncertainties, and to be satisfied
only with things that are real and exact.
Under the inspiration of the system
of Alexander, and guided by the suggestions of certain
great men who had caught the spirit of the times,
the Egyptian kings thus created, under their own immediate
auspices, the Museum. State policy, operating
in the manner I have previously described, furnished
them with an additional theological reason for founding
this establishment. In the Macedonian campaign
a vast amount of engineering and mathematical talent
had been necessarily stimulated into existence, for
great armies cannot be handled, great marches cannot
be made, nor great battles fought without that result.
When the period of energetic action was over, and
to the military operations succeeded comparative repose
and temporary moments of peace, the talent thus called
forth found occupation in the way most congenial to
it by cultivating mathematical and physical studies.
In Alexandria, itself a monument of engineering and
architectural skill, soon were to be found men whose
names were destined for futurity Apollonius,
Eratosthenes, Manetho. Of these, one may be selected
for the remark that, while speculative philosophers
were occupying themselves with discussions respecting
the criterion of truth, and, upon the whole, coming
to the conclusion that no such thing existed, and
that, if the truth was actually in the possession
of man, he had no means of knowing it, Euclid of Alexandria
was writing an immortal work, destined to challenge
contradiction from the whole human race, and to make
good its title as the representative of absolute and
undeniable truth truth not to be gainsaid
in any nation or at any time. We still use the
geometry of Euclid in our schools.
It is said that Euclid opened a geometrical
school in Alexandria about B.C. 300. He occupied
himself not only with mathematical, but also with
physical investigation. Besides many works of
the former class supposed to have been written by
him, as on Fallacies, Conic Sections, Divisions, Porisms,
Data, there are imputed to him treatises on Harmonics,
Optics, and Catoptrics, the two latter subjects being
discussed, agreeably to the views of those times,
on the hypothesis of rays issuing from the eye to
the object, instead of passing, as we consider them
to do, from the object to the eye. It is, however,
on the excellencies of his Elements of Geometry that
the durable reputation of Euclid depends; and though
the hypercriticism of modern mathematicians has perhaps
successfully maintained such objections against them
as that they might have been more precise in their
axioms, that they sometimes assume what might be proved,
that they are occasionally redundant, and their arrangement
sometimes imperfect, yet they still maintain their
ground as a model of extreme accuracy, of perspicuity,
and as a standard of exact demonstration. They
were employed universally by the Greeks, and, in subsequent
ages, were translated and preserved by the Arabs.
Great as is the fame of Euclid, it
is eclipsed by that of Archimedes the Syracusan, born
B.C. 287, whose connection with Egyptian science is
not alone testified by tradition, but also by such
facts as his acknowledged friendship with Conon of
Alexandria, and his invention of the screw still bearing
his name, intended for raising the waters of the Nile.
Among his mathematical works, the most interesting,
perhaps, in his own estimation, as we may judge from
the incident that he directed the diagram thereof
to be engraved on his tombstone, was his demonstration
that the solid content of a sphere is two-thirds that
of its circumscribing cylinder. It was by this
mark that Cicero, when Quaestor of Sicily, discovered
the tomb of Archimedes grown over with weeds.
This theorem was, however, only one of a large number
of a like kind, which he treated of in his two books
on the sphere and cylinder in an equally masterly
manner, and with equal success. His position as
a geometer is perhaps better understood from the assertion
made respecting him by a modern mathematician, that
he came as near to the discovery of the Differential
Calculus as can be done without the aid of algebraic
transformations. Among the special problems he
treated of may be mentioned the quadrature of the
circle, his determination of the ratio of the circumference
to the diameter being between: 3.1428 and 3.1408,
the true value, as is now known, being 3.1416 nearly.
He also wrote on Conoids and Spheroids, and upon that
spiral still passing under his name, the genesis of
which had been suggested to him by Conon. In his
work entitled “Psammites” he alludes to
the astronomical system subsequently established by
Copernicus, whose name has been given to it.
He also mentions the attempts which had been made to
measure the size of the earth; the chief object of
the work being, however, to prove not only that the
sands upon the sea-shore can be numbered, but even
those required to fill the entire space within the
sphere of the fixed stars; the result being, according
to our system of arithmetic, a less number than is
expressed by unity followed by 63 ciphers. Such
a book is the sport of a geometrical giant wantonly
amusing himself with his strength. Among his
mathematical investigations must not be omitted the
quadrature of the parabola. His fame depends,
however, not so much on his mathematical triumphs
as upon his brilliant discoveries in physics and his
mechanical inventions. How he laid the foundation
of Hydrostatics is familiar to everyone, through the
story of Hiero’s crown. A certain artisan
having adulterated the gold given him by King Hiero
to form a crown, Archimedes discovered while he was
accidentally stepping into a bath, that the falsification
might be detected, and thereby invented the method
for the determination of specific gravity. From
these investigations he was naturally led to the consideration
of the equilibrium of floating bodies; but his grand
achievement in the mechanical direction was his discovery
of the true theory of the lever: his surprising
merit in these respects is demonstrated by the fact
that no advance was made in theoretical mechanics
during the eighteen centuries intervening between
him and Leonardo da Vinci. Of minor
matters not fewer than forty mechanical inventions
have been attributed to him. Among these are
the endless screw, the screw pump, a hydraulic organ,
and burning mirrors. His genius is well indicated
by the saying popularly attributed to him, “Give
me whereon to stand, and I will move the earth,”
and by the anecdotes told of his exertions against
Marcellus during the siege of Syracuse; his invention
of catapults and other engines for throwing projectiles,
as darts and heavy stones, claws which, reaching over
the walls, lifted up into the air ships and their
crews, and then suddenly dropped them into the sea;
burning mirrors, by which, at a great distance, the
Roman fleet was set on fire. It is related that
Marcellus, honouring his intellect, gave the strictest
orders that no harm should be done to him at the taking
of the town, and that he was killed, unfortunately,
by an ignorant soldier unfortunately, for
Europe was not able to produce his equal for nearly
two thousand years.
Eratosthenes was contemporary with
Archimedes. He was born at Cyrene, B.C. 276.
The care of the library appears to have been committed
to him by Euergetes; but his attention was more specially
directed to mathematical, astronomical, geographical,
and historical pursuits. The work entitled “Catasterisms,”
doubtfully imputed to him, is a catalogue of 475 of
the principal stars; but it was probably intended for
nothing more than a manual. He also is said to
have written a poem upon terrestrial zones. Among
his important geographical labours may be mentioned
his determination of the interval between the tropics.
He found it to be eleven eighty-thirds of the circumference.
He also attempted the measurement of the size of the
earth by ascertaining the distance between Alexandria
and Syene, the difference of latitude between which
he had found to be one-fiftieth of the earth’s
circumference. It was his object to free geography
from the legends with which the superstition of ages
had adorned and oppressed it. In effecting this
he well deserves the tribute paid to him by Humboldt,
the modern who of all others could best appreciate
his labours. He considered the articulation and
expansion of continents; the position of mountain
chains; the action of clouds; the geological submersion
of lands; the elevation of ancient sea-beds; the opening
of the Dardanelles and of the Straits of Gibraltar;
the relations of the Euxine Sea; the problem of the
equal level of the circumfluous ocean; and the necessary
existence of a mountain chain running through Asia
in the diaphragm of Dicaearchus. What an advance
is all this beyond the meditations of Thales!
Herein we see the practical tendencies of the Macedonian
wars. In his astronomical observations he had
the advantage of using the armils and other instruments
in the Observatory. He ascertained that the direction
of terrestrial gravity is not constant, but that the
verticals converge. He composed a complete systematic
description of the earth in three books physical,
mathematical, historical accompanied by
a map of all the parts then known. Of his skill
as a geometer, his solution of the problem of two
mean proportionals, still extant, offers ample evidence;
and it is only of late years that the fragments remaining
of his Chronicles of the Theban Kings have been properly
appreciated. He hoped to free history as well
as geography from the myths that deform it, a task
which the prejudices and interests of man will never
permit to be accomplished. Some amusing anecdotes
of his opinions in these respects have descended to
us. He ventured to doubt the historical truth
of the Homeric legends. “I will believe
in it when I have been shown the currier who made
the wind-bags which Ulysses on his homeward voyage
received from Aeolus.” It is said that,
having attained the age of eighty years, he became
weary of life, and put an end to himself by voluntary
starvation.
I shall here pause to make a few remarks
suggested by the chronological and astronomical works
of Eratosthenes. Our current chronology was the
offspring of erroneous theological considerations,
the nature of which required not only a short historical
term for the various nations of antiquity, but even
for the existence of man upon the globe. This
necessity appears to have been chiefly experienced
in the attempt to exalt certain facts in the history
of the Hebrews from their subordinate position in
human affairs, and, indeed, to give the whole of that
history an exaggerated value. This was done in
a double way: by elevating Hebrew history from
its true grade, and depreciating or falsifying that
of other nations. Among those who have been guilty
of this literary offence, the name of the celebrated
Eusebius, the Bishop of Caesarea in the time of Constantine,
should be designated, since in his chronography and
synchronal tables he purposely “perverted chronology
for the sake of making synchronisms” (Bunsen).
It is true, as Niebuhr asserts, “He is a very
dishonest writer.” To a great extent, the
superseding of the Egyptian annals was brought about
by his influence. It was forgotten, however,
that of all things chronology is the least suited
to be an object of inspiration; and that, though men
may be wholly indifferent to truth for its own sake,
and consider it not improper to wrest it unscrupulously
to what they may suppose to be a just purpose, yet
that it will vindicate itself at last. It is
impossible to succeed completely in perverting the
history of a nation which has left numerous enduring
records. Egypt offers us testimonials reaching
over five thousand years. As Bunsen remarks, from
the known portion of the curve of history we may determine
the whole. The Egyptians, old as they are, belong
to the middle ages of mankind, for there is a period
antecedent to monumental history, or indeed, to history
of any kind, during which language and mythology are
formed, for these must exist prior to all political
institutions, all art, all science. Even at the
first moment that we gain a glimpse of the state of
Egypt she had attained a high intellectual condition,
as is proved by the fact that her system of hieroglyphics
was perfected before the fourth dynasty. It continued
unchanged until the time of Psammetichus. A stationary
condition of language and writing for thousands of
years necessarily implies a long and very remote period
of active improvement and advance. It was doubtless
such a general consideration, rather than a positive
knowledge of the fact, which led the Greeks to assert
that the introduction of geometry into Egypt must
be attributed to kings before the times of Menes.
Not alone do her artificial monuments attest for that
country an extreme antiquity; she is herself her own
witness; for, though the Nile raises its bed only
four feet in a thousand years, all the alluvial portion
of Egypt has been deposited from the waters of that
river. A natural register thus re-enforces the
written records, and both together compose a body
of evidence not to be gainsaid. Thus the depth
of muddy silt accumulated round the pedestals of monuments
is an irreproachable index of their age. In the
eminent position he occupied, Eusebius might succeed
in perverting the received book-chronology; but he
had no power to make the endless trade-wind that sweeps
over the tropical Pacific blow a day more or a day
less; none to change the weight of water precipitated
from it by the African mountains; none to arrest the
annual mass of mud brought down by the river.
It is by collating such different orders of evidence
together the natural and the monumental,
the latter gaining strength every year from the cultivation
of hieroglyphic studies that we begin to
discern the true Egyptian chronology, and to put confidence
in the fragments that remain of Eratosthenes and Manetho.
At the time of which we are speaking the
time of Eratosthenes general ideas had
been attained to respecting the doctrine of the sphere,
its poles, axis, the equator, arctic and antarctic
circles, equinoctial points, solstices, colures,
horizon, etc. No one competent to form an
opinion any longer entertained a doubt respecting the
globular form of the earth, the arguments adduced
in support of that fact being such as are still popularly
resorted to the different positions of the
horizon at different places, the changes in elevation
of the pole, the phenomena of eclipses, and the gradual
disappearance of ships as they sail from us.
As to eclipses, once looked upon with superstitious
awe, their true causes had not only been assigned,
but their periodicities so well ascertained that predictions
of their occurrence could be made. The Babylonians
had thus long known that after a cycle of 223 lunations
the eclipses of the moon return. The mechanism
of the phases of that satellite was clearly understood.
Indeed, Aristarchus of Samos attempted to ascertain
the distance of the sun from the earth on the principle
of observing the moon when she is dichotomized, a
method quite significant of the knowledge of the time,
though in practice untrustworthy; Aristarchus thus
finding that the sun’s distance is eighteen times
that of the moon, whereas it is in reality 400.
In like manner, in a general way, pretty clear notions
were entertained of the climatic distribution of heat
upon the earth, exaggerated, however, in this respect,
that the torrid zone was believed to be too hot for
human life, and the frigid too cold. Observations,
as good as could be made by simple instruments, had
not only demonstrated in a general manner the progressions,
retrogradations and stations of the planets, but attempts
had been made to account for, or rather to represent
them, by the aid of epicycles.
It was thus in Alexandria, under the
Ptolemies, that modern astronomy arose. Ptolemy
Soter, the founder of this line of kings, was not only
a patron of science, but likewise an author.
He composed a history of the campaigns of Alexander.
Under him the collection of the library was commenced,
probably soon after the defeat of Antigonus at the
battle of Ipsus, B.C. 301. The museum is due
to his son Ptolemy Philadelphus, who not only patronized
learning in his own dominions, but likewise endeavoured
to extend the boundaries of human knowledge in other
quarters. Thus he sent an expedition under his
admiral Timosthenes as far as Madagascar. Of
the succeeding Ptolemies, Euergetes and Philopator
were both very able men, though the later was a bad
one; he murdered his father, and perpetrated many
horrors in Alexandria. Épiphanes, succeeding
his father when only five years old, was placed by
his guardians under the protection of Rome, thus furnishing
to the ambitious republic a pretence for interfering
in the affairs of Egypt. The same policy was
continued during the reign of his son Philometor, who,
upon the whole, was an able and good king. Even
Physcon, who succeeded in B.C. 146, and who is described
as sensual, corpulent, and cruel cruel,
for he cut off the head, hands, and feet of his son,
and sent them to Cleopatra his wife could
not resist the inspirations to which the policy of
his ancestors, continued for nearly two centuries,
had given birth, but was an effective promoter of
literature and the arts, and himself the author of
an historical work. A like inclination was displayed
by his successors, Lathyrus and Auletes, the name of
the latter indicating his proficiency in music.
The surnames under which all these Ptolemies pass
were nicknames, or titles of derision imposed upon
them by their giddy and satirical Alexandrian subjects.
The political state of Alexandria was significantly
said to be a tyranny tempered by ridicule. The
dynasty ended in the person of the celebrated Cleopatra,
who, after the battle of Actium, caused herself, as
is related in the legends, to be bitten by an asp.
She took poison that she might not fall captive to
Octavianus, and be led in his triumph through the streets
of Rome.
If we possessed a complete and unbiased
history of these Greek kings, it would doubtless uphold
their title to be regarded as the most illustrious
of all ancient sovereigns. Even after their political
power had passed into the hands of the Romans a
nation who had no regard to truth and to right and
philosophy, in its old age, had become extinguished
or eclipsed by the faith of the later Caesars, enforced
by an unscrupulous use of their power, so strong was
the vitality of the intellectual germ they had fostered,
that, though compelled to lie dormant for centuries,
it shot up vigorously on the first occasion that favouring
circumstances allowed.
This Egyptian dynasty extended its
protection and patronage to literature as well as
to science. Thus Philadelphus did not consider
it beneath him to count among his personal friends
the poet Callimachus, who had written a treatise on
birds, and honourably maintained himself by keeping
a school in Alexandria. The court of that sovereign
was, moreover, adorned by a constellation of seven
poets, to which the gay Alexandrians gave the nickname
of the Pleiades. They are said to have been Lycophron,
Theocritus, Callimachus, Aratus, Apollonius Rhodius,
Nicander, and Homer the son of Macro. Among them
may be distinguished Lycophron, whose work, entitled
Cassandra, still remains; and Theocritus, whose exquisite
bucolics prove how sweet a poet he was.
To return to the scientific movement.
The school of Euclid was worthily represented in the
time of Euergetes by Apollonius Pergaeus, forty
years later than Archimedes. He excelled both
in the mathematical and physical department.
His chief work was a treatise on Conic Sections.
It is said that he was the first to introduce the
words ellipse and hyperbola. So late as the eleventh
century his complete works were extant in Arabic.
Modern geometers describe him as handling his subjects
with less power than his great predecessor Archimedes,
but nevertheless displaying extreme precision and
beauty in his methods. His fifth book, on Maxima
and Minima, is to be regarded as one of the highest
efforts of Greek geometry. As an example of his
physical inquiries may be mentioned his invention
of a clock.
Fifty years after Apollonius,
B.C. 160-125, we meet with the great astronomer Hipparchus.
He does not appear to have made observations himself
in Alexandria, but he uses those of Aristyllus and
Timochares of that place. Indeed, his great discovery
of the precession of the équinoxes was essentially
founded on the discussion of the Alexandrian observations
on Spica Virginis made by Timochares.
In pure mathematics he gave methods for solving all
triangles plane and spherical: he also constructed
a table of chords. In astronomy, besides his capital
discovery of the precession of the équinoxes just
mentioned, he also determined the first inequality
of the moon, the equation of the centre, and all but
anticipated Ptolemy in the discovery of the evection.
To him also must be attributed the establishment of
the theory of epicycles and eccentrics, a geometrical
conception for the purpose of resolving the apparent
motions of the heavenly bodies, on the principle of
circular movement. In the case of the sun and
moon, Hipparchus succeeded in the application of that
theory, and indicated that it might be adapted to
the planets. Though never intended as a representation
of the actual motions of the heavenly bodies, it maintained
its ground until the era of Kepler and Newton, when
the heliocentric doctrine, and that of elliptic motions,
were incontestably established. Even Newton himself,
in the 37th proposition of the third book of the “Principia,”
availed himself of its aid. Hipparchus also undertook
to make a register of the stars by the method of alineations that
is, by indicating those which were in the same apparent
straight line. The number of stars catalogued
by him was 1,080. If he thus depicted the aspect
of the sky for his times, he also endeavoured to do
the same for the surface of the earth by marking the
position of towns and other places by lines of latitude
and longitude.
Subsequently to Hipparchus, we find
the astronomers Geminus and Cleomedes; their
fame, however, is totally eclipsed by that of Ptolemy,
A.D. 138, the author of the great work “Syntaxis,”
or the mathematical construction of the heavens a
work fully deserving the epithet which has been bestowed
upon it, “a noble exposition of the mathematical
theory of epicycles and eccentrics.” It
was translated by the Arabians after the Mohammedan
conquest of Egypt; and, under the title of Almagest,
was received by them as the highest authority on the
mechanism and phenomena of the universe. It maintained
its ground in Europe in the same eminent position
for nearly fifteen hundred years, justifying the encomium
of Synesius on the institution which gave it birth,
“the divine school of Alexandria.”
The Almagest commences with the doctrine that the
earth is globular and fixed in space; it describes
the construction of a table of chords and instruments
for observing the solstices, and deduces the
obliquity of the ecliptic. It finds terrestrial
latitudes by the gnomon; describes climates; shows
how ordinary may be converted into sidereal time;
gives reasons for preferring the tropical to the sidereal
year; furnishes the solar theory on the principle of
the sun’s orbit being a simple eccentric; explains
the equation of time; advances to the discussion of
the motions of the moon; treats of the first inequality,
of her eclipses, and the motion of the node. It
then gives Ptolemy’s own great discovery that
which has made his name immortal the discovery
of the moon’s evection or second inequality,
reducing it to the epicyclic theory. It attempts
the determination of the distances of the sun and
moon from the earth, with, however, only partial success,
since it makes the sun’s distance but one-twentieth
of the real amount. It considers the precession
of the équinoxes, the discovery of Hipparchus,
the full period for which is twenty-five thousand
years. It gives a catalogue of 1,022 stars; treats
of the nature of the Milky Way; and discusses, in
the most masterly manner, the motions of the planets.
This point constitutes Ptolemy’s second claim
to scientific fame. His determination of the
planetary orbits was accomplished by comparing his
own observations with those of former astronomers,
especially with those of Timochares on Venus.
To Ptolemy we are also indebted for
a work on Geography used in European schools as late
as the fifteenth century. The known world to him
was from the Canary Islands eastward to China, and
from the equator northward to Caledonia. His
maps, however, are very erroneous; for, in the attempt
to make them correspond to the spherical figure of
the earth, the longitudes are too much to the east;
the Mediterranean Sea is twenty degrees too long.
Ptolemy’s determinations are, therefore, inferior
in accuracy to those of his illustrious predecessor
Eratosthenes, who made the distance from the sacred
promontory in Spain to the eastern mouth of the Ganges
to be seventy thousand stadia. Ptolemy also wrote
on Optics, the Planisphere, and Astrology. It
is not often given to an author to endure for so many
ages; perhaps, indeed, few deserve it. The mechanism
of the heavens, from his point of view, has however,
been greatly misunderstood. Neither he nor Hipparchus
ever intended that theory as anything more than a
geometrical fiction. It is not to be regarded
as a representation of the actual celestial motions.
And, as might be expected, for such is the destiny
of all unreal abstractions, the theory kept advancing
in complexity as facts accumulated, and was on the
point of becoming altogether unmanageable, when it
was supplanted by the theory of universal gravitation,
which has ever exhibited the inalienable attribute
of a true theory affording an explanation
of every new fact as soon as it was discovered, without
requiring to be burdened with new provisions, and prophetically
foretelling phenomena which had not as yet been observed.
From the time of the Ptolemies the
scientific spirit of the Alexandrian school declined;
for though such mathematicians as Theodosius, whose
work on Spherical Geometry was greatly valued by the
Arab geometers; and Pappus, whose mathematical collections,
in eight books, still for the most part remain; and
Theon, doubly celebrated for his geometrical attainments,
and as being the father of the unfortunate Hypatia,
A.D. 415, lived in the next three centuries, they
were not men like their great predecessors. That
mental strength which gives birth to original discovery
had passed away. The commentator had succeeded
to the philosopher. No new development illustrated
the physical sciences; they were destined long to
remain stationary. Mechanics could boast of no
trophy like the proposition of Archimedes on the equilibrium
of the lever; no new and exact ideas like those of
the same great man on statical and hydrostatical pressure;
no novel and clear views like those developed in his
treatise on floating bodies; no mechanical invention
like the first of all steam-engines that
of Hero. Natural Philosophy had come to a stop.
Its great, and hitherto successfully cultivated department,
Astronomy, exhibited no farther advance. Men were
content with what had been done, and continued to
amuse themselves with reconciling the celestial phenomena
to a combination of equable circular motions.
To what are we to attribute this pause? Something
had occurred to enervate the spirit of science.
A gloom had settled on the Museum.
There is no difficulty in giving an
explanation of this unfortunate condition. Greek
intellectual life had passed the period of its maturity,
and was entering on old age. Moreover, the talent
which might have been devoted to the service of science
was in part allured to another pursuit, and in part
repressed. Alexandria had sapped Athens, and
in her turn Alexandria was sapped by Rome. From
metropolitan pre-eminence she had sunk to be a mere
provincial town. The great prizes of life were
not so likely to be met with in such a declining city
as in Italy or, subsequently, in Constantinople.
Whatever affected these chief centres of Roman activity,
necessarily influenced her; but, such is the fate
of the conquered, she must await their decisions.
In the very institutions by which she had once been
glorified, success could only be attained by a conformity
to the manner of thinking fashionable in the imperial
metropolis, and the best that could be done was to
seek distinction in the path so marked out. Yet
even with all this restraint Alexandria asserted her
intellectual power, leaving an indelible impress on
the new theology of her conquerors. During three
centuries the intellectual atmosphere of the Roman
empire had been changing. Men were unable to
resist the steadily increasing pressure. Tranquillity
could only be secured by passiveness. Things
had come to such a state that the thinking of men
was to be done for them by others, or, if they thought
at all, it must be in accordance with a prescribed
formula or rule. Greek intellect was passing
into decrepitude, and the moral condition of the European
world was in antagonism to scientific progress.