This dialogue presents us with an
account of the manner In which Socrates spent the
last day of his, life, and how he met his death.
The main subject is that of the soul’s immortality,
which Socrates takes upon himself to prove with as
much certainty as it is possible for the human mind
to arrive at. The question itself, though none
could be better suited to the occasion, arises simply
and naturally from the general conversation that precedes
it.
When his friends visit him in the
morning for the purpose of spending this his last
day with him, they find him sitting up in bed, and
rubbing his leg, which had just been freed from bonds.
He remarks on the unaccountable alternation and connection
between pleasure and pain, and adds that AEsop, had
he observed it, would have made a fable from it.
This remark reminds Cebes of Socrates’s having
put some of AEsop’s fables into metre since
his imprisonment, and he asks, for the satisfaction
of the poet Evenus, what has induced him to do so.
Socrates explains his reason, and concludes by bidding
him tell Evenus to follow him as soon as he can.
Simmias expresses his surprise at this message, on
which Socrates asks, “Is not Evenus a philosopher?”
and on the question being answered in the affirmative,
he says that he or any philosopher would be willing
to die, though perhaps he would not commit violence
on himself. This, again, seems a contradiction
to Simmias; but Socrates explains it by showing that
our souls are placed in the body by God, and may not
leave it without his permission. Whereupon Cebes
objects that in that case foolish men only would wish
to die, and quit the service of the best of masters,
to which Simmias agrees. Socrates, therefore,
proposes to plead his cause before them, and to show
that there is a great probability that after this
life he shall go into the presence of God and good
men, and be happy in proportion to the purity of his
own mind.
He begins by stating that philosophy
itself is nothing else than a preparation for and
meditation on death. Death and philosophy have
this in common: death separates the soul from
the body; philosophy draws off the mind from bodily
things to the contemplation of truth and virtue:
for he is not a true philosopher who is led away by
bodily pleasures, since the senses are the source
of ignorance and all evil. The mind, therefore,
is entirely occupied in meditating on death, and freeing
itself as much as possible from the body. How,
then, can such a man be afraid of death? He who
grieves at the approach of death can not be a true
lover of wisdom, but is a lover of his body. And,
indeed, most men are temperate through intemperance;
that is to say, they abstain from some pleasures that
they may the more easily and permanently enjoy others.
They embrace only a shadow of virtue, not virtue itself,
since they estimate the value of all things by the
pleasures they afford. Whereas the philosopher
purifies his mind from all such things, and pursues
virtue and wisdom for their own sakes. This course
Socrates himself has pursued to the utmost of his
ability, with what success he should shortly know;
and on these grounds he did not repine at leaving
his friends in this world, being persuaded that in
another he should meet with good masters and good
friends.
Upon this Cebes says that he agrees
with all else that had been said, but can not help
entertaining doubts of what will become of the soul
when separated from the body, for the common opinion
is that it is dispersed and vanishes like breath or
smoke, and no longer exists anywhere. Socrates,
therefore, proposes to inquire into the probability
of the case, a fit employment for him under his present
circumstances.
His first argument is drawn from
the ancient belief prevalent among men, that souls
departing hence exist in Hades, and are produced again
from the dead. If this be true, it must follow
that our souls are there, for they could not be produced
again if they did not exist; and its truth is confirmed
by this, that it is a general law of nature that contraries
are produced from contraries the greater
from the less, strong from weak, slow from swift,
heat from cold, and in like manner life from death,
and vice versa. To explain this more clearly,
he proceeds to show that what is changed passes from
one state to another, and so undergoes three different
states first, the actual state; then the
transition; and, thirdly, the new state; as from a
state of sleep, by awaking to being awake. In
like manner birth is a transition from a state of
death to life, and dying from life to death; so that
the soul, by the act of dying, only passes to another
state. If it were not so, all nature would in
time become dead, just as if people did not awake
out of sleep all would at last be buried in eternal
sleep. Whence the conclusion is that the souls
of men are not annihilated by death.
Cebes agrees to this reasoning,
and adds that he is further convinced, of its truth
by calling to mind an argument used by Socrates on
former occasions, that knowledge is nothing but reminiscence;
and if this is so, the soul must have existed, and
had knowledge, before it became united to the body.
But in case Simmias should not yet
be satisfied, Socrates proceeds to enlarge on
this, his second argument, drawn from reminiscence.
We daily find that we are carried from the knowledge
of one thing to another. Things perceived by
the eyes, ears, and other senses bring up the thought
of other things; thus the sight of a lyre or a garment
reminds us of a friend, and not only are we thus reminded
of sensible objects, but of things which are comprehended
by the mind alone, and have no sensitive existence.
For we have formed in our minds an idea of abstract
equality, of the beautiful, the just, the good; in
short, of every thing which we say exists without
the aid of the senses, for we use them only in the
perception of individual things; whence it follows
that the mind did not acquire this knowledge in this
life, but must have had it before, and therefore the
soul must have existed before.
Simmias and Cebes both agree in
admitting that Socrates has proved the pre-existence
of the soul, but insist that he has not shown it to
be immortal, for that nothing hinders but that, according
to the popular opinion, it may be dispersed at the
dissolution of the body. To which Socrates replies,
that if their former admissions are joined to his last
argument, the immortality, as well as the pre-existence,
of the soul has been sufficiently proved. For
if it is true that any thing living is produced from
that which is dead, then the soul must exist after
death, otherwise it could not be produced again.
However, to remove the apprehension
that the soul may be dispersed by a wind, as it were,
Socrates proceeds, in his third argument, to examine
that doubt more thoroughly. What, then, is meant
by being dispersed but being dissolved into its parts?
In order, therefore, to a thing being capable of dispersion
it must be compounded of parts. Now, there are
two kinds of things one compounded, the
other simple The former kind is subject to change,
the latter not, and can be comprehended by the mind
alone. The one is visible, the other invisible;
and the soul, which is invisible, when it employs the
bodily senses, wanders and is confused, but when it
abstracts itself from the body it attains to the knowledge
of that which is eternal, immortal, and unchangeable.
The soul, therefore, being uncompounded and invisible,
must be indissoluble; that is to say, immortal.
Still Simmias and Cebes are unconvinced.
The former objects that the soul, according to Socrates’s
own showing, is nothing but a harmony resulting from
a combination of the parts of the body, and so may
perish with the body, as the harmony of a lyre does
when the lyre itself is broken. And Cebes, though
he admits that the soul is more durable than the body,
yet objects that it is not, therefore, of necessity
immortal, but may in time wear out; and it is by no
means clear that this is not its last period.
These objections produce a powerful
effect on the rest of the company; but Socrates, undismayed,
exhorts them not to suffer themselves to be deterred
from seeking the truth by any difficulties they may
meet with; and then proceeds to show, in a moment,
the fallacy of Simmias’s objection. It
was before admitted, he says, that the soul existed
before the body; but harmony is produced after the
lyre is formed, so that the two cases are totally
different. And, further, there are various degrees
of harmony, but every soul is as much a soul as any
other. But, then, what will a person who holds
this doctrine, that the soul is harmony, say of virtue
and vice in the soul? Will he call them another
kind of harmony and discord? If so, he will contradict
himself; for it is admitted that one soul is not more
or less a soul than another, and therefore one can
not he more or less harmonized than another, and one
could not admit of a greater degree of virtue or vice
than another; and indeed a soul, being harmony, could
not partake of vice at all, which is discord.
Socrates, having thus satisfactorily
answered the argument adduced by Simmias, goes on
to rebut that of Cebes, who objected that the soul
might in time wear out. In order to do this, he
relates that, when a young man, he attempted to investigate
the causes of all things, why they exist and why they
perish; and in the course of his researches, finding
the futility of attributing the existence of things
to what are called natural causes, he resolved on
endeavoring to find out the reasons of things.
He therefore assumed that there are a certain abstract
beauty and goodness and magnitude, and so of all other
things; the truth of which being granted, he thinks
he shall be able to prove that the soul is immortal.
This, then, being conceded by Cebes,
Socrates argues that every thing that is beautiful
is so from partaking of abstract beauty, and great
from partaking of magnitude, and little from partaking
of littleness. Now, it is impossible, he argues,
that contraries can exist in the same thing at the
same time; for instance, the same thing can not possess
both magnitude and littleness, but one will withdraw
at the approach of the other; and not only so, but
things which, though not contrary to each other, yet
always contain contraries within themselves, can not
co-exist; for instance, the number three has no contrary,
yet it contains within itself the idea of odd, which
is the contrary of even, and so three never can become
even; in like manner, heat while it is heat can never
admit the idea of its contrary, cold. Now, if
this method of reasoning is applied to the soul, it
will be found to be immortal; for life and death are
contraries, and never can co-exist; but wherever the
soul is, there is life: so that it contains within
itself that which is contrary to death, and consequently
can never admit of death; therefore it is immortal.
With this he closes his arguments
in support of the soul’s immortality. Cebes
owns himself convinced, but Simmias, though he is unable
to make any objection to the soundness of Socrates’s
reasoning, can not help still entertaining doubts
on the subject. If, however, the soul is immortal,
Socrates proceeds, great need is there in this
life to endeavor to become as wise and good as possible.
For if death were a deliverance from every thing,
it would be a great gain for the wicked; but since
the soul appears to be immortal, it must go to the
place suited to its nature. For it is said that
each person’s demon conducts him to a place
where he receives sentence according to his deserts.
He then draws a fanciful picture
of the various regions of the earth, to which the
good and the bad will respectively go after death,
and exhorts his friends to use every endeavor to acquire
virtue and wisdom in this life, “for,”
he adds, “the reward is noble, and the hope
great.”
Having thus brought his subject to
a conclusion, Socrates proposes to bathe himself,
in order not to trouble others to wash his dead body.
Crito thereupon asks if he has any commands to give,
and especially how he would be buried, to which he,
with his usual cheerfulness, makes answer, “Just
as you please, if only you can catch me;” and
then, smiling, he reminds them that after death he
shall be no longer with them, and begs the others
of the party to be sureties to Crito for his absence
from the body, as they had been before bound for his
presence before his judges.
After he had bathed, and taken leave
of his children and the women of his family the officer
of the Eleven comes in to intimate to him that it
is now time to drink the poison. Crito urges a
little delay, as the sun had not yet set; but Socrates
refuses to make himself ridiculous by showing such
a fondness for life. The man who is to administer
the poison is therefore sent for; and on his holding
out the cup, Socrates, neither trembling nor changing
color or countenance at all, but, as he was wont,
looking steadfastly at the man, asked if he might make
a libation to any one; and being told that no more
poison than enough had been mixed, he simply prayed
that his departure from this to another world might
be happy, and then drank off the poison, readily and
calmly. His friends, who had hitherto with difficulty
restrained themselves, could no longer control the
outward expressions of grief, to which Socrates said,
“What are you doing, my friends? I, for
this reason, chiefly, sent away the women, that they
might not commit any folly of this kind; for I have
heard that it is right to die with good omens.
Be quiet, therefore, and bear up.”
When he had walked about for a while
his legs began to grow heavy, so he lay down on his
back; and his body, from the feet upward, gradually
grew cold and stiff. His last words were, “Crito,
we owe a cock to AEsculapius; pay it, therefore, and
do not neglect it.”
“This,” concludes Phaedo,
“was the end of our friend a man,
as we may say, the best of all his time, that we have
known, and, moreover, the most wise and just.”