Nature in the aspect which she presented
to a Greek philosopher of the fourth century before
Christ is not easily reproduced to modern eyes.
The associations of mythology and poetry have to be
added, and the unconscious influence of science has
to be subtracted, before we can behold the heavens
or the earth as they appeared to the Greek. The
philosopher himself was a child and also a man a
child in the range of his attainments, but also a
great intelligence having an insight into nature,
and often anticipations of the truth. He was full
of original thoughts, and yet liable to be imposed
upon by the most obvious fallacies. He occasionally
confused numbers with ideas, and atoms with numbers;
his a priori notions were out of all proportion to
his experience. He was ready to explain the phenomena
of the heavens by the most trivial analogies of earth.
The experiments which nature worked for him he sometimes
accepted, but he never tried experiments for himself
which would either prove or disprove his theories.
His knowledge was unequal; while in some branches,
such as medicine and astronomy, he had made considerable
proficiency, there were others, such as chemistry,
electricity, mechanics, of which the very names were
unknown to him. He was the natural enemy of mythology,
and yet mythological ideas still retained their hold
over him. He was endeavouring to form a conception
of principles, but these principles or ideas were regarded
by him as real powers or entities, to which the world
had been subjected. He was always tending to
argue from what was near to what was remote, from what
was known to what was unknown, from man to the universe,
and back again from the universe to man. While
he was arranging the world, he was arranging the forms
of thought in his own mind; and the light from within
and the light from without often crossed and helped
to confuse one another. He might be compared
to a builder engaged in some great design, who could
only dig with his hands because he was unprovided with
common tools; or to some poet or musician, like Tynnichus
(Ion), obliged to accommodate his lyric raptures to
the limits of the tetrachord or of the flute.
The Hesiodic and Orphic cosmogonies
were a phase of thought intermediate between mythology
and philosophy and had a great influence on the beginnings
of knowledge. There was nothing behind them; they
were to physical science what the poems of Homer were
to early Greek history. They made men think of
the world as a whole; they carried the mind back into
the infinity of past time; they suggested the first
observation of the effects of fire and water on the
earth’s surface. To the ancient physics
they stood much in the same relation which geology
does to modern science. But the Greek was not,
like the enquirer of the last generation, confined
to a period of six thousand years; he was able to
speculate freely on the effects of infinite ages in
the production of physical phenomena. He could
imagine cities which had existed time out of mind
(States.; Laws), laws or forms of art and music which
had lasted, ‘not in word only, but in very truth,
for ten thousand years’ (Laws); he was aware
that natural phenomena like the Delta of the Nile
might have slowly accumulated in long periods of time
(Hdt.). But he seems to have supposed that the
course of events was recurring rather than progressive.
To this he was probably led by the fixedness of Egyptian
customs and the general observation that there were
other civilisations in the world more ancient than
that of Hellas.
The ancient philosophers found in
mythology many ideas which, if not originally derived
from nature, were easily transferred to her such,
for example, as love or hate, corresponding to attraction
or repulsion; or the conception of necessity allied
both to the regularity and irregularity of nature;
or of chance, the nameless or unknown cause; or of
justice, symbolizing the law of compensation; are of
the Fates and Furies, typifying the fixed order or
the extraordinary convulsions of nature. Their
own interpretations of Homer and the poets were supposed
by them to be the original meaning. Musing in
themselves on the phenomena of nature, they were relieved
at being able to utter the thoughts of their hearts
in figures of speech which to them were not figures,
and were already consecrated by tradition. Hesiod
and the Orphic poets moved in a region of half-personification
in which the meaning or principle appeared through
the person. In their vaster conceptions of Chaos,
Erebus, Aether, Night, and the like, the first
rude attempts at generalization are dimly seen.
The Gods themselves, especially the greater Gods,
such as Zeus, Poseidon, Apollo, Athene, are
universals as well as individuals. They were gradually
becoming lost in a common conception of mind or God.
They continued to exist for the purposes of ritual
or of art; but from the sixth century onwards or even
earlier there arose and gained strength in the minds
of men the notion of ’one God, greatest among
Gods and men, who was all sight, all hearing, all
knowing’ (Xenophanes).
Under the influence of such ideas,
perhaps also deriving from the traditions of their
own or of other nations scraps of medicine and astronomy,
men came to the observation of nature. The Greek
philosopher looked at the blue circle of the heavens
and it flashed upon him that all things were one;
the tumult of sense abated, and the mind found repose
in the thought which former generations had been striving
to realize. The first expression of this was
some element, rarefied by degrees into a pure abstraction,
and purged from any tincture of sense. Soon an
inner world of ideas began to be unfolded, more absorbing,
more overpowering, more abiding than the brightest
of visible objects, which to the eye of the philosopher
looking inward, seemed to pale before them, retaining
only a faint and precarious existence. At the
same time, the minds of men parted into the two great
divisions of those who saw only a principle of motion,
and of those who saw only a principle of rest, in
nature and in themselves; there were born Heracliteans
or Eleatics, as there have been in later ages born
Aristotelians or Platonists. Like some philosophers
in modern times, who are accused of making a theory
first and finding their facts afterwards, the advocates
of either opinion never thought of applying either
to themselves or to their adversaries the criterion
of fact. They were mastered by their ideas and
not masters of them. Like the Heraclitean fanatics
whom Plato has ridiculed in the Theaetetus, they were
incapable of giving a reason of the faith that was
in them, and had all the animosities of a religious
sect. Yet, doubtless, there was some first impression
derived from external nature, which, as in mythology,
so also in philosophy, worked upon the minds of the
first thinkers. Though incapable of induction
or generalization in the modern sense, they caught
an inspiration from the external world. The most
general facts or appearances of nature, the circle
of the universe, the nutritive power of water, the
air which is the breath of life, the destructive force
of fire, the seeming regularity of the greater part
of nature and the irregularity of a remnant, the recurrence
of day and night and of the seasons, the solid earth
and the impalpable aether, were always present
to them.
The great source of error and also
the beginning of truth to them was reasoning from
analogy; they could see resemblances, but not differences;
and they were incapable of distinguishing illustration
from argument. Analogy in modern times only points
the way, and is immediately verified by experiment.
The dreams and visions, which pass through the philosopher’s
mind, of resemblances between different classes of
substances, or between the animal and vegetable world,
are put into the refiner’s fire, and the dross
and other elements which adhere to them are purged
away. But the contemporary of Plato and Socrates
was incapable of resisting the power of any analogy
which occurred to him, and was drawn into any consequences
which seemed to follow. He had no methods of
difference or of concomitant variations, by the use
of which he could distinguish the accidental from the
essential. He could not isolate phenomena, and
he was helpless against the influence of any word
which had an equivocal or double sense.
Yet without this crude use of analogy
the ancient physical philosopher would have stood
still; he could not have made even ’one guess
among many’ without comparison. The course
of natural phenomena would have passed unheeded before
his eyes, like fair sights or musical sounds before
the eyes and ears of an animal. Even the fetichism
of the savage is the beginning of reasoning; the assumption
of the most fanciful of causes indicates a higher
mental state than the absence of all enquiry about
them. The tendency to argue from the higher to
the lower, from man to the world, has led to many
errors, but has also had an elevating influence on
philosophy. The conception of the world as a whole,
a person, an animal, has been the source of hasty
generalizations; yet this general grasp of nature
led also to a spirit of comprehensiveness in early
philosophy, which has not increased, but rather diminished,
as the fields of knowledge have become more divided.
The modern physicist confines himself to one or perhaps
two branches of science. But he comparatively
seldom rises above his own department, and often falls
under the narrowing influence which any single branch,
when pursued to the exclusion of every other, has
over the mind. Language, two, exercised a spell
over the beginnings of physical philosophy, leading
to error and sometimes to truth; for many thoughts
were suggested by the double meanings of words (Greek),
and the accidental distinctions of words sometimes
led the ancient philosopher to make corresponding
differences in things (Greek). ’If they
are the same, why have they different names; or if
they are different, why have they the same name?’ is
an argument not easily answered in the infancy of knowledge.
The modern philosopher has always been taught the lesson
which he still imperfectly learns, that he must disengage
himself from the influence of words. Nor are
there wanting in Plato, who was himself too often the
victim of them, impressive admonitions that we should
regard not words but things (States.). But upon
the whole, the ancients, though not entirely dominated
by them, were much more subject to the influence of
words than the moderns. They had no clear divisions
of colours or substances; even the four elements were
undefined; the fields of knowledge were not parted
off. They were bringing order out of disorder,
having a small grain of experience mingled in a confused
heap of a priori notions. And yet, probably,
their first impressions, the illusions and mirages
of their fancy, created a greater intellectual activity
and made a nearer approach to the truth than any patient
investigation of isolated facts, for which the time
had not yet come, could have accomplished.
There was one more illusion to which
the ancient philosophers were subject, and against
which Plato in his later dialogues seems to be struggling the
tendency to mere abstractions; not perceiving that
pure abstraction is only negation, they thought that
the greater the abstraction the greater the truth.
Behind any pair of ideas a new idea which comprehended
them the (Greek), as it was technically
termed began at once to appear. Two
are truer than three, one than two. The words
‘being,’ or ‘unity,’ or essence,’
or ‘good,’ became sacred to them.
They did not see that they had a word only, and in
one sense the most unmeaning of words. They did
not understand that the content of notions is in inverse
proportion to their universality the element
which is the most widely diffused is also the thinnest;
or, in the language of the common logic, the greater
the extension the less the comprehension. But
this vacant idea of a whole without parts, of a subject
without predicates, a rest without motion, has been
also the most fruitful of all ideas. It is the
beginning of a priori thought, and indeed of thinking
at all. Men were led to conceive it, not by a
love of hasty generalization, but by a divine instinct,
a dialectical enthusiasm, in which the human faculties
seemed to yearn for enlargement. We know that
‘being’ is only the verb of existence,
the copula, the most general symbol of relation, the
first and most meagre of abstractions; but to some
of the ancient philosophers this little word appeared
to attain divine proportions, and to comprehend all
truth. Being or essence, and similar words, represented
to them a supreme or divine being, in which they thought
that they found the containing and continuing principle
of the universe. In a few years the human mind
was peopled with abstractions; a new world was called
into existence to give law and order to the old.
But between them there was still a gulf, and no one
could pass from the one to the other.
Number and figure were the greatest
instruments of thought which were possessed by the
Greek philosopher; having the same power over the mind
which was exerted by abstract ideas, they were also
capable of practical application. Many curious
and, to the early thinker, mysterious properties of
them came to light when they were compared with one
another. They admitted of infinite multiplication
and construction; in Pythagorean triangles or in proportions
of 1:2:4:8 and 1:3:9:27, or compounds of them, the
laws of the world seemed to be more than half revealed.
They were also capable of infinite subdivision a
wonder and also a puzzle to the ancient thinker (Rep.).
They were not, like being or essence, mere vacant
abstractions, but admitted of progress and growth,
while at the same time they confirmed a higher sentiment
of the mind, that there was order in the universe.
And so there began to be a real sympathy between the
world within and the world without. The numbers
and figures which were present to the mind’s
eye became visible to the eye of sense; the truth
of nature was mathematics; the other properties of
objects seemed to reappear only in the light of number.
Law and morality also found a natural expression in
number and figure. Instruments of such power
and elasticity could not fail to be ’a most
gracious assistance’ to the first efforts of
human intelligence.
There was another reason why numbers
had so great an influence over the minds of early
thinkers they were verified by experience.
Every use of them, even the most trivial, assured
men of their truth; they were everywhere to be found,
in the least things and the greatest alike. One,
two, three, counted on the fingers was a ’trivial
matter (Rep.), a little instrument out of which to
create a world; but from these and by the help of
these all our knowledge of nature has been developed.
They were the measure of all things, and seemed to
give law to all things; nature was rescued from chaos
and confusion by their power; the notes of music,
the motions of the stars, the forms of atoms, the evolution
and recurrence of days, months, years, the military
divisions of an army, the civil divisions of a state,
seemed to afford a ‘present witness’ of
them what would have become of man or of
the world if deprived of number (Rep.)? The mystery
of number and the mystery of music were akin.
There was a music of rhythm and of harmonious motion
everywhere; and to the real connexion which existed
between music and number, a fanciful or imaginary
relation was superadded. There was a music of
the spheres as well as of the notes of the lyre.
If in all things seen there was number and figure,
why should they not also pervade the unseen world,
with which by their wonderful and unchangeable nature
they seemed to hold communion?
Two other points strike us in the
use which the ancient philosophers made of numbers.
First, they applied to external nature the relations
of them which they found in their own minds; and where
nature seemed to be at variance with number, as for
example in the case of fractions, they protested against
her (Rep.; Arist. Metaph.). Having long meditated
on the properties of 1:2:4:8, or 1:3:9:27, or of 3,
4, 5, they discovered in them many curious correspondences
and were disposed to find in them the secret of the
universe. Secondly, they applied number and figure
equally to those parts of physics, such as astronomy
or mechanics, in which the modern philosopher expects
to find them, and to those in which he would never
think of looking for them, such as physiology and
psychology. For the sciences were not yet divided,
and there was nothing really irrational in arguing
that the same laws which regulated the heavenly bodies
were partially applied to the erring limbs or brain
of man. Astrology was the form which the lively
fancy of ancient thinkers almost necessarily gave
to astronomy. The observation that the lower
principle, e.g. mechanics, is always seen in the
higher, e.g. in the phenomena of life, further
tended to perplex them. Plato’s doctrine
of the same and the other ruling the courses of the
heavens and of the human body is not a mere vagary,
but is a natural result of the state of knowledge
and thought at which he had arrived.
When in modern times we contemplate
the heavens, a certain amount of scientific truth
imperceptibly blends, even with the cursory glance
of an unscientific person. He knows that the
earth is revolving round the sun, and not the sun
around the earth. He does not imagine the earth
to be the centre of the universe, and he has some
conception of chemistry and the cognate sciences.
A very different aspect of nature would have been
present to the mind of the early Greek philosopher.
He would have beheld the earth a surface only, not
mirrored, however faintly, in the glass of science,
but indissolubly connected with some theory of one,
two, or more elements. He would have seen the
world pervaded by number and figure, animated by a
principle of motion, immanent in a principle of rest.
He would have tried to construct the universe on a
quantitative principle, seeming to find in endless
combinations of geometrical figures or in the infinite
variety of their sizes a sufficient account of the
multiplicity of phenomena. To these a priori speculations
he would add a rude conception of matter and his own
immediate experience of health and disease. His
cosmos would necessarily be imperfect and unequal,
being the first attempt to impress form and order on
the primaeval chaos of human knowledge. He would
see all things as in a dream.
The ancient physical philosophers
have been charged by Dr. Whewell and others with wasting
their fine intelligences in wrong methods of enquiry;
and their progress in moral and political philosophy
has been sometimes contrasted with their supposed
failure in physical investigations. ‘They
had plenty of ideas,’ says Dr. Whewell, ’and
plenty of facts; but their ideas did not accurately
represent the facts with which they were acquainted.’
This is a very crude and misleading way of describing
ancient science. It is the mistake of an uneducated
person uneducated, that is, in the higher
sense of the word who imagines every one
else to be like himself and explains every other age
by his own. No doubt the ancients often fell into
strange and fanciful errors: the time had not
yet arrived for the slower and surer path of the modern
inductive philosophy. But it remains to be shown
that they could have done more in their age and country;
or that the contributions which they made to the sciences
with which they were acquainted are not as great upon
the whole as those made by their successors. There
is no single step in astronomy as great as that of
the nameless Pythagorean who first conceived the world
to be a body moving round the sun in space: there
is no truer or more comprehensive principle than the
application of mathematics alike to the heavenly bodies,
and to the particles of matter. The ancients
had not the instruments which would have enabled them
to correct or verify their anticipations, and their
opportunities of observation were limited. Plato
probably did more for physical science by asserting
the supremacy of mathematics than Aristotle or his
disciples by their collections of facts. When
the thinkers of modern times, following Bacon, undervalue
or disparage the speculations of ancient philosophers,
they seem wholly to forget the conditions of the world
and of the human mind, under which they carried on
their investigations. When we accuse them of being
under the influence of words, do we suppose that we
are altogether free from this illusion? When
we remark that Greek physics soon became stationary
or extinct, may we not observe also that there have
been and may be again periods in the history of modern
philosophy which have been barren and unproductive?
We might as well maintain that Greek art was not real
or great, because it had nihil simile aut
secundum, as say that Greek physics were a failure
because they admire no subsequent progress.
The charge of premature generalization
which is often urged against ancient philosophers
is really an anachronism. For they can hardly
be said to have generalized at all. They may
be said more truly to have cleared up and defined
by the help of experience ideas which they already
possessed. The beginnings of thought about nature
must always have this character. A true method
is the result of many ages of experiment and observation,
and is ever going on and enlarging with the progress
of science and knowledge. At first men personify
nature, then they form impressions of nature, at last
they conceive ‘measure’ or laws of nature.
They pass out of mythology into philosophy. Early
science is not a process of discovery in the modern
sense; but rather a process of correcting by observation,
and to a certain extent only, the first impressions
of nature, which mankind, when they began to think,
had received from poetry or language or unintelligent
sense. Of all scientific truths the greatest
and simplest is the uniformity of nature; this was
expressed by the ancients in many ways, as fate, or
necessity, or measure, or limit. Unexpected events,
of which the cause was unknown to them, they attributed
to chance (Thucyd.). But their conception of
nature was never that of law interrupted by exceptions, a
somewhat unfortunate metaphysical invention of modern
times, which is at variance with facts and has failed
to satisfy the requirements of thought.