We have now to consider how far in
any of these speculations Plato approximated to the
discoveries of modern science. The modern physical
philosopher is apt to dwell exclusively on the absurdities
of ancient ideas about science, on the haphazard fancies
and a priori assumptions of ancient teachers, on their
confusion of facts and ideas, on their inconsistency
and blindness to the most obvious phenomena. He
measures them not by what preceded them, but by what
has followed them. He does not consider that
ancient physical philosophy was not a free enquiry,
but a growth, in which the mind was passive rather
than active, and was incapable of resisting the impressions
which flowed in upon it. He hardly allows to
the notions of the ancients the merit of being the
stepping-stones by which he has himself risen to a
higher knowledge. He never reflects, how great
a thing it was to have formed a conception, however
imperfect, either of the human frame as a whole, or
of the world as a whole. According to the view
taken in these volumes the errors of ancient physicists
were not separable from the intellectual conditions
under which they lived. Their genius was their
own; and they were not the rash and hasty generalizers
which, since the days of Bacon, we have been apt to
suppose them. The thoughts of men widened to receive
experience; at first they seemed to know all things
as in a dream: after a while they look at them
closely and hold them in their hands. They begin
to arrange them in classes and to connect causes with
effects. General notions are necessary to the
apprehension of particular facts, the metaphysical
to the physical. Before men can observe the world,
they must be able to conceive it.
To do justice to the subject, we should
consider the physical philosophy of the ancients as
a whole; we should remember, (1) that the nebular
theory was the received belief of several of the early
physicists; (2) that the development of animals out
of fishes who came to land, and of man out of the
animals, was held by Anaximander in the sixth century
before Christ (Plut. Symp. Quaest;
Plac. Phil.); (3) that even by Philolaus and
the early Pythagoreans, the earth was held to be a
body like the other stars revolving in space around
the sun or a central fire; (4) that the beginnings
of chemistry are discernible in the ‘similar
particles’ of Anaxagoras. Also they knew
or thought (5) that there was a sex in plants as well
as in animals; (6) they were aware that musical notes
depended on the relative length or tension of the
strings from which they were emitted, and were measured
by ratios of number; (7) that mathematical laws pervaded
the world; and even qualitative differences were supposed
to have their origin in number and figure; (8) the
annihilation of matter was denied by several of them,
and the seeming disappearance of it held to be a transformation
only. For, although one of these discoveries
might have been supposed to be a happy guess, taken
together they seem to imply a great advance and almost
maturity of natural knowledge.
We should also remember, when we attribute
to the ancients hasty generalizations and delusions
of language, that physical philosophy and metaphysical
too have been guilty of similar fallacies in quite
recent times. We by no means distinguish clearly
between mind and body, between ideas and facts.
Have not many discussions arisen about the Atomic
theory in which a point has been confused with a material
atom? Have not the natures of things been explained
by imaginary entities, such as life or phlogiston,
which exist in the mind only? Has not disease
been regarded, like sin, sometimes as a negative and
necessary, sometimes as a positive or malignant principle?
The ‘idols’ of Bacon are nearly as common
now as ever; they are inherent in the human mind, and
when they have the most complete dominion over us,
we are least able to perceive them. We recognize
them in the ancients, but we fail to see them in ourselves.
Such reflections, although this is
not the place in which to dwell upon them at length,
lead us to take a favourable view of the speculations
of the Timaeus. We should consider not how much
Plato actually knew, but how far he has contributed
to the general ideas of physics, or supplied the notions
which, whether true or false, have stimulated the minds
of later generations in the path of discovery.
Some of them may seem old-fashioned, but may nevertheless
have had a great influence in promoting system and
assisting enquiry, while in others we hear the latest
word of physical or metaphysical philosophy. There
is also an intermediate class, in which Plato falls
short of the truths of modern science, though he is
not wholly unacquainted with them. (1) To the first
class belongs the teleological theory of creation.
Whether all things in the world can be explained as
the result of natural laws, or whether we must not
admit of tendencies and marks of design also, has
been a question much disputed of late years. Even
if all phenomena are the result of natural forces,
we must admit that there are many things in heaven
and earth which are as well expressed under the image
of mind or design as under any other. At any
rate, the language of Plato has been the language
of natural theology down to our own time, nor can any
description of the world wholly dispense with it.
The notion of first and second or co-operative causes,
which originally appears in the Timaeus, has likewise
survived to our own day, and has been a great peace-maker
between theology and science. Plato also approaches
very near to our doctrine of the primary and secondary
qualities of matter. (2) Another popular notion which
is found in the Timaeus, is the feebleness of the
human intellect ’God knows the original
qualities of things; man can only hope to attain to
probability.’ We speak in almost the same
words of human intelligence, but not in the same manner
of the uncertainty of our knowledge of nature.
The reason is that the latter is assured to us by
experiment, and is not contrasted with the certainty
of ideal or mathematical knowledge. But the ancient
philosopher never experimented: in the Timaeus
Plato seems to have thought that there would be impiety
in making the attempt; he, for example, who tried
experiments in colours would ’forget the difference
of the human and divine natures.’ Their
indefiniteness is probably the reason why he singles
them out, as especially incapable of being tested by
experiment. (Compare the saying of Anaxagoras Sext.
Pyrrh. that since snow is made of water
and water is black, snow ought to be black.)
The greatest ‘divination’
of the ancients was the supremacy which they assigned
to mathematics in all the realms of nature; for in
all of them there is a foundation of mechanics.
Even physiology partakes of figure and number; and
Plato is not wrong in attributing them to the human
frame, but in the omission to observe how little could
be explained by them. Thus we may remark in passing
that the most fanciful of ancient philosophies is
also the most nearly verified in fact. The fortunate
guess that the world is a sum of numbers and figures
has been the most fruitful of anticipations.
The ‘diatonic’ scale of the Pythagoreans
and Plato suggested to Kepler that the secret of the
distances of the planets from one another was to be
found in mathematical proportions. The doctrine
that the heavenly bodies all move in a circle is known
by us to be erroneous; but without such an error how
could the human mind have comprehended the heavens?
Astronomy, even in modern times, has made far greater
progress by the high a priori road than could have
been attained by any other. Yet, strictly speaking and
the remark applies to ancient physics generally this
high a priori road was based upon a posteriori grounds.
For there were no facts of which the ancients were
so well assured by experience as facts of number.
Having observed that they held good in a few instances,
they applied them everywhere; and in the complexity,
of which they were capable, found the explanation of
the equally complex phenomena of the universe.
They seemed to see them in the least things as well
as in the greatest; in atoms, as well as in suns and
stars; in the human body as well as in external nature.
And now a favourite speculation of modern chemistry
is the explanation of qualitative difference by quantitative,
which is at present verified to a certain extent and
may hereafter be of far more universal application.
What is this but the atoms of Democritus and the triangles
of Plato? The ancients should not be wholly deprived
of the credit of their guesses because they were unable
to prove them. May they not have had, like the
animals, an instinct of something more than they knew?
Besides general notions we seem to
find in the Timaeus some more precise approximations
to the discoveries of modern physical science.
First, the doctrine of equipoise. Plato affirms,
almost in so many words, that nature abhors a vacuum.
Whenever a particle is displaced, the rest push and
thrust one another until equality is restored.
We must remember that these ideas were not derived
from any definite experiment, but were the original
reflections of man, fresh from the first observation
of nature. The latest word of modern philosophy
is continuity and development, but to Plato this is
the beginning and foundation of science; there is
nothing that he is so strongly persuaded of as that
the world is one, and that all the various existences
which are contained in it are only the transformations
of the same soul of the world acting on the same matter.
He would have readily admitted that out of the protoplasm
all things were formed by the gradual process of creation;
but he would have insisted that mind and intelligence not
meaning by this, however, a conscious mind or person were
prior to them, and could alone have created them.
Into the workings of this eternal mind or intelligence
he does not enter further; nor would there have been
any use in attempting to investigate the things which
no eye has seen nor any human language can express.
Lastly, there remain two points in
which he seems to touch great discoveries of modern
times the law of gravitation, and the circulation
of the blood.
(1) The law of gravitation, according
to Plato, is a law, not only of the attraction of
lesser bodies to larger ones, but of similar bodies
to similar, having a magnetic power as well as a principle
of gravitation. He observed that earth, water,
and air had settled down to their places, and he imagined
fire or the exterior aether to have a place
beyond air. When air seemed to go upwards and
fire to pierce through air when water and
earth fell downward, they were seeking their native
elements. He did not remark that his own explanation
did not suit all phenomena; and the simpler explanation,
which assigns to bodies degrees of heaviness and lightness
proportioned to the mass and distance of the bodies
which attract them, never occurred to him. Yet
the affinities of similar substances have some effect
upon the composition of the world, and of this Plato
may be thought to have had an anticipation. He
may be described as confusing the attraction of gravitation
with the attraction of cohesion. The influence
of such affinities and the chemical action of one
body upon another in long periods of time have become
a recognized principle of geology.
(2) Plato is perfectly aware and
he could hardly be ignorant that blood
is a fluid in constant motion. He also knew that
blood is partly a solid substance consisting of several
elements, which, as he might have observed in the
use of ‘cupping-glasses’, decompose and
die, when no longer in motion. But the specific
discovery that the blood flows out on one side of
the heart through the arteries and returns through
the veins on the other, which is commonly called the
circulation of the blood, was absolutely unknown to
him.
A further study of the Timaeus suggests
some after-thoughts which may be conveniently brought
together in this place. The topics which I propose
briefly to reconsider are (a) the relation of the Timaeus
to the other dialogues of Plato and to the previous
philosophy; (b) the nature of God and of creation
(c) the morality of the Timaeus:
(a) The Timaeus is more imaginative
and less scientific than any other of the Platonic
dialogues. It is conjectural astronomy, conjectural
natural philosophy, conjectural medicine. The
writer himself is constantly repeating that he is
speaking what is probable only. The dialogue
is put into the mouth of Timaeus, a Pythagorean philosopher,
and therefore here, as in the Parmenides, we are in
doubt how far Plato is expressing his own sentiments.
Hence the connexion with the other dialogues is comparatively
slight. We may fill up the lacunae of the Timaeus
by the help of the Republic or Phaedrus: we may
identify the same and other with the (Greek) of the
Philebus. We may find in the Laws or in the Statesman
parallels with the account of creation and of the
first origin of man. It would be possible to frame
a scheme in which all these various elements might
have a place. But such a mode of proceeding would
be unsatisfactory, because we have no reason to suppose
that Plato intended his scattered thoughts to be collected
in a system. There is a common spirit in his
writings, and there are certain general principles,
such as the opposition of the sensible and intellectual,
and the priority of mind, which run through all of
them; but he has no definite forms of words in which
he consistently expresses himself. While the
determinations of human thought are in process of creation
he is necessarily tentative and uncertain. And
there is least of definiteness, whenever either in
describing the beginning or the end of the world, he
has recourse to myths. These are not the fixed
modes in which spiritual truths are revealed to him,
but the efforts of imagination, by which at different
times and in various manners he seeks to embody his
conceptions. The clouds of mythology are still
resting upon him, and he has not yet pierced ‘to
the heaven of the fixed stars’ which is beyond
them. It is safer then to admit the inconsistencies
of the Timaeus, or to endeavour to fill up what is
wanting from our own imagination, inspired by a study
of the dialogue, than to refer to other Platonic writings, and
still less should we refer to the successors of Plato, for
the elucidation of it.
More light is thrown upon the Timaeus
by a comparison of the previous philosophies.
For the physical science of the ancients was traditional,
descending through many generations of Ionian and Pythagorean
philosophers. Plato does not look out upon the
heavens and describe what he sees in them, but he
builds upon the foundations of others, adding something
out of the ‘depths of his own self-consciousness.’
Socrates had already spoken of God the creator, who
made all things for the best. While he ridiculed
the superficial explanations of phenomena which were
current in his age, he recognised the marks both of
benevolence and of design in the frame of man and
in the world. The apparatus of winds and waters
is contemptuously rejected by him in the Phaedo,
but he thinks that there is a power greater than that
of any Atlas in the ‘Best’ (Phaedo;
Arist. Met.). Plato, following his master,
affirms this principle of the best, but he acknowledges
that the best is limited by the conditions of matter.
In the generation before Socrates, Anaxagoras had
brought together ‘Chaos’ and ‘Mind’;
and these are connected by Plato in the Timaeus, but
in accordance with his own mode of thinking he has
interposed between them the idea or pattern according
to which mind worked. The circular impulse (Greek)
of the one philosopher answers to the circular movement
(Greek) of the other. But unlike Anaxagoras, Plato
made the sun and stars living beings and not masses
of earth or metal. The Pythagoreans again had
framed a world out of numbers, which they constructed
into figures. Plato adopted their speculations
and improved upon them by a more exact knowledge of
geometry. The Atomists too made the world, if
not out of geometrical figures, at least out of different
forms of atoms, and these atoms resembled the triangles
of Plato in being too small to be visible. But
though the physiology of the Timaeus is partly borrowed
from them, they are either ignored by Plato or referred
to with a secret contempt and dislike. He looks
with more favour on the Pythagoreans, whose intervals
of number applied to the distances of the planets
reappear in the Timaeus. It is probable that
among the Pythagoreans living in the fourth century
B.C., there were already some who, like Plato, made
the earth their centre. Whether he obtained his
circles of the Same and Other from any previous thinker
is uncertain. The four elements are taken from
Empedocles; the interstices of the Timaeus may also
be compared with his (Greek). The passage of one
element into another is common to Heracleitus and several
of the Ionian philosophers. So much of a syncretist
is Plato, though not after the manner of the Neoplatonists.
For the elements which he borrows from others are
fused and transformed by his own genius. On the
other hand we find fewer traces in Plato of early
Ionic or Eleatic speculation. He does not imagine
the world of sense to be made up of opposites or to
be in a perpetual flux, but to vary within certain
limits which are controlled by what he calls the principle
of the same. Unlike the Eleatics, who relegated
the world to the sphere of not-being, he admits creation
to have an existence which is real and even eternal,
although dependent on the will of the creator.
Instead of maintaining the doctrine that the void
has a necessary place in the existence of the world,
he rather affirms the modern thesis that nature abhors
a vacuum, as in the Sophist he also denies the reality
of not-being (Aristot. Metaph.). But though
in these respects he differs from them, he is deeply
penetrated by the spirit of their philosophy; he differs
from them with reluctance, and gladly recognizes the
‘generous depth’ of Parmenides (Theaet.).
There is a similarity between the
Timaeus and the fragments of Philolaus, which by some
has been thought to be so great as to create a suspicion
that they are derived from it. Philolaus is known
to us from the Phaedo of Plato as a Pythagorean
philosopher residing at Thebes in the latter half
of the fifth century B.C., after the dispersion of
the original Pythagorean society. He was the
teacher of Simmias and Cebes, who became disciples
of Socrates. We have hardly any other information
about him. The story that Plato had purchased
three books of his writings from a relation is not
worth repeating; it is only a fanciful way in which
an ancient biographer dresses up the fact that there
was supposed to be a resemblance between the two writers.
Similar gossiping stories are told about the sources
of the Republic and the Phaedo. That there
really existed in antiquity a work passing under the
name of Philolaus there can be no doubt. Fragments
of this work are preserved to us, chiefly in Stobaeus,
a few in Boethius and other writers. They remind
us of the Timaeus, as well as of the Phaedrus and Philebus.
When the writer says (Stob. Eclog.) that all things
are either finite (definite) or infinite (indefinite),
or a union of the two, and that this antithesis and
synthesis pervades all art and nature, we are reminded
of the Philebus. When he calls the centre of the
world (Greek), we have a parallel to the Phaedrus.
His distinction between the world of order, to which
the sun and moon and the stars belong, and the world
of disorder, which lies in the region between the moon
and the earth, approximates to Plato’s sphere
of the Same and of the Other. Like Plato (Tim.),
he denied the above and below in space, and said that
all things were the same in relation to a centre.
He speaks also of the world as one and indestructible:
’for neither from within nor from without does
it admit of destruction’ (Tim). He mentions
ten heavenly bodies, including the sun and moon, the
earth and the counter-earth (Greek), and in the midst
of them all he places the central fire, around which
they are moving this is hidden from the
earth by the counter-earth. Of neither is there
any trace in Plato, who makes the earth the centre
of his system. Philolaus magnifies the virtues
of particular numbers, especially of the number 10
(Stob. Eclog.), and descants upon odd and even
numbers, after the manner of the later Pythagoreans.
It is worthy of remark that these mystical fancies
are nowhere to be found in the writings of Plato,
although the importance of number as a form and also
an instrument of thought is ever present to his mind.
Both Philolaus and Plato agree in making the world
move in certain numerical ratios according to a musical
scale: though Bockh is of opinion that the two
scales, of Philolaus and of the Timaeus, do not correspond...We
appear not to be sufficiently acquainted with the
early Pythagoreans to know how far the statements
contained in these fragments corresponded with their
doctrines; and we therefore cannot pronounce, either
in favour of the genuineness of the fragments, with
Bockh and Zeller, or, with Valentine Rose and Schaarschmidt,
against them. But it is clear that they throw
but little light upon the Timaeus, and that their resemblance
to it has been exaggerated.
That there is a degree of confusion
and indistinctness in Plato’s account both of
man and of the universe has been already acknowledged.
We cannot tell (nor could Plato himself have told)
where the figure or myth ends and the philosophical
truth begins; we cannot explain (nor could Plato himself
have explained to us) the relation of the ideas to
appearance, of which one is the copy of the other,
and yet of all things in the world they are the most
opposed and unlike. This opposition is presented
to us in many forms, as the antithesis of the one and
many, of the finite and infinite, of the intelligible
and sensible, of the unchangeable and the changing,
of the indivisible and the divisible, of the fixed
stars and the planets, of the creative mind and the
primeval chaos. These pairs of opposites are
so many aspects of the great opposition between ideas
and phenomena they easily pass into one
another; and sometimes the two members of the relation
differ in kind, sometimes only in degree. As
in Aristotle’s matter and form the connexion
between them is really inseparable; for if we attempt
to separate them they become devoid of content and
therefore indistinguishable; there is no difference
between the idea of which nothing can be predicated,
and the chaos or matter which has no perceptible qualities between
Being in the abstract and Nothing. Yet we are
frequently told that the one class of them is the reality
and the other appearance; and one is often spoken
of as the double or reflection of the other.
For Plato never clearly saw that both elements had
an equal place in mind and in nature; and hence, especially
when we argue from isolated passages in his writings,
or attempt to draw what appear to us to be the natural
inferences from them, we are full of perplexity.
There is a similar confusion about necessity and free-will,
and about the state of the soul after death.
Also he sometimes supposes that God is immanent in
the world, sometimes that he is transcendent.
And having no distinction of objective and subjective,
he passes imperceptibly from one to the other; from
intelligence to soul, from eternity to time.
These contradictions may be softened or concealed by
a judicious use of language, but they cannot be wholly
got rid of. That an age of intellectual transition
must also be one of inconsistency; that the creative
is opposed to the critical or defining habit of mind
or time, has been often repeated by us. But,
as Plato would say, ’there is no harm in repeating
twice or thrice’ (Laws) what is important for
the understanding of a great author.
It has not, however, been observed,
that the confusion partly arises out of the elements
of opposing philosophies which are preserved in him.
He holds these in solution, he brings them into relation
with one another, but he does not perfectly harmonize
them. They are part of his own mind, and he is
incapable of placing himself outside of them and criticizing
them. They grow as he grows; they are a kind of
composition with which his own philosophy is overlaid.
In early life he fancies that he has mastered them:
but he is also mastered by them; and in language (Sophist)
which may be compared with the hesitating tone of the
Timaeus, he confesses in his later years that they
are full of obscurity to him. He attributes new
meanings to the words of Parmenides and Heracleitus;
but at times the old Eleatic philosophy appears to
go beyond him; then the world of phenomena disappears,
but the doctrine of ideas is also reduced to nothingness.
All of them are nearer to one another than they themselves
supposed, and nearer to him than he supposed.
All of them are antagonistic to sense and have an
affinity to number and measure and a presentiment
of ideas. Even in Plato they still retain their
contentious or controversial character, which was
developed by the growth of dialectic. He is never
able to reconcile the first causes of the pre-Socratic
philosophers with the final causes of Socrates himself.
There is no intelligible account of the relation of
numbers to the universal ideas, or of universals to
the idea of good. He found them all three, in
the Pythagorean philosophy and in the teaching of Socrates
and of the Megarians respectively; and, because they
all furnished modes of explaining and arranging phenomena,
he is unwilling to give up any of them, though he
is unable to unite them in a consistent whole.
Lastly, Plato, though an idealist
philosopher, is Greek and not Oriental in spirit and
feeling. He is no mystic or ascetic; he is not
seeking in vain to get rid of matter or to find absorption
in the divine nature, or in the Soul of the universe.
And therefore we are not surprised to find that his
philosophy in the Timaeus returns at last to a worship
of the heavens, and that to him, as to other Greeks,
nature, though containing a remnant of evil, is still
glorious and divine. He takes away or drops the
veil of mythology, and presents her to us in what appears
to him to be the form-fairer and truer far of
mathematical figures. It is this element in the
Timaeus, no less than its affinity to certain Pythagorean
speculations, which gives it a character not wholly
in accordance with the other dialogues of Plato.
(b) The Timaeus contains an assertion
perhaps more distinct than is found in any of the
other dialogues (Rep.; Laws) of the goodness of God.
‘He was good himself, and he fashioned the good
everywhere.’ He was not ‘a jealous
God,’ and therefore he desired that all other
things should be equally good. He is the idea
of good who has now become a person, and speaks and
is spoken of as God. Yet his personality seems
to appear only in the act of creation. In so
far as he works with his eye fixed upon an eternal
pattern he is like the human artificer in the Republic.
Here the theory of Platonic ideas intrudes upon us.
God, like man, is supposed to have an ideal of which
Plato is unable to tell us the origin. He may
be said, in the language of modern philosophy, to
resolve the divine mind into subject and object.
The first work of creation is perfected,
the second begins under the direction of inferior
ministers. The supreme God is withdrawn from
the world and returns to his own accustomed nature
(Tim.). As in the Statesman, he retires to his
place of view. So early did the Epicurean doctrine
take possession of the Greek mind, and so natural is
it to the heart of man, when he has once passed out
of the stage of mythology into that of rational religion.
For he sees the marks of design in the world; but
he no longer sees or fancies that he sees God walking
in the garden or haunting stream or mountain.
He feels also that he must put God as far as possible
out of the way of evil, and therefore he banishes him
from an evil world. Plato is sensible of the difficulty;
and he often shows that he is desirous of justifying
the ways of God to man. Yet on the other hand,
in the Tenth Book of the Laws he passes a censure on
those who say that the Gods have no care of human things.
The creation of the world is the impression
of order on a previously existing chaos. The
formula of Anaxagoras ’all things
were in chaos or confusion, and then mind came and
disposed them’ is a summary of the
first part of the Timaeus. It is true that of
a chaos without differences no idea could be formed.
All was not mixed but one; and therefore it was not
difficult for the later Platonists to draw inferences
by which they were enabled to reconcile the narrative
of the Timaeus with the Mosaic account of the creation.
Neither when we speak of mind or intelligence, do
we seem to get much further in our conception than
circular motion, which was deemed to be the most perfect.
Plato, like Anaxagoras, while commencing his theory
of the universe with ideas of mind and of the best,
is compelled in the execution of his design to condescend
to the crudest physics.
(c) The morality of the Timaeus is
singular, and it is difficult to adjust the balance
between the two elements of it. The difficulty
which Plato feels, is that which all of us feel, and
which is increased in our own day by the progress
of physical science, how the responsibility of man
is to be reconciled with his dependence on natural
causes. And sometimes, like other men, he is
more impressed by one aspect of human life, sometimes
by the other. In the Republic he represents man
as freely choosing his own lot in a state prior to
birth a conception which, if taken literally,
would still leave him subject to the dominion of necessity
in his after life; in the Statesman he supposes the
human race to be preserved in the world only by a
divine interposition; while in the Timaeus the supreme
God commissions the inferior deities to avert from
him all but self-inflicted evils words which
imply that all the evils of men are really self-inflicted.
And here, like Plato (the insertion of a note in the
text of an ancient writer is a literary curiosity
worthy of remark), we may take occasion to correct
an error. For we too hastily said that Plato
in the Timaeus regarded all ’vices and crimes
as involuntary.’ But the fact is that he
is inconsistent with himself; in one and the same
passage vice is attributed to the relaxation of the
bodily frame, and yet we are exhorted to avoid it and
pursue virtue. It is also admitted that good and
evil conduct are to be attributed respectively to
good and evil laws and institutions. These cannot
be given by individuals to themselves; and therefore
human actions, in so far as they are dependent upon
them, are regarded by Plato as involuntary rather
than voluntary. Like other writers on this subject,
he is unable to escape from some degree of self-contradiction.
He had learned from Socrates that vice is ignorance,
and suddenly the doctrine seems to him to be confirmed
by observing how much of the good and bad in human
character depends on the bodily constitution.
So in modern times the speculative doctrine of necessity
has often been supported by physical facts.
The Timaeus also contains an anticipation
of the stoical life according to nature. Man
contemplating the heavens is to regulate his erring
life according to them. He is to partake of the
repose of nature and of the order of nature, to bring
the variable principle in himself into harmony with
the principle of the same. The ethics of the Timaeus
may be summed up in the single idea of ‘law.’
To feel habitually that he is part of the order of
the universe, is one of the highest ethical motives
of which man is capable. Something like this
is what Plato means when he speaks of the soul ’moving
about the same in unchanging thought of the same.’
He does not explain how man is acted upon by the lesser
influences of custom or of opinion; or how the commands
of the soul watching in the citadel are conveyed to
the bodily organs. But this perhaps, to use once
more expressions of his own, ’is part of another
subject’ or ‘may be more suitably discussed
on some other occasion.’
There is no difficulty, by the help
of Aristotle and later writers, in criticizing the
Timaeus of Plato, in pointing out the inconsistencies
of the work, in dwelling on the ignorance of anatomy
displayed by the author, in showing the fancifulness
or unmeaningness of some of his reasons. But
the Timaeus still remains the greatest effort of the
human mind to conceive the world as a whole which
the genius of antiquity has bequeathed to us.
One more aspect of the Timaeus remains
to be considered the mythological or geographical.
Is it not a wonderful thing that a few pages of one
of Plato’s dialogues have grown into a great
legend, not confined to Greece only, but spreading
far and wide over the nations of Europe and reaching
even to Egypt and Asia? Like the tale of Troy,
or the legend of the Ten Tribes (Ewald, Hist. of Isr.),
which perhaps originated in a few verses of II Esdras,
it has become famous, because it has coincided with
a great historical fact. Like the romance of King
Arthur, which has had so great a charm, it has found
a way over the seas from one country and language
to another. It inspired the navigators of the
fifteenth and sixteenth centuries; it foreshadowed
the discovery of America. It realized the fiction
so natural to the human mind, because it answered
the enquiry about the origin of the arts, that there
had somewhere existed an ancient primitive civilization.
It might find a place wherever men chose to look for
it; in North, South, East, or West; in the Islands
of the Blest; before the entrance of the Straits of
Gibraltar, in Sweden or in Palestine. It mattered
little whether the description in Plato agreed with
the locality assigned to it or not. It was a
legend so adapted to the human mind that it made a
habitation for itself in any country. It was
an island in the clouds, which might be seen anywhere
by the eye of faith. It was a subject especially
congenial to the ponderous industry of certain French
and Swedish writers, who delighted in heaping up learning
of all sorts but were incapable of using it.
M. Martin has written a valuable dissertation
on the opinions entertained respecting the Island
of Atlantis in ancient and modern times. It is
a curious chapter in the history of the human mind.
The tale of Atlantis is the fabric of a vision, but
it has never ceased to interest mankind. It was
variously regarded by the ancients themselves.
The stronger heads among them, like Strabo and Longinus,
were as little disposed to believe in the truth of
it as the modern reader in Gulliver or Robinson Crusoe.
On the other hand there is no kind or degree of absurdity
or fancy in which the more foolish writers, both of
antiquity and of modern times, have not indulged respecting
it. The Neo-Platonists, loyal to their master,
like some commentators on the Christian Scriptures,
sought to give an allegorical meaning to what they
also believed to be an historical fact. It was
as if some one in our own day were to convert the
poems of Homer into an allegory of the Christian religion,
at the same time maintaining them to be an exact and
veritable history. In the Middle Ages the legend
seems to have been half-forgotten until revived by
the discovery of America. It helped to form the
Utopia of Sir Thomas More and the New Atlantis of
Bacon, although probably neither of those great men
were at all imposed upon by the fiction. It was
most prolific in the seventeenth or in the early part
of the eighteenth century, when the human mind, seeking
for Utopias or inventing them, was glad to escape
out of the dulness of the present into the romance
of the past or some ideal of the future. The later
forms of such narratives contained features taken from
the Edda, as well as from the Old and New Testament;
also from the tales of missionaries and the experiences
of travellers and of colonists.
The various opinions respecting the
Island of Atlantis have no interest for us except
in so far as they illustrate the extravagances
of which men are capable. But this is a real
interest and a serious lesson, if we remember that
now as formerly the human mind is liable to be imposed
upon by the illusions of the past, which are ever assuming
some new form.
When we have shaken off the rubbish
of ages, there remain one or two questions of which
the investigation has a permanent value:
1. Did Plato derive the legend
of Atlantis from an Egyptian source? It may be
replied that there is no such legend in any writer
previous to Plato; neither in Homer, nor in Pindar,
nor in Herodotus is there any mention of an Island
of Atlantis, nor any reference to it in Aristotle,
nor any citation of an earlier writer by a later one
in which it is to be found. Nor have any traces
been discovered hitherto in Egyptian monuments of
a connexion between Greece and Egypt older than the
eighth or ninth century B.C. It is true that
Proclus, writing in the fifth century after Christ,
tells us of stones and columns in Egypt on which the
history of the Island of Atlantis was engraved.
The statement may be false there are similar
tales about columns set up ’by the Canaanites
whom Joshua drove out’ (Procop.); but even if
true, it would only show that the legend, 800 years
after the time of Plato, had been transferred to Egypt,
and inscribed, not, like other forgeries, in books,
but on stone. Probably in the Alexandrian age,
when Egypt had ceased to have a history and began
to appropriate the legends of other nations, many such
monuments were to be found of events which had become
famous in that or other countries. The oldest
witness to the story is said to be Crantor, a Stoic
philosopher who lived a generation later than Plato,
and therefore may have borrowed it from him.
The statement is found in Proclus; but we require
better assurance than Proclus can give us before we
accept this or any other statement which he makes.
Secondly, passing from the external
to the internal evidence, we may remark that the story
is far more likely to have been invented by Plato
than to have been brought by Solon from Egypt.
That is another part of his legend which Plato also
seeks to impose upon us. The verisimilitude which
he has given to the tale is a further reason for suspecting
it; for he could easily ‘invent Egyptian or
any other tales’ (Phaedrus). Are not the
words, ‘The truth of the story is a great advantage,’
if we read between the lines, an indication of the
fiction? It is only a legend that Solon went
to Egypt, and if he did he could not have conversed
with Egyptian priests or have read records in their
temples. The truth is that the introduction is
a mosaic work of small touches which, partly by their
minuteness, and also by their seeming probability,
win the confidence of the reader. Who would desire
better evidence than that of Critias, who had heard
the narrative in youth when the memory is strongest
at the age of ten from his grandfather Critias, an
old man of ninety, who in turn had heard it from Solon
himself? Is not the famous expression ’You
Hellènes are ever children and there is no knowledge
among you hoary with age,’ really a compliment
to the Athenians who are described in these words
as ‘ever young’? And is the thought
expressed in them to be attributed to the learning
of the Egyptian priest, and not rather to the genius
of Plato? Or when the Egyptian says ’Hereafter
at our leisure we will take up the written documents
and examine in detail the exact truth about these
things’ what is this but a literary
trick by which Plato sets off his narrative?
Could any war between Athens and the Island of Atlantis
have really coincided with the struggle between the
Greeks and Persians, as is sufficiently hinted though
not expressly stated in the narrative of Plato?
And whence came the tradition to Egypt? or in what
does the story consist except in the war between the
two rival powers and the submersion of both of them?
And how was the tale transferred to the poem of Solon?
‘It is not improbable,’ says Mr. Grote,
‘that Solon did leave an unfinished Egyptian
poem’ (Plato). But are probabilities for
which there is not a tittle of evidence, and which
are without any parallel, to be deemed worthy of attention
by the critic? How came the poem of Solon to
disappear in antiquity? or why did Plato, if the whole
narrative was known to him, break off almost at the
beginning of it?
While therefore admiring the diligence
and erudition of M. Martin, we cannot for a moment
suppose that the tale was told to Solon by an Egyptian
priest, nor can we believe that Solon wrote a poem
upon the theme which was thus suggested to him a
poem which disappeared in antiquity; or that the Island
of Atlantis or the antediluvian Athens ever had any
existence except in the imagination of Plato.
Martin is of opinion that Plato would have been terrified
if he could have foreseen the endless fancies to which
his Island of Atlantis has given occasion. Rather
he would have been infinitely amused if he could have
known that his gift of invention would have deceived
M. Martin himself into the belief that the tradition
was brought from Egypt by Solon and made the subject
of a poem by him. M. Martin may also be gently
censured for citing without sufficient discrimination
ancient authors having very different degrees of authority
and value.
2. It is an interesting and not
unimportant question which is touched upon by Martin,
whether the Atlantis of Plato in any degree held out
a guiding light to the early navigators. He is
inclined to think that there is no real connexion
between them. But surely the discovery of the
New World was preceded by a prophetic anticipation
of it, which, like the hope of a Messiah, was entering
into the hearts of men? And this hope was nursed
by ancient tradition, which had found expression from
time to time in the celebrated lines of Seneca and
in many other places. This tradition was sustained
by the great authority of Plato, and therefore the
legend of the Island of Atlantis, though not closely
connected with the voyages of the early navigators,
may be truly said to have contributed indirectly to
the great discovery.
The Timaeus of Plato, like the Protagoras
and several portions of the Phaedrus and Republic,
was translated by Cicero into Latin. About a
fourth, comprehending with lacunae the first portion
of the dialogue, is preserved in several mss.
These generally agree, and therefore may be supposed
to be derived from a single original. The version
is very faithful, and is a remarkable monument of
Cicero’s skill in managing the difficult and
intractable Greek. In his treatise De Natura Deorum,
he also refers to the Timaeus, which, speaking in
the person of Velleius the Epicurean, he severely
criticises.
The commentary of Proclus on the Timaeus
is a wonderful monument of the silliness and prolixity
of the Alexandrian Age. It extends to about thirty
pages of the book, and is thirty times the length of
the original. It is surprising that this voluminous
work should have found a translator (Thomas Taylor,
a kindred spirit, who was himself a Neo-Platonist,
after the fashion, not of the fifth or sixteenth, but
of the nineteenth century A.D.). The commentary
is of little or no value, either in a philosophical
or philological point of view. The writer is
unable to explain particular passages in any precise
manner, and he is equally incapable of grasping the
whole. He does not take words in their simple
meaning or sentences in their natural connexion.
He is thinking, not of the context in Plato, but of
the contemporary Pythagorean philosophers and their
wordy strife. He finds nothing in the text which
he does not bring to it. He is full of Porphyry,
Iamblichus and Plotinus, of misapplied logic, of misunderstood
grammar, and of the Orphic theology.
Although such a work can contribute
little or nothing to the understanding of Plato, it
throws an interesting light on the Alexandrian times;
it realizes how a philosophy made up of words only
may create a deep and widespread enthusiasm, how the
forms of logic and rhetoric may usurp the place of
reason and truth, how all philosophies grow faded
and discoloured, and are patched and made up again
like worn-out garments, and retain only a second-hand
existence. He who would study this degeneracy
of philosophy and of the Greek mind in the original
cannot do better than devote a few of his days and
nights to the commentary of Proclus on the Timaeus.
A very different account must be given
of the short work entitled ‘Timaeus Locrus,’
which is a brief but clear analysis of the Timaeus
of Plato, omitting the introduction or dialogue and
making a few small additions. It does not allude
to the original from which it is taken; it is quite
free from mysticism and Neo-Platonism. In length
it does not exceed a fifth part of the Timaeus.
It is written in the Doric dialect, and contains several
words which do not occur in classical Greek. No
other indication of its date, except this uncertain
one of language, appears in it. In several places
the writer has simplified the language of Plato, in
a few others he has embellished and exaggerated it.
He generally preserves the thought of the original,
but does not copy the words. On the whole this
little tract faithfully reflects the meaning and spirit
of the Timaeus.
From the garden of the Timaeus, as
from the other dialogues of Plato, we may still gather
a few flowers and present them at parting to the reader.
There is nothing in Plato grander and simpler than
the conversation between Solon and the Egyptian priest,
in which the youthfulness of Hellas is contrasted
with the antiquity of Egypt. Here are to be found
the famous words, ’O Solon, Solon, you Hellènes
are ever young, and there is not an old man among
you’ which may be compared to the
lively saying of Hegel, that ’Greek history began
with the youth Achilles and left off with the youth
Alexander.’ The numerous arts of verisimilitude
by which Plato insinuates into the mind of the reader
the truth of his narrative have been already referred
to. Here occur a sentence or two not wanting
in Platonic irony (Greek a word to the
wise). ’To know or tell the origin of the
other divinities is beyond us, and we must accept
the traditions of the men of old time who affirm themselves
to be the offspring of the Gods that is
what they say and they must surely have
known their own ancestors. How can we doubt the
word of the children of the Gods? Although they
give no probable or certain proofs, still, as they
declare that they are speaking of what took place
in their own family, we must conform to custom and
believe them.’ ’Our creators well
knew that women and other animals would some day be
framed out of men, and they further knew that many
animals would require the use of nails for many purposes;
wherefore they fashioned in men at their first creation
the rudiments of nails.’ Or once more, let
us reflect on two serious passages in which the order
of the world is supposed to find a place in the human
soul and to infuse harmony into it. ’The
soul, when touching anything that has essence, whether
dispersed in parts or undivided, is stirred through
all her powers to declare the sameness or difference
of that thing and some other; and to what individuals
are related, and by what affected, and in what way
and how and when, both in the world of generation and
in the world of immutable being. And when reason,
which works with equal truth, whether she be in the
circle of the diverse or of the same, in
voiceless silence holding her onward course in the
sphere of the self-moved, when reason,
I say, is hovering around the sensible world, and when
the circle of the diverse also moving truly imparts
the intimations of sense to the whole soul, then arise
opinions and beliefs sure and certain. But when
reason is concerned with the rational, and the circle
of the same moving smoothly declares it, then intelligence
and knowledge are necessarily perfected;’ where,
proceeding in a similar path of contemplation, he
supposes the inward and the outer world mutually to
imply each other. ’God invented and gave
us sight to the end that we might behold the courses
of intelligence in the heaven, and apply them to the
courses of our own intelligence which are akin to them,
the unperturbed to the perturbed; and that we, learning
them and partaking of the natural truth of reason,
might imitate the absolutely unerring courses of God
and regulate our own vagaries.’ Or let us
weigh carefully some other profound thoughts, such
as the following. ’He who neglects education
walks lame to the end of his life, and returns imperfect
and good for nothing to the world below.’
’The father and maker of all this universe is
past finding out; and even if we found him, to tell
of him to all men would be impossible.’
’Let me tell you then why the Creator made this
world of generation. He was good, and the good
can never have jealousy of anything. And being
free from jealousy, he desired that all things should
be as like himself as they could be. This is in
the truest sense the origin of creation and of the
world, as we shall do well in believing on the testimony
of wise men: God desired that all things should
be good and nothing bad, so far as this was attainable.’
This is the leading thought in the Timaeus, just as
the idea of Good is the leading thought of the
Republic, the one expression describing the personal,
the other the impersonal Good or God, differing in
form rather than in substance, and both equally implying
to the mind of Plato a divine reality. The slight
touch, perhaps ironical, contained in the words, ‘as
we shall do well in believing on the testimony of wise
men,’ is very characteristic of Plato.