BROWNING AND SORDELLO
There are certain analogies between
Browning as a poet and the Sordello of the poem; between
his relation to the world of his time and that of
Sordello to his time; and finally, between Browning’s
language in this poem and the change in the Italian
language which he imputes to the work of Sordello.
This chapter will discuss these analogies, and close
with an appreciation of Browning’s position
between the classic and romantic schools of poetry.
The analogies of which I write may
be denied, but I do not think they can be disproved.
Browning is, no doubt, separate from Sordello in his
own mind, but underneath the young poet he is creating,
he is continually asking himself the same question
which Sordello asks What shall I do as
an artist? To what conclusion shall I come with
regard to my life as a poet? It is no small proof
of this underlying personal element in the first three
books of the poem that at the end of the third book
Browning flings himself suddenly out of the mediaeval
world and the men he has created, and waking into
1835-40 at Venice, asks himself What am
I writing, and why? What is my aim in being a
poet? Is it worth my while to go on with Sordello’s
story, and why is it worth the telling? In fact,
he allows us to think that he has been describing
in Sordello’s story a transitory phase of his
own career. And then, having done this, he tells
how he got out of confusion into clearer light.
The analogy between Browning’s
and Sordello’s time is not a weak one.
The spirit of the world, between 1830 and 1840 in England,
resembled in many ways the spirit abroad at the beginning
of the thirteenth century. The country had awakened
out of a long sleep, and was extraordinarily curious
not only with regard to life and the best way to live
it, but also with regard to government, law, the condition
of the people, the best kind of religion and how best
to live it, the true aims of poetry and how it was
to be written, what subjects it should work on, what
was to be the mother-motive of it, that is, what was
the mother-motive of all the arts. And this curiosity
deepened from year to year for fifty years. But
even stronger than the curiosity was the eager individualism
of this time, which extended into every sphere of human
thought and action, and only began about 1866 to be
balanced by an equally strong tendency towards collectivism.
These two elements in the time-spirit
did not produce, in a settled state like England,
the outward war and confusion they produced in the
thirteenth century, though they developed after 1840,
in ’48, into a European storm but
they did produce a confused welter of mingled thoughts
concerning the sources and ends of human life, the
action it should take, and why it should take it.
The poetry of Arnold and Clough represents with great
clearness the further development in the soul of man
of this confusion. I think that Browning has represented
in the first three books of Sordello his passage
through this tossing sea of thought.
He had put into Paracelsus
all that he had worked out with clearness during his
youth; his theory of life is stated with lucidity in
that poem. But when it was finished, and he had
entered, like Sordello from Goito into Mantua, into
the crowd and clash of the world; when, having published
Pauline and Paracelsus, he had, like
Sordello, met criticism and misunderstanding, his
Paracelsian theory did not seem to explain humanity
as clearly as he imagined. It was only a theory;
Would it stand the test of life among mankind, be
a saving and healing prophecy? Life lay before
him, now that the silent philosophising of poetic
youth was over, in all its inexplicable, hurried, tormented,
involved, and multitudinously varied movement.
He had built up a transcendental building in Paracelsus.
Was it all to fall in ruin? No answer came when
he looked forth on humanity over whose landscape the
irony of the gods, a bitter mist, seemed to brood.
At what then shall he aim as a poet? What shall
be his subject-matter? How is life to be lived?
Then he thought that he would, as
a poet, describe his own time and his own soul under
the character of Sordello, and place Sordello in a
time more stormy than his own. And he would make
Sordello of an exceptional temper like himself, and
to clash with his time as he was then clashing
with his own. With these thoughts he wrote the
first books of Sordello, and Naddo, the critic
of Sordello’s verses, represents the critics
of Paracelsus and the early poems. I have experienced,
he says of himself in Sordello, something of
the spite of fate.
Then, having done this, he leaves
Sordello at the end of the third book, and turns,
beset with a thousand questions, to himself and his
art in a personal digression. Reclining on a
ruined palace-step at Venice, he thinks of Eglamor
who made a flawless song, the type of those who reach
their own perfection here; and then of Sordello who
made a song which stirred the world far more than
Eglamor’s, which yet was not flawless, not perfect;
but because of its imperfection looked forward uncontented
to a higher song. Shall he, Browning the poet,
choose Eglamor or Sordello; even though Sordello perish
without any achievement? And he chooses to sail
for ever towards the infinite, chooses the imperfection
which looks forward. A sailor who loves voyaging
may say, when weather-bound, “Here rest, unlade
the ship, sleep on this grassy bank.” ’Tis
but a moment on his path; let the wind change, and
he is away again, whether triumph or shipwreck await
him, for ever
The tempter of the everlasting
steppe.
That much is then settled for life
and for poetry. And in that choice of endless
aspiration Browning confirms all that he thought, with
regard to half of his theory of life, in Paracelsus.
This is his first thought for life, and it is embodied
in the whole of Sordello’s career. Sordello
is never content with earth, either when he is young,
or when he passes into the world, or when he dies
not having attained or been already perfect a
thought which is as much at the root of romanticism
as of Christianity. Then comes the further question:
To whom shall I dedicate the service of my art?
Who shall be my motive, the Queen whom I shall love
and write of; and he thinks of Sordello who asks that
question and who, for the time, answers “Palma,”
that is, the passion of love.
“But now, shall I, Browning,
take as my Queen” and he symbolises
his thought in the girls he sees in the boats from
his palace steps “that girl from
Bassano, or from Asolo, or her from Padua; that
is, shall I write of youth’s love, of its tragic
or its comedy, of its darkness, joy and beauty only?
No, he answers, not of that stuff shall I make my work,
but of that sad dishevelled ghost of a girl, half in
rags, with eyes inveterately full of tears; of wild,
worn, care-bitten, ravishing, piteous, and pitiful
Humanity, who begs of me and offers me her faded love
in the street corners. She shall be my Queen,
the subject of my song, the motive of my poetry.
She may be guilty, warped awry from her birth, and
now a tired harlotry; but she shall rest on my shoulder
and I shall comfort her. She is false, mistaken,
degraded, ignorant, but she moves blindly from evil
to good, and from lies to truth, and from ignorance
to knowledge, and from all to love; and all her errors
prove that she has another world in which, the errors
being worked through, she will develop into perfectness.
Slowly she moves, step by step; but not a millionth
part is here done of what she will do at last.
That is the matter of my poetry, which, in its infinite
change and hopes, I shall express in my work.
I shall see it, say what I have seen, and it may be
Impart the gift of seeing
to the rest.
Therefore I have made Sordello, thus far, with all his
weakness and wrong
moulded,
made anew
A Man, and give him to be
turned and tried,
Be angry with or pleased at.”
And then Browning severs himself from
Sordello. After this retirement of thought into
himself, described as taking place in Venice during
an hour, but I dare say ranging over half a year in
reality, he tells the rest of Sordello’s story
from the outside, as a spectator and describer.
Browning has now resolved to dedicate
his art, which is his life, to love of Humanity, of
that pale dishevelled girl, unlovely and lovely, evil
and good; and to tell the story of individual men and
women, and of as many as possible; to paint the good
which is always mixed with their evil; to show that
their failures and sins point to a success and goodness
beyond, because they emerged from aspiration and aspiration
from the divinity at the root of human nature.
But to do this, a poet must not live like Sordello,
in abstractions, nor shrink from the shock of men
and circumstance, nor refuse to take men and life as
they are but throw himself into the vital
present, with its difficulties, baffling elements
and limitations; take its failures for his own; go
through them while he looks beyond them, and, because
he looks beyond them, never lose hope, or retreat
from life, or cease to fight his way onward.
And, to support him in this, there is but one thing infinite
love, pity, and sympathy for mankind, increased, not
lessened by knowledge of the sins and weakness, the
failure and despairs of men. This is Browning’s
second thought for life. But this is the very
thing Sordello, as conceived by Browning, did not
and could not do. He lived in abstractions and
in himself; he tried to discard his human nature, or
to make it bear more than it could bear. He threw
overboard the natural physical life of the body because
it limited, he thought, the outgoings of the imaginative
soul, and only found that in weakening the body he
enfeebled the soul. At every point he resented
the limits of human life and fought against them.
Neither would he live in the world allotted to him,
nor among the men of his time, nor in its turmoil;
but only in imagination of his own inner world, among
men whom he created for himself, of which world he
was to be sole king. He had no love for men;
they wearied, jarred, and disturbed his ideal world.
All he wanted was their applause or their silence,
not their criticism, not their affection. And
of course human love and sympathy for men and insight
into them, departed from him, and with them his art
departed. He never became a true poet.
It is this failure, passing through
several phases of life in which action is demanded
of Sordello, that Browning desired to record in the
last three books of the poem. And he thinks it
worth doing because it is human, and the record of
what is human is always of worth to man. He paints
Sordello’s passage through phase after phase
of thought and act in the outside world, in all of
which he seems for the moment to succeed or to touch
the verge of success, but in which his neglect of the
needs of the body and the uncontentment of his soul
produce failure. At last, at the very moment
of death he knows why he failed, and sees, as through
a glass darkly, the failure making the success of the
world to come. The revelation bursts his heart.
And now what is the end, what is the
result for man of this long striving of Sordello?
Nothing! Nothing has been done. Yet no, there
is one result. The imperfect song he made when
he was young at Goito, in the flush of happiness,
when he forgot himself in love of nature and of the
young folk who wandered rejoicing through the loveliness
of nature that song is still alive, not
in the great world among the noble women and warriors
of the time, but on the lips of the peasant girls of
Asolo who sing it on dewy mornings when they climb
the castle hill. This is the outcome of Sordello’s
life, and it sounds like irony on Browning’s
lips. It is not so; the irony is elsewhere in
the poem, and is of another kind. Here, the conclusion
is, that the poem, or any work of art,
made in joy, in sympathy with human life, moved by
the love of loveliness in man or in nature, lives
and lasts in beauty, heals and makes happy the world.
And it has its divine origin in the artist’s
loss of himself in humanity, and his finding of himself,
through union with humanity, in union with God the
eternal poet. In this is hidden the life of an
artist’s greatness. And here the little
song, which gives joy to a child, and fits in with
and enhances its joy, is greater in the eyes of the
immortal judges than all the glory of the world which
Sordello sought so long for himself alone. It
is a truth Browning never failed to record, the greatness
and power of the things of love; for, indeed, love
being infinite and omnipotent, gives to its smallest
expression the glory of all its qualities.
The second of these analogies between
Browning and Sordello relates to Browning’s
treatment of the English language in the poem of Sordello
and what he pictures Sordello as doing for the Italian
language in the poem. The passage to which I
refer is about half-way in the second book. As
there is no real ground for representing Sordello as
working any serious change in the Italian tongue of
literature except a slight phrase in a treatise of
Dante’s, the representation is manifestly an
invention of Browning’s added to the character
of Sordello as conceived by himself. As such
it probably comes out of, and belongs to, his own
experience. The Sordello who acts thus with language
represents the action of Browning himself at the time
he was writing the poem. If so, the passage is
full of interest.
All we know about Sordello as a poet
is that he wrote some Italian poems. Those by
which he was famous were in Provencal. In Dante’s
treatise on the use of his native tongue, he suggests
that Sordello was one of the pioneers of literary
Italian. So, at least, Browning seems to infer
from the passage, for he makes it the motive of his
little “excursus” on Sordello’s
presumed effort to strike out a new form and method
in poetic language. Nothing was more needed than
such an effort if any fine literature were to arise
in Italy. In this unformed but slowly forming
thirteenth century the language was in as great a
confusion and, I may say, as individual
(for each poet wrote in his own dialect) as the life
of the century.
What does Browning make Sordello do?
He has brought him to Mantua as the accepted master
of song; and Sordello burns to be fully recognised
as the absolute poet. He has felt for some time
that while he cannot act well he can imagine action
well. And he sings his imaginations. But
there is at the root of his singing a love of the applause
of the people more than a love of song for itself.
And he fails to please. So Sordello changes his
subject and sings no longer of himself in the action
of the heroes he imagines, but of abstract ideas,
philosophic dreams and problems. The very critics
cried that he had left human nature behind him.
Vexed at his failure, and still longing to catch the
praise of men, that he may confirm his belief that
he is the loftiest of poets, he makes another effort
to amaze the world. “I’ll write no
more of imaginary things,” he cries; “I
will catch the crowd by reorganising the language
of poetry, by new arrangements of metre and words,
by elaborate phraseology, especially by careful concentration
of thought into the briefest possible frame of words.
I will take the stuff of thought that is,
the common language beat it on the anvil
into new shapes, break down the easy flow of the popular
poetry, and scarcely allow a tithe of the original
words I have written to see the light,
welding
words into the crude
Mass from the new speech round
him, till a rude
Armour was hammered out, in
time to be
Approved beyond the Roman
panoply
Melted to make it.”
That is, he dissolved the Roman dialect
to beat out of it an Italian tongue. And in this
new armour of language he clothed his thoughts.
But the language broke away from his thoughts:
neither expressed them nor made them clear. The
people failed to understand his thought, and at the
new ways of using language the critics sneered.
“Do get back,” they said, “to the
simple human heart, and tell its tales in the simple
language of the people.”
I do not think that the analogy can
be missed. Browning is really describing with,
perhaps, a half-scornful reference to his own desire
for public appreciation what he tried to
do in Sordello for the language in which his
poetry was to be written. I have said that when
he came to write Sordello his mind had fallen
back from the clear theory of life laid down in Paracelsus
into a tumbled sea of troubled thoughts; and Sordello
is a welter of thoughts tossing up and down, now appearing,
then disappearing, and then appearing again in conjunction
with new matter, like objects in a sea above which
a cyclone is blowing. Or we may say that his
mind, before and during the writing of Sordello,
was like the thirteenth century, pressing blindly in
vital disturbance towards an unknown goal. That
partly accounts for the confused recklessness of the
language of the poem. But a great many of the
tricks Browning now played with his poetic language
were deliberately done. He had tried like
Sordello at the Court of Love a love-poem
in Pauline. It had not succeeded.
He had tried in Paracelsus to expose an abstract
theory of life, as Sordello had tried writing on abstract
imaginings. That also had failed. Now he
determined as he represents Sordello doing to
alter his whole way of writing. “I will
concentrate now,” he thought, “since they
say I am too loose and too diffuse; cut away nine-tenths
of all I write, and leave out every word I can possibly
omit. I will not express completely what I think;
I shall only suggest it by an illustration. And
if anything occur to me likely to illuminate it, I
shall not add it afterwards but insert it in a parenthesis.
I will make a new tongue for my poetry.”
And the result was the style and the strange manner
in which Sordello was written. This partly
excuses its obscurity, if deliberation can be an excuse
for a bad manner in literature. Malice prepense
does not excuse a murder, though it makes it more
interesting. Finally, the manner in which Sordello
was written did not please him. He left it behind
him, and Pippa Passes, which followed Sordello,
is as clear and simple as its predecessor is obscure
in style.
Thirdly, the language of Sordello,
and, in a lesser degree, that of all Browning’s
poetry, proves if his whole way of thought
and passion did not also prove it that
Browning was not a classic, that he deliberately put
aside the classic traditions in poetry. In this
he presents a strong contrast to Tennyson. Tennyson
was possessed by those traditions. His masters
were Homer, Vergil, Milton and the rest of those who
wrote with measure, purity, and temperance; and from
whose poetry proceeded a spirit of order, of tranquillity,
of clearness, of simplicity; who were reticent in
ornament, in illustration, and stern in rejection
of unnecessary material. None of these classic
excellences belong to Browning, nor did he ever try
to gain them, and that was, perhaps, a pity.
But, after all, it would have been of no use had he
tried for them. We cannot impose from without
on ourselves that which we have not within; and Browning
was, in spirit, a pure romantic, not a classic.
Tennyson never allowed what romanticism he possessed
to have its full swing. It always wore the classic
dress, submitted itself to the classic traditions,
used the classic forms. In the Idylls of the
King he took a romantic story; but nothing could
be more unromantic than many of the inventions and
the characters; than the temper, the morality, and
the conduct of the poem. The Arthurian poets,
Malory himself, would have jumped out their skin with
amazement, even with indignation, had they read it.
And a great deal of this oddity, this unfitness of
the matter to the manner, arose from the romantic story
being expressed in poetry written in accordance with
classic traditions. Of course, there were other
sources for these inharmonies in the poem, but that
was one, and not the least of them.
Browning had none of these classic
traditions. He had his own matter, quite new
stuff it was; and he made his own manner. He did
not go back to the old stories, but, being filled
with the romantic spirit, embodied it in new forms,
and drenched with it his subjects, whether he took
them from ancient, mediaeval, Renaissance, or modern
life. He felt, and truly, that it is of the essence
of romanticism to be always arising into new shapes,
assimilating itself, century by century, to the needs,
the thought and the passions of growing mankind; progressive,
a lover of change; in steady opposition to that dull
conservatism the tendency to which besets the classic
literature.
Browning had the natural faults of
the romantic poet; and these are most remarkable when
such a poet is young. The faults are the opposites
of the classic poet’s excellences: want
of measure, want of proportion, want of clearness
and simplicity, want of temperance, want of that selective
power which knows what to leave out or when to stop.
And these frequently become positive and end in actual
disorder of composition, huddling of the matters treated
of into ill-digested masses, violence in effects and
phrase, bewildering obscurity, sought-out even desperate
strangeness of subject and expression, uncompromising
individuality, crude ornament, and fierce colour.
Many examples of these faults are to be found in Sordello
and throughout the work of Browning. They are
the extremes into which the Romantic is frequently
hurried.
But, then, Browning has the natural
gifts and excellences of the romantic poet, and these
elements make him dearer than the mere Classic to
a multitude of imaginative persons. One of them
is endless and impassioned curiosity, for ever unsatisfied,
always finding new worlds of thought and feeling into
which to make dangerous and thrilling voyages of discovery voyages
that are filled from end to end with incessantly changing
adventure, or delight in that adventure. This
enchants the world. And it is not only in his
subjects that the romantic poet shows his curiosity.
He is just as curious of new methods of tragedy, of
lyric work, of every mode of poetry; of new ways of
expressing old thoughts; new ways of treating old metres;
of the invention of new metres and new ways of phrasing;
of strange and startling word-combinations, to clothe
fittingly the strange and startling things discovered
in human nature, in one’s own soul, or in the
souls of others. In ancient days such a temper
produced the many tales of invention which filled
the romantic cycles.
Again and again, from century to century,
this romantic spirit has done its re-creating work
in the development of poetry in France, Germany, Italy,
Spain, and England. And in 1840, and for many
years afterwards, it produced in Browning, and for
our pleasure, his dramatic lyrics as he called them;
his psychological studies, which I may well call excursions,
adventures, battles, pursuits, retreats, discoveries
of the soul; for in the soul of man lay, for Browning,
the forest of Broceliande, the wild country of Morgan
lé Fay, the cliffs and moors of Lyonnesse.
It was there, over that unfooted country, that Childe
Roland rode to the Dark Tower. Nor can anything
be more in the temper of old spiritual romance though
with a strangely modern mise-en-scene than
the great adventure on the dark common with Christ
in Christmas-Eve and Easter-Day.
Another root of the romantic spirit
was the sense of, and naturally the belief in, a world
not to be felt of the senses or analysed by the understanding;
which was within the apparent world as its substance
or soul, or beyond it as the power by which it existed;
and this mystic belief took, among poets, philosophers,
theologians, warriors and the common people, a thousand
forms, ranging from full-schemed philosophies to the
wildest superstitions. It tended, in its extremes,
to make this world a shadow, a dream; and our life
only a real life when it habitually dwelt in the mystic
region mortal eye could not see, whose voices mortal
ear could not receive. Out of this root, which
shot its first fibres into the soul of humanity in
the days of the earliest savage and separated him
by an unfathomable gulf from the brute, arose all
the myths and legends and mystic stories which fill
romance. Out of it developed the unquenchable
thirst of those of the romantic temper for communion
with the spiritual beings of this mystic world; a thirst
which, however repressed for a time, always arises
again; and is even now arising among the poets of
to-day.
In Browning’s view of the natural
world some traces of this element of the romantic
spirit may be distinguished, but in his poetry of Man
it scarcely appears. Nor, indeed, is he ever
the true mystic. He had too much of the sense
which handles daily life; he saw the facts of life
too clearly, to fall into the vaguer regions of mysticism.
But one part of its region, and of the romantic spirit,
so incessantly recurs in Browning that it may be said
to underlie the whole of his work. It is that
into which the thoughts and passions of the romantic
poets in all ages ran up, as into a goal the
conception of a perfect world, beyond this visible,
in which the noble hopes, loves and work of humanity baffled,
limited, and ruined here should be fulfilled
and satisfied. The Greeks did not frame this
conception as a people, though Plato outreached towards
it; the Romans had it not, though Vergil seems to
have touched it in hours of inspiration. The Teutonic
folk did not possess it till Christianity invaded
them. Of course, it was alive like a beating
heart in Christianity, that most romantic of all religions.
But the Celtic peoples did conceive it before Christianity
and with a surprising fulness, and wherever they went
through Europe they pushed it into the thought, passions
and action of human life. And out of this conception,
which among the Irish took form as the Land of Eternal
Youth, love and joy, where human trouble ceased, grew
that element in romance which is perhaps the strongest
in it the hunger for eternity, for infinite
perfection of being, and, naturally, for unremitting
pursuit of it; and among Christian folk for a life
here which should fit them for perfect life to come.
Christian romance threw itself with fervour into that
ideal, and the pursuit, for example, of the Holy Grail
is only one of the forms of this hunger for eternity
and perfection.
Browning possessed this element of
romance with remarkable fulness, and expressed it
with undiminished ardour for sixty years of poetic
work. From Pauline to Asolando
it reigns supreme. It is the fountain-source
of Sordello by the pervasiveness
of which the poem consists. Immortal life in
God’s perfection! Into that cry the Romantic’s
hunger for eternity had developed in the soul of Browning.
His heroes, in drama and lyric, in Paracelsus
and Sordello, pass into the infinite, there
to be completed.
And if I may here introduce a kind
of note, it is at this moment that we ought to take
up the Purgatorio, and see Sordello as Dante
saw him in that flowery valley of the Ante-Purgatory
when he talked with Dante and Vergil. He is there
a very different person from the wavering creature
Browning drew. He is on the way to that perfect
fulfilment in God which Browning desired for him and
all mankind.
Nevertheless, in order to complete
this statement, Browning, in his full idea of life,
was not altogether a romantic. He saw there was
a great danger that the romantic mysticism might lead
its pursuers to neglect the duties of life, or lessen
their interest in the drama of mankind. Therefore
he added to his cry for eternity and perfection, his
other cry: “Recognise your limitations,
and work within them, while you must never be content
with them. Give yourself in love and patience
to the present labour of mankind; but never imagine
for a moment that it ends on earth.” He
thus combined with the thirst of the romantic for eternity
the full ethical theory of life, as well as the classic
poet’s determination to represent the complete
aspect of human life on earth. At this point,
but with many fantastic deviations due to his prevailing
romanticism, he was partly of the classic temper.
The poem of Sordello is not without an image
of this temper, set vigorously in contrast with Sordello
himself. This is Salinguerra, who takes the world
as it is, and is only anxious to do what lies before
him day by day. His long soliloquy, in which
for the moment he indulges in dreams, ends in the
simple resolution to fight on, hour by hour, as circumstances
call on him.
Browning’s position, then, is
a combination of the romantic and classical, of the
Christian and ethical, of the imaginative and scientific
views of human life; of the temper which says, “Here
only is our life, here only our concern,” and
that which says, “Not here, but hereafter is
our life.” “Here, and hereafter,”
answered Browning. “Live within earth’s
limits with all your force; never give in, fight on;
but always transcend your fullest action in aspiration,
faith and love.”
It amuses me sometimes the way he
is taken by his readers. The romantic and the
Christian folk often claim him as the despiser of this
world, as one who bids us live wholly for the future,
or in the mystic ranges of thought and passion.
The scientific, humanitarian, and ethical folk accept
that side of him which agrees with their views of human
life views which exclude God, immortality,
and a world beyond that is, they take as
the whole of Browning the lesser part of his theory
of life. This is not creditable to their understanding,
though it is natural enough. We may accept it
as an innocent example of the power of a strong bias
in human nature. But it is well to remember that
the romantic, Christian, mystic elements of human
life are more important in Browning’s eyes than
the ethical or scientific; that the latter are nothing
to him without the former; that the best efforts of
the latter for humanity are in his belief not only
hopeless, but the stuff that dreams are made of, without
the former. In the combination of both is Browning’s
message to mankind.