In the sequence of cultural evolution
the emergence of a leisure class coincides with the
beginning of ownership. This is necessarily the
case, for these two institutions result from the same
set of economic forces. In the inchoate phase
of their development they are but different aspects
of the same general facts of social structure.
It is as elements of social structure conventional
facts that leisure and ownership are matters
of interest for the purpose in hand. An habitual
neglect of work does not constitute a leisure class;
neither does the mechanical fact of use and consumption
constitute ownership. The present inquiry, therefore,
is not concerned with the beginning of indolence,
nor with the beginning of the appropriation of useful
articles to individual consumption. The point
in question is the origin and nature of a conventional
leisure class on the one hand and the beginnings of
individual ownership as a conventional right or equitable
claim on the other hand.
The early differentiation out of which
the distinction between a leisure and a working class
arises is a division maintained between men’s
and women’s work in the lower stages of barbarism.
Likewise the earliest form of ownership is an ownership
of the women by the able bodied men of the community.
The facts may be expressed in more general terms, and
truer to the import of the barbarian theory of life,
by saying that it is an ownership of the woman by
the man.
There was undoubtedly some appropriation
of useful articles before the custom of appropriating
women arose. The usages of existing archaic communities
in which there is no ownership of women is warrant
for such a view. In all communities the members,
both male and female, habitually appropriate to their
individual use a variety of useful things; but these
useful things are not thought of as owned by the person
who appropriates and consumes them. The habitual
appropriation and consumption of certain slight personal
effects goes on without raising the question of ownership;
that is to say, the question of a conventional, equitable
claim to extraneous things.
The ownership of women begins in the
lower barbarian stages of culture, apparently with
the seizure of female captives. The original reason
for the seizure and appropriation of women seems to
have been their usefulness as trophies. The practice
of seizing women from the enemy as trophies, gave
rise to a form of ownership-marriage, resulting in
a household with a male head. This was followed
by an extension of slavery to other captives and inferiors,
besides women, and by an extension of ownership-marriage
to other women than those seized from the enemy.
The outcome of emulation under the circumstances of
a predatory life, therefore, has been on the one hand
a form of marriage resting on coercion, and on the
other hand the custom of ownership. The two institutions
are not distinguishable in the initial phase of their
development; both arise from the desire of the successful
men to put their prowess in evidence by exhibiting
some durable result of their exploits. Both also
minister to that propensity for mastery which pervades
all predatory communities. From the ownership
of women the concept of ownership extends itself to
include the products of their industry, and so there
arises the ownership of things as well as of persons.
In this way a consistent system of
property in goods is gradually installed. And
although in the latest stages of the development,
the serviceability of goods for consumption has come
to be the most obtrusive element of their value, still,
wealth has by no means yet lost its utility as a honorific
evidence of the owner’s prépotence.
Wherever the institution of private
property is found, even in a slightly developed form,
the economic process bears the character of a struggle
between men for the possession of goods. It has
been customary in economic theory, and especially
among those economists who adhere with least faltering
to the body of modernised classical doctrines, to
construe this struggle for wealth as being substantially
a struggle for subsistence. Such is, no doubt,
its character in large part during the earlier and
less efficient phases of industry. Such is also
its character in all cases where the “niggardliness
of nature” is so strict as to afford but a scanty
livelihood to the community in return for strenuous
and unremitting application to the business of getting
the means of subsistence. But in all progressing
communities an advance is presently made beyond this
early stage of technological development. Industrial
efficiency is presently carried to such a pitch as
to afford something appreciably more than a bare livelihood
to those engaged in the industrial process. It
has not been unusual for economic theory to speak
of the further struggle for wealth on this new industrial
basis as a competition for an increase of the comforts
of life, primarily for an increase of the
physical comforts which the consumption of goods affords.
The end of acquisition and accumulation
is conventionally held to be the consumption of the
goods accumulated whether it is consumption
directly by the owner of the goods or by the household
attached to him and for this purpose identified with
him in theory. This is at least felt to be the
economically legitimate end of acquisition, which alone
it is incumbent on the theory to take account of.
Such consumption may of course be conceived to serve
the consumer’s physical wants his
physical comfort or his so-called higher
wants spiritual, aesthetic, intellectual,
or what not; the latter class of wants being served
indirectly by an expenditure of goods, after the fashion
familiar to all economic readers.
But it is only when taken in a sense
far removed from its naïve meaning that consumption
of goods can be said to afford the incentive from which
accumulation invariably proceeds. The motive that
lies at the root of ownership is emulation; and the
same motive of emulation continues active in the further
development of the institution to which it has given
rise and in the development of all those features of
the social structure which this institution of ownership
touches. The possession of wealth confers honour;
it is an invidious distinction. Nothing equally
cogent can be said for the consumption of goods, nor
for any other conceivable incentive to acquisition,
and especially not for any incentive to accumulation
of wealth.
It is of course not to be overlooked
that in a community where nearly all goods are private
property the necessity of earning a livelihood is
a powerful and ever present incentive for the poorer
members of the community. The need of subsistence
and of an increase of physical comfort may for a time
be the dominant motive of acquisition for those classes
who are habitually employed at manual labour, whose
subsistence is on a precarious footing, who possess
little and ordinarily accumulate little; but it will
appear in the course of the discussion that even in
the case of these impecunious classes the predominance
of the motive of physical want is not so decided as
has sometimes been assumed. On the other hand,
so far as regards those members and classes of the
community who are chiefly concerned in the accumulation
of wealth, the incentive of subsistence or of physical
comfort never plays a considerable part. Ownership
began and grew into a human institution on grounds
unrelated to the subsistence minimum. The dominant
incentive was from the outset the invidious distinction
attaching to wealth, and, save temporarily and by
exception, no other motive has usurped the primacy
at any later stage of the development.
Property set out with being booty
held as trophies of the successful raid. So long
as the group had departed and so long as it still stood
in close contact with other hostile groups, the utility
of things or persons owned lay chiefly in an invidious
comparison between their possessor and the enemy from
whom they were taken. The habit of distinguishing
between the interests of the individual and those of
the group to which he belongs is apparently a later
growth. Invidious comparison between the possessor
of the honorific booty and his less successful neighbours
within the group was no doubt present early as an
element of the utility of the things possessed, though
this was not at the outset the chief element of their
value. The man’s prowess was still primarily
the group’s prowess, and the possessor of the
booty felt himself to be primarily the keeper of the
honour of his group. This appreciation of exploit
from the communal point of view is met with also at
later stages of social growth, especially as regards
the laurels of war.
But as soon as the custom of individual
ownership begins to gain consistency, the point of
view taken in making the invidious comparison on which
private property rests will begin to change. Indeed,
the one change is but the reflex of the other.
The initial phase of ownership, the phase of acquisition
by naïve seizure and conversion, begins to pass into
the subsequent stage of an incipient organization of
industry on the basis of private property (in slaves);
the horde develops into a more or less self-sufficing
industrial community; possessions then come to be
valued not so much as evidence of successful foray,
but rather as evidence of the prépotence of the
possessor of these goods over other individuals within
the community. The invidious comparison now becomes
primarily a comparison of the owner with the other
members of the group. Property is still of the
nature of trophy, but, with the cultural advance,
it becomes more and more a trophy of successes scored
in the game of ownership carried on between the members
of the group under the quasi-peaceable methods of
nomadic life.
Gradually, as industrial activity
further displaced predatory activity in the community’s
everyday life and in men’s habits of thought,
accumulated property more and more replaces trophies
of predatory exploit as the conventional exponent
of prépotence and success. With the growth
of settled industry, therefore, the possession of wealth
gains in relative importance and effectiveness as
a customary basis of repute and esteem. Not that
esteem ceases to be awarded on the basis of other,
more direct evidence of prowess; not that successful
predatory aggression or warlike exploit ceases to
call out the approval and admiration of the crowd,
or to stir the envy of the less successful competitors;
but the opportunities for gaining distinction by means
of this direct manifestation of superior force grow
less available both in scope and frequency. At
the same time opportunities for industrial aggression,
and for the accumulation of property, increase in
scope and availability. And it is even more to
the point that property now becomes the most easily
recognised evidence of a reputable degree of success
as distinguished from heroic or signal achievement.
It therefore becomes the conventional basis of esteem.
Its possession in some amount becomes necessary in
order to any reputable standing in the community.
It becomes indispensable to accumulate, to acquire
property, in order to retain one’s good name.
When accumulated goods have in this way once become
the accepted badge of efficiency, the possession of
wealth presently assumes the character of an independent
and definitive basis of esteem. The possession
of goods, whether acquired aggressively by one’s
own exertion or passively by transmission through inheritance
from others, becomes a conventional basis of reputability.
The possession of wealth, which was at the outset
valued simply as an evidence of efficiency, becomes,
in popular apprehension, itself a meritorious act.
Wealth is now itself intrinsically honourable and confers
honour on its possessor. By a further refinement,
wealth acquired passively by transmission from ancestors
or other antecedents presently becomes even more honorific
than wealth acquired by the possessor’s own effort;
but this distinction belongs at a later stage in the
evolution of the pecuniary culture and will be spoken
of in its place.
Prowess and exploit may still remain
the basis of award of the highest popular esteem,
although the possession of wealth has become the basis
of common place reputability and of a blameless social
standing. The predatory instinct and the consequent
approbation of predatory efficiency are deeply ingrained
in the habits of thought of those peoples who have
passed under the discipline of a protracted predatory
culture. According to popular award, the highest
honours within human reach may, even yet, be those
gained by an unfolding of extraordinary predatory
efficiency in war, or by a quasi-predatory efficiency
in statecraft; but for the purposes of a commonplace
decent standing in the community these means of repute
have been replaced by the acquisition and accumulation
of goods. In order to stand well in the eyes of
the community, it is necessary to come up to a certain,
somewhat indefinite, conventional standard of wealth;
just as in the earlier predatory stage it is necessary
for the barbarian man to come up to the tribe’s
standard of physical endurance, cunning, and skill
at arms. A certain standard of wealth in the
one case, and of prowess in the other, is a necessary
condition of reputability, and anything in excess of
this normal amount is meritorious.
Those members of the community who
fall short of this, somewhat indefinite, normal degree
of prowess or of property suffer in the esteem of
their fellow-men; and consequently they suffer also
in their own esteem, since the usual basis of self-respect
is the respect accorded by one’s neighbours.
Only individuals with an aberrant temperament can in
the long run retain their self-esteem in the face of
the disesteem of their fellows. Apparent exceptions
to the rule are met with, especially among people
with strong religious convictions. But these apparent
exceptions are scarcely real exceptions, since such
persons commonly fall back on the putative approbation
of some supernatural witness of their deeds.
So soon as the possession of property
becomes the basis of popular esteem, therefore, it
becomes also a requisite to the complacency which
we call self-respect. In any community where goods
are held in severalty it is necessary, in order to
his own peace of mind, that an individual should possess
as large a portion of goods as others with whom he
is accustomed to class himself; and it is extremely
gratifying to possess something more than others.
But as fast as a person makes new acquisitions, and
becomes accustomed to the resulting new standard of
wealth, the new standard forthwith ceases to afford
appreciably greater satisfaction than the earlier
standard did. The tendency in any case is constantly
to make the present pecuniary standard the point of
departure for a fresh increase of wealth; and this
in turn gives rise to a new standard of sufficiency
and a new pecuniary classification of one’s
self as compared with one’s neighbours.
So far as concerns the present question, the end sought
by accumulation is to rank high in comparison with
the rest of the community in point of pecuniary strength.
So long as the comparison is distinctly unfavourable
to himself, the normal, average individual will live
in chronic dissatisfaction with his present lot; and
when he has reached what may be called the normal pecuniary
standard of the community, or of his class in the community,
this chronic dissatisfaction will give place to a
restless straining to place a wider and ever-widening
pecuniary interval between himself and this average
standard. The invidious comparison can never become
so favourable to the individual making it that he
would not gladly rate himself still higher relatively
to his competitors in the struggle for pecuniary reputability.
In the nature of the case, the desire
for wealth can scarcely be satiated in any individual
instance, and evidently a satiation of the average
or general desire for wealth is out of the question.
However widely, or equally, or “fairly”,
it may be distributed, no general increase of the
community’s wealth can make any approach to satiating
this need, the ground of which approach to satiating
this need, the ground of which is the desire of every
one to excel every one else in the accumulation of
goods. If, as is sometimes assumed, the incentive
to accumulation were the want of subsistence or of
physical comfort, then the aggregate economic wants
of a community might conceivably be satisfied at some
point in the advance of industrial efficiency; but
since the struggle is substantially a race for reputability
on the basis of an invidious comparison, no approach
to a definitive attainment is possible.
What has just been said must not be
taken to mean that there are no other incentives to
acquisition and accumulation than this desire to excel
in pecuniary standing and so gain the esteem and envy
of one’s fellow-men. The desire for added
comfort and security from want is present as a motive
at every stage of the process of accumulation in a
modern industrial community; although the standard
of sufficiency in these respects is in turn greatly
affected by the habit of pecuniary emulation.
To a great extent this emulation shapes the methods
and selects the objects of expenditure for personal
comfort and decent livelihood.
Besides this, the power conferred
by wealth also affords a motive to accumulation.
That propensity for purposeful activity and that repugnance
to all futility of effort which belong to man by virtue
of his character as an agent do not desert him when
he emerges from the naïve communal culture where the
dominant note of life is the unanalysed and undifferentiated
solidarity of the individual with the group with which
his life is bound up. When he enters upon the
predatory stage, where self-seeking in the narrower
sense becomes the dominant note, this propensity goes
with him still, as the pervasive trait that shapes
his scheme of life. The propensity for achievement
and the repugnance to futility remain the underlying
economic motive. The propensity changes only
in the form of its expression and in the proximate
objects to which it directs the man’s activity.
Under the regime of individual ownership the most
available means of visibly achieving a purpose is that
afforded by the acquisition and accumulation of goods;
and as the self-regarding antithesis between man and
man reaches fuller consciousness, the propensity for
achievement the instinct of workmanship tends
more and more to shape itself into a straining to
excel others in pecuniary achievement. Relative
success, tested by an invidious pecuniary comparison
with other men, becomes the conventional end of action.
The currently accepted legitimate end of effort becomes
the achievement of a favourable comparison with other
men; and therefore the repugnance to futility to a
good extent coalesces with the incentive of emulation.
It acts to accentuate the struggle for pecuniary reputability
by visiting with a sharper disapproval all shortcoming
and all evidence of shortcoming in point of pecuniary
success. Purposeful effort comes to mean, primarily,
effort directed to or resulting in a more creditable
showing of accumulated wealth. Among the motives
which lead men to accumulate wealth, the primacy,
both in scope and intensity, therefore, continues
to belong to this motive of pecuniary emulation.
In making use of the term “invidious”,
it may perhaps be unnecessary to remark, there is
no intention to extol or depreciate, or to commend
or deplore any of the phenomena which the word is
used to characterise. The term is used in a technical
sense as describing a comparison of persons with a
view to rating and grading them in respect of relative
worth or value in an aesthetic or moral
sense and so awarding and defining the
relative degrees of complacency with which they may
legitimately be contemplated by themselves and by
others. An invidious comparison is a process
of valuation of persons in respect of worth.