The caution has already been repeated
more than once, that while the regulating norm of
consumption is in large part the requirement of conspicuous
waste, it must not be understood that the motive on
which the consumer acts in any given case is this
principle in its bald, unsophisticated form.
Ordinarily his motive is a wish to conform to established
usage, to avoid unfavorable notice and comment, to
live up to the accepted canons of decency in the kind,
amount, and grade of goods consumed, as well as in
the decorous employment of his time and effort.
In the common run of cases this sense of prescriptive
usage is present in the motives of the consumer and
exerts a direct constraining force, especially as
regards consumption carried on under the eyes of observers.
But a considerable element of prescriptive expensiveness
is observable also in consumption that does not in
any appreciable degree become known to outsiders as,
for instance, articles of underclothing, some articles
of food, kitchen utensils, and other household apparatus
designed for service rather than for evidence.
In all such useful articles a close scrutiny will
discover certain features which add to the cost and
enhance the commercial value of the goods in question,
but do not proportionately increase the serviceability
of these articles for the material purposes which
alone they ostensibly are designed to serve.
Under the selective surveillance of
the law of conspicuous waste there grows up a code
of accredited canons of consumption, the effect of
which is to hold the consumer up to a standard of expensiveness
and wastefulness in his consumption of goods and in
his employment of time and effort. This growth
of prescriptive usage has an immediate effect upon
economic life, but it has also an indirect and remoter
effect upon conduct in other respects as well.
Habits of thought with respect to the expression of
life in any given direction unavoidably affect the
habitual view of what is good and right in life in
other directions also. In the organic complex
of habits of thought which make up the substance of
an individual’s conscious life the economic interest
does not lie isolated and distinct from all other
interests. Something, for instance, has already
been said of its relation to the canons of reputability.
The principle of conspicuous waste
guides the formation of habits of thought as to what
is honest and reputable in life and in commodities.
In so doing, this principle will traverse other norms
of conduct which do not primarily have to do with
the code of pecuniary honor, but which have, directly
or incidentally, an economic significance of some
magnitude. So the canon of honorific waste may,
immediately or remotely, influence the sense of duty,
the sense of beauty, the sense of utility, the sense
of devotional or ritualistic fitness, and the scientific
sense of truth.
It is scarcely necessary to go into
a discussion here of the particular points at which,
or the particular manner in which, the canon of honorific
expenditure habitually traverses the canons of moral
conduct. The matter is one which has received
large attention and illustration at the hands of those
whose office it is to watch and admonish with respect
to any departures from the accepted code of morals.
In modern communities, where the dominant economic
and legal feature of the community’s life is
the institution of private property, one of the salient
features of the code of morals is the sacredness of
property. There needs no insistence or illustration
to gain assent to the proposition that the habit of
holding private property inviolate is traversed by
the other habit of seeking wealth for the sake of the
good repute to be gained through its conspicuous consumption.
Most offenses against property, especially offenses
of an appreciable magnitude, come under this head.
It is also a matter of common notoriety and byword
that in offenses which result in a large accession
of property to the offender he does not ordinarily
incur the extreme penalty or the extreme obloquy with
which his offenses would be visited on the ground of
the naïve moral code alone. The thief or swindler
who has gained great wealth by his delinquency has
a better chance than the small thief of escaping the
rigorous penalty of the law and some good repute accrues
to him from his increased wealth and from his spending
the irregularly acquired possessions in a seemly manner.
A well-bred expenditure of his booty especially appeals
with great effect to persons of a cultivated sense
of the proprieties, and goes far to mitigate the sense
of moral turpitude with which his dereliction is viewed
by them. It may be noted also and
it is more immediately to the point that
we are all inclined to condone an offense against
property in the case of a man whose motive is the
worthy one of providing the means of a “decent”
manner of life for his wife and children. If
it is added that the wife has been “nurtured
in the lap of luxury,” that is accepted as an
additional extenuating circumstance. That is
to say, we are prone to condone such an offense where
its aim is the honorific one of enabling the offender’s
wife to perform for him such an amount of vicarious
consumption of time and substance as is demanded by
the standard of pecuniary decency. In such a
case the habit of approving the accustomed degree of
conspicuous waste traverses the habit of deprecating
violations of ownership, to the extent even of sometimes
leaving the award of praise or blame uncertain.
This is peculiarly true where the dereliction involves
an appreciable predatory or piratical element.
This topic need scarcely be pursued
further here; but the remark may not be out of place
that all that considerable body of morals that clusters
about the concept of an inviolable ownership is itself
a psychological precipitate of the traditional meritoriousness
of wealth. And it should be added that this wealth
which is held sacred is valued primarily for the sake
of the good repute to be got through its conspicuous
consumption. The bearing of pecuniary decency
upon the scientific spirit or the quest of knowledge
will be taken up in some detail in a separate chapter.
Also as regards the sense of devout or ritual merit
and adequacy in this connection, little need be said
in this place. That topic will also come up incidentally
in a later chapter. Still, this usage of honorific
expenditure has much to say in shaping popular tastes
as to what is right and meritorious in sacred matters,
and the bearing of the principle of conspicuous waste
upon some of the commonplace devout observances and
conceits may therefore be pointed out.
Obviously, the canon of conspicuous
waste is accountable for a great portion of what may
be called devout consumption; as, e.g., the consumption
of sacred edifices, vestments, and other goods of the
same class. Even in those modern cults to whose
divinities is imputed a predilection for temples not
built with hands, the sacred buildings and the other
properties of the cult are constructed and decorated
with some view to a reputable degree of wasteful expenditure.
And it needs but little either of observation or introspection and
either will serve the turn to assure us
that the expensive splendor of the house of worship
has an appreciable uplifting and mellowing effect upon
the worshipper’s frame of mind. It will
serve to enforce the same fact if we reflect upon
the sense of abject shamefulness with which any evidence
of indigence or squalor about the sacred place affects
all beholders. The accessories of any devout
observance should be pecuniarily above reproach.
This requirement is imperative, whatever latitude
may be allowed with regard to these accessories in
point of aesthetic or other serviceability. It
may also be in place to notice that in all communities,
especially in neighborhoods where the standard of
pecuniary decency for dwellings is not high, the local
sanctuary is more ornate, more conspicuously wasteful
in its architecture and decoration, than the dwelling
houses of the congregation. This is true of nearly
all denominations and cults, whether Christian or
Pagan, but it is true in a peculiar degree of the
older and maturer cults. At the same time the
sanctuary commonly contributes little if anything
to the physical comfort of the members. Indeed,
the sacred structure not only serves the physical well-being
of the members to but a slight extent, as compared
with their humbler dwelling-houses; but it is felt
by all men that a right and enlightened sense of the
true, the beautiful, and the good demands that in all
expenditure on the sanctuary anything that might serve
the comfort of the worshipper should be conspicuously
absent. If any element of comfort is admitted
in the fittings of the sanctuary, it should be at least
scrupulously screened and masked under an ostensible
austerity. In the most reputable latter-day houses
of worship, where no expense is spared, the principle
of austerity is carried to the length of making the
fittings of the place a means of mortifying the flesh,
especially in appearance. There are few persons
of delicate tastes, in the matter of devout consumption
to whom this austerely wasteful discomfort does not
appeal as intrinsically right and good. Devout
consumption is of the nature of vicarious consumption.
This canon of devout austerity is based on the pecuniary
reputability of conspicuously wasteful consumption,
backed by the principle that vicarious consumption
should conspicuously not conduce to the comfort of
the vicarious consumer.
The sanctuary and its fittings have
something of this austerity in all the cults in which
the saint or divinity to whom the sanctuary pertains
is not conceived to be present and make personal use
of the property for the gratification of luxurious
tastes imputed to him. The character of the sacred
paraphernalia is somewhat different in this respect
in those cults where the habits of life imputed to
the divinity more nearly approach those of an earthly
patriarchal potentate where he is conceived
to make use of these consumable goods in person.
In the latter case the sanctuary and its fittings
take on more of the fashion given to goods destined
for the conspicuous consumption of a temporal master
or owner. On the other hand, where the sacred
apparatus is simply employed in the divinity’s
service, that is to say, where it is consumed vicariously
on his account by his servants, there the sacred properties
take the character suited to goods that are destined
for vicarious consumption only.
In the latter case the sanctuary and
the sacred apparatus are so contrived as not to enhance
the comfort or fullness of life of the vicarious consumer,
or at any rate not to convey the impression that the
end of their consumption is the consumer’s comfort.
For the end of vicarious consumption is to enhance,
not the fullness of life of the consumer, but the
pecuniary repute of the master for whose behoof the
consumption takes place. Therefore priestly vestments
are notoriously expensive, ornate, and inconvenient;
and in the cults where the priestly servitor of the
divinity is not conceived to serve him in the capacity
of consort, they are of an austere, comfortless fashion.
And such it is felt that they should be.
It is not only in establishing a devout
standard of decent expensiveness that the principle
of waste invades the domain of the canons of ritual
serviceability. It touches the ways as well as
the means, and draws on vicarious leisure as well
as on vicarious consumption. Priestly demeanor
at its best is aloof, leisurely, perfunctory, and uncontaminated
with suggestions of sensuous pleasure. This holds
true, in different degrees of course, for the different
cults and denominations; but in the priestly life
of all anthropomorphic cults the marks of a vicarious
consumption of time are visible.
The same pervading canon of vicarious
leisure is also visibly present in the exterior details
of devout observances and need only be pointed out
in order to become obvious to all beholders. All
ritual has a notable tendency to reduce itself to
a rehearsal of formulas. This development of
formula is most noticeable in the maturer cults, which
have at the same time a more austere, ornate, and
severe priestly life and garb; but it is perceptible
also in the forms and methods of worship of the newer
and fresher sects, whose tastes in respect of priests,
vestments, and sanctuaries are less exacting.
The rehearsal of the service (the term “service”
carries a suggestion significant for the point in question)
grows more perfunctory as the cult gains in age and
consistency, and this perfunctoriness of the rehearsal
is very pleasing to the correct devout taste.
And with a good reason, for the fact of its being
perfunctory goes to say pointedly that the master for
whom it is performed is exalted above the vulgar need
of actually proficuous service on the part of his
servants. They are unprofitable servants, and
there is an honorific implication for their master
in their remaining unprofitable. It is needless
to point out the close analogy at this point between
the priestly office and the office of the footman.
It is pleasing to our sense of what is fitting in
these matters, in either case, to recognize in the
obvious perfunctoriness of the service that it is
a pro forma execution only. There should be no
show of agility or of dexterous manipulation in the
execution of the priestly office, such as might suggest
a capacity for turning off the work.
In all this there is of course an
obvious implication as to the temperament, tastes,
propensities, and habits of life imputed to the divinity
by worshippers who live under the tradition of these
pecuniary canons of reputability. Through its
pervading men’s habits of thought, the principle
of conspicuous waste has colored the worshippers’
notions of the divinity and of the relation in which
the human subject stands to him. It is of course
in the more naïve cults that this suffusion of pecuniary
beauty is most patent, but it is visible throughout.
All peoples, at whatever stage of culture or degree
of enlightenment, are fain to eke out a sensibly scant
degree of authentic formation regarding the personality
and habitual surroundings of their divinities.
In so calling in the aid of fancy to enrich and fill
in their picture of the divinity’s presence
and manner of life they habitually impute to him such
traits as go to make up their ideal of a worthy man.
And in seeking communion with the divinity the ways
and means of approach are assimilated as nearly as
may be to the divine ideal that is in men’s
minds at the time. It is felt that the divine
presence is entered with the best grace, and with
the best effect, according to certain accepted methods
and with the accompaniment of certain material circumstances
which in popular apprehension are peculiarly consonant
with the divine nature. This popularly accepted
ideal of the bearing and paraphernalia adequate to
such occasions of communion is, of course, to a good
extent shaped by the popular apprehension of what
is intrinsically worthy and beautiful in human carriage
and surroundings on all occasions of dignified intercourse.
It would on this account be misleading to attempt
an analysis of devout demeanor by referring all evidences
of the presence of a pecuniary standard of reputability
back directly and baldly to the underlying norm of
pecuniary emulation. So it would also be misleading
to ascribe to the divinity, as popularly conceived,
a jealous regard for his pecuniary standing and a
habit of avoiding and condemning squalid situations
and surroundings simply because they are under grade
in the pecuniary respect.
And still, after all allowance has
been made, it appears that the canons of pecuniary
reputability do, directly or indirectly, materially
affect our notions of the attributes of divinity,
as well as our notions of what are the fit and adequate
manner and circumstances of divine communion.
It is felt that the divinity must be of a peculiarly
serene and leisurely habit of life. And whenever
his local habitation is pictured in poetic imagery,
for edification or in appeal to the devout fancy,
the devout word-painter, as a matter of course, brings
out before his auditors’ imagination a throne
with a profusion of the insignia of opulence and power,
and surrounded by a great number of servitors.
In the common run of such presentations of the celestial
abodes, the office of this corps of servants is a
vicarious leisure, their time and efforts being in
great measure taken up with an industrially unproductive
rehearsal of the meritorious characteristics and exploits
of the divinity; while the background of the presentation
is filled with the shimmer of the precious metals
and of the more expensive varieties of precious stones.
It is only in the crasser expressions of
devout fancy that this intrusion of pecuniary canons
into the devout ideals reaches such an extreme.
An extreme case occurs in the devout imagery of the
Negro population of the South. Their word-painters
are unable to descend to anything cheaper than gold;
so that in this case the insistence on pecuniary beauty
gives a startling effect in yellow such
as would be unbearable to a soberer taste. Still,
there is probably no cult in which ideals of pecuniary
merit have not been called in to supplement the ideals
of ceremonial adequacy that guide men’s conception
of what is right in the matter of sacred apparatus.
Similarly it is felt and
the sentiment is acted upon that the priestly
servitors of the divinity should not engage in industrially
productive work; that work of any kind any
employment which is of tangible human use must
not be carried on in the divine presence, or within
the precincts of the sanctuary; that whoever comes
into the presence should come cleansed of all profane
industrial features in his apparel or person, and
should come clad in garments of more than everyday
expensiveness; that on holidays set apart in honor
of or for communion with the divinity no work that
is of human use should be performed by any one.
Even the remoter, lay dependents should render a vicarious
leisure to the extent of one day in seven. In
all these deliverances of men’s uninstructed
sense of what is fit and proper in devout observance
and in the relations of the divinity, the effectual
presence of the canons of pecuniary reputability is
obvious enough, whether these canons have had their
effect on the devout judgment in this respect immediately
or at the second remove.
These canons of reputability have
had a similar, but more far-reaching and more specifically
determinable, effect upon the popular sense of beauty
or serviceability in consumable goods. The requirements
of pecuniary decency have, to a very appreciable extent,
influenced the sense of beauty and of utility in articles
of use or beauty. Articles are to an extent preferred
for use on account of their being conspicuously wasteful;
they are felt to be serviceable somewhat in proportion
as they are wasteful and ill adapted to their ostensible
use.
The utility of articles valued for
their beauty depends closely upon the expensiveness
of the articles. A homely illustration will bring
out this dependence. A hand-wrought silver spoon,
of a commercial value of some ten to twenty dollars,
is not ordinarily more serviceable in the
first sense of the word than a machine-made
spoon of the same material. It may not even be
more serviceable than a machine-made spoon of some
“base” metal, such as aluminum, the value
of which may be no more than some ten to twenty cents.
The former of the two utensils is, in fact, commonly
a less effective contrivance for its ostensible purpose
than the latter. The objection is of course ready
to hand that, in taking this view of the matter, one
of the chief uses, if not the chief use, of the costlier
spoon is ignored; the hand-wrought spoon gratifies
our taste, our sense of the beautiful, while that
made by machinery out of the base metal has no useful
office beyond a brute efficiency. The facts are
no doubt as the objection states them, but it will
be evident on rejection that the objection is after
all more plausible than conclusive. It appears
(1) that while the different materials of which the
two spoons are made each possesses beauty and serviceability
for the purpose for which it is used, the material
of the hand-wrought spoon is some one hundred times
more valuable than the baser metal, without very greatly
excelling the latter in intrinsic beauty of grain or
color, and without being in any appreciable degree
superior in point of mechanical serviceability; (2)
if a close inspection should show that the supposed
hand-wrought spoon were in reality only a very clever
citation of hand-wrought goods, but an imitation so
cleverly wrought as to give the same impression of
line and surface to any but a minute examination by
a trained eye, the utility of the article, including
the gratification which the user derives from its
contemplation as an object of beauty, would immediately
decline by some eighty or ninety per cent, or even
more; (3) if the two spoons are, to a fairly close
observer, so nearly identical in appearance that the
lighter weight of the spurious article alone betrays
it, this identity of form and color will scarcely add
to the value of the machine-made spoon, nor appreciably
enhance the gratification of the user’s “sense
of beauty” in contemplating it, so long as the
cheaper spoon is not a novelty, ad so long as it can
be procured at a nominal cost. The case of the
spoons is typical. The superior gratification
derived from the use and contemplation of costly and
supposedly beautiful products is, commonly, in great
measure a gratification of our sense of costliness
masquerading under the name of beauty. Our higher
appreciation of the superior article is an appreciation
of its superior honorific character, much more frequently
than it is an unsophisticated appreciation of its beauty.
The requirement of conspicuous wastefulness is not
commonly present, consciously, in our canons of taste,
but it is none the less present as a constraining
norm selectively shaping and sustaining our sense of
what is beautiful, and guiding our discrimination
with respect to what may legitimately be approved
as beautiful and what may not.
It is at this point, where the beautiful
and the honorific meet and blend, that a discrimination
between serviceability and wastefulness is most difficult
in any concrete case. It frequently happens that
an article which serves the honorific purpose of conspicuous
waste is at the same time a beautiful object; and
the same application of labor to which it owes its
utility for the former purpose may, and often does,
give beauty of form and color to the article.
The question is further complicated by the fact that
many objects, as, for instance, the precious stones
and the metals and some other materials used for adornment
and decoration, owe their utility as items of conspicuous
waste to an antecedent utility as objects of beauty.
Gold, for instance, has a high degree of sensuous
beauty very many if not most of the highly prized
works of art are intrinsically beautiful, though often
with material qualification; the like is true of some
stuffs used for clothing, of some landscapes, and
of many other things in less degree. Except for
this intrinsic beauty which they possess, these objects
would scarcely have been coveted as they are, or have
become monopolized objects of pride to their possessors
and users. But the utility of these things to
the possessor is commonly due less to their intrinsic
beauty than to the honor which their possession and
consumption confers, or to the obloquy which it wards
off.
Apart from their serviceability in
other respects, these objects are beautiful and have
a utility as such; they are valuable on this account
if they can be appropriated or monopolized; they are,
therefore, coveted as valuable possessions, and their
exclusive enjoyment gratifies the possessor’s
sense of pecuniary superiority at the same time that
their contemplation gratifies his sense of beauty.
But their beauty, in the naïve sense of the word,
is the occasion rather than the ground of their monopolization
or of their commercial value. “Great as
is the sensuous beauty of gems, their rarity and price
adds an expression of distinction to them, which they
would never have if they were cheap.” There
is, indeed, in the common run of cases under this
head, relatively little incentive to the exclusive
possession and use of these beautiful things, except
on the ground of their honorific character as items
of conspicuous waste. Most objects of this general
class, with the partial exception of articles of personal
adornment, would serve all other purposes than the
honorific one equally well, whether owned by the person
viewing them or not; and even as regards personal ornaments
it is to be added that their chief purpose is to lend
eclat to the person of their wearer (or owner) by
comparison with other persons who are compelled to
do without. The aesthetic serviceability of objects
of beauty is not greatly nor universally heightened
by possession.
The generalization for which the discussion
so far affords ground is that any valuable object
in order to appeal to our sense of beauty must conform
to the requirements of beauty and of expensiveness
both. But this is not all. Beyond this the
canon of expensiveness also affects our tastes in
such a way as to inextricably blend the marks of expensiveness,
in our appreciation, with the beautiful features of
the object, and to subsume the resultant effect under
the head of an appreciation of beauty simply.
The marks of expensiveness come to be accepted as
beautiful features of the expensive articles.
They are pleasing as being marks of honorific costliness,
and the pleasure which they afford on this score blends
with that afforded by the beautiful form and color
of the object; so that we often declare that an article
of apparel, for instance, is “perfectly lovely,”
when pretty much all that an analysis of the aesthetic
value of the article would leave ground for is the
declaration that it is pecuniarily honorific.
This blending and confusion of the
elements of expensiveness and of beauty is, perhaps,
best exemplified in articles of dress and of household
furniture. The code of reputability in matters
of dress decides what shapes, colors, materials, and
general effects in human apparel are for the time
to be accepted as suitable; and departures from the
code are offensive to our taste, supposedly as being
departures from aesthetic truth. The approval
with which we look upon fashionable attire is by no
means to be accounted pure make-believe. We readily,
and for the most part with utter sincerity, find those
things pleasing that are in vogue. Shaggy dress-stuffs
and pronounced color effects, for instance, offend
us at times when the vogue is goods of a high, glossy
finish and neutral colors. A fancy bonnet of this
year’s model unquestionably appeals to our sensibilities
today much more forcibly than an equally fancy bonnet
of the model of last year; although when viewed in
the perspective of a quarter of a century, it would,
I apprehend, be a matter of the utmost difficulty
to award the palm for intrinsic beauty to the one
rather than to the other of these structures.
So, again, it may be remarked that, considered simply
in their physical juxtaposition with the human form,
the high gloss of a gentleman’s hat or of a
patent-leather shoe has no more of intrinsic beauty
than a similarly high gloss on a threadbare sleeve;
and yet there is no question but that all well-bred
people (in the Occidental civilized communities) instinctively
and unaffectedly cleave to the one as a phenomenon
of great beauty, and eschew the other as offensive
to every sense to which it can appeal. It is
extremely doubtful if any one could be induced to
wear such a contrivance as the high hat of civilized
society, except for some urgent reason based on other
than aesthetic grounds.
By further habituation to an appreciative
perception of the marks of expensiveness in goods,
and by habitually identifying beauty with reputability,
it comes about that a beautiful article which is not
expensive is accounted not beautiful. In this
way it has happened, for instance, that some beautiful
flowers pass conventionally for offensive weeds; others
that can be cultivated with relative ease are accepted
and admired by the lower middle class, who can afford
no more expensive luxuries of this kind; but these
varieties are rejected as vulgar by those people who
are better able to pay for expensive flowers and who
are educated to a higher schedule of pecuniary beauty
in the florist’s products; while still other
flowers, of no greater intrinsic beauty than these,
are cultivated at great cost and call out much admiration
from flower-lovers whose tastes have been matured
under the critical guidance of a polite environment.
The same variation in matters of taste,
from one class of society to another, is visible also
as regards many other kinds of consumable goods, as,
for example, is the case with furniture, houses, parks,
and gardens. This diversity of views as to what
is beautiful in these various classes of goods is
not a diversity of the norm according to which the
unsophisticated sense of the beautiful works.
It is not a constitutional difference of endowments
in the aesthetic respect, but rather a difference
in the code of reputability which specifies what objects
properly lie within the scope of honorific consumption
for the class to which the critic belongs. It
is a difference in the traditions of propriety with
respect to the kinds of things which may, without
derogation to the consumer, be consumed under the head
of objects of taste and art. With a certain allowance
for variations to be accounted for on other grounds,
these traditions are determined, more or less rigidly,
by the pecuniary plane of life of the class.
Everyday life affords many curious
illustrations of the way in which the code of pecuniary
beauty in articles of use varies from class to class,
as well as of the way in which the conventional sense
of beauty departs in its deliverances from the sense
untutored by the requirements of pecuniary repute.
Such a fact is the lawn, or the close-cropped yard
or park, which appeals so unaffectedly to the taste
of the Western peoples. It appears especially
to appeal to the tastes of the well-to-do classes
in those communities in which the dolicho-blond element
predominates in an appreciable degree. The lawn
unquestionably has an element of sensuous beauty,
simply as an object of apperception, and as such no
doubt it appeals pretty directly to the eye of nearly
all races and all classes; but it is, perhaps, more
unquestionably beautiful to the eye of the dolicho-blond
than to most other varieties of men. This higher
appreciation of a stretch of greensward in this ethnic
element than in the other elements of the population,
goes along with certain other features of the dolicho-blond
temperament that indicate that this racial element
had once been for a long time a pastoral people inhabiting
a region with a humid climate. The close-cropped
lawn is beautiful in the eyes of a people whose inherited
bent it is to readily find pleasure in contemplating
a well-preserved pasture or grazing land.
For the aesthetic purpose the lawn
is a cow pasture; and in some cases today where
the expensiveness of the attendant circumstances bars
out any imputation of thrift the idyl of
the dolicho-blond is rehabilitated in the introduction
of a cow into a lawn or private ground. In such
cases the cow made use of is commonly of an expensive
breed. The vulgar suggestion of thrift, which
is nearly inseparable from the cow, is a standing
objection to the decorative use of this animal.
So that in all cases, except where luxurious surroundings
negate this suggestion, the use of the cow as an object
of taste must be avoided. Where the predilection
for some grazing animal to fill out the suggestion
of the pasture is too strong to be suppressed, the
cow’s place is often given to some more or less
inadequate substitute, such as deer, antelopes, or
some such exotic beast. These substitutes, although
less beautiful to the pastoral eye of Western man
than the cow, are in such cases preferred because
of their superior expensiveness or futility, and their
consequent repute. They are not vulgarly lucrative
either in fact or in suggestion.
Public parks of course fall in the
same category with the lawn; they too, at their best,
are imitations of the pasture. Such a park is
of course best kept by grazing, and the cattle on
the grass are themselves no mean addition to the beauty
of the thing, as need scarcely be insisted on with
anyone who has once seen a well-kept pasture.
But it is worth noting, as an expression of the pecuniary
element in popular taste, that such a method of keeping
public grounds is seldom resorted to. The best
that is done by skilled workmen under the supervision
of a trained keeper is a more or less close imitation
of a pasture, but the result invariably falls somewhat
short of the artistic effect of grazing. But
to the average popular apprehension a herd of cattle
so pointedly suggests thrift and usefulness that their
presence in the public pleasure ground would be intolerably
cheap. This method of keeping grounds is comparatively
inexpensive, therefore it is indecorous.
Of the same general bearing is another
feature of public grounds. There is a studious
exhibition of expensiveness coupled with a make-believe
of simplicity and crude serviceability. Private
grounds also show the same physiognomy wherever they
are in the management or ownership of persons whose
tastes have been formed under middle-class habits of
life or under the upper-class traditions of no later
a date than the childhood of the generation that is
now passing. Grounds which conform to the instructed
tastes of the latter-day upper class do not show these
features in so marked a degree. The reason for
this difference in tastes between the past and the
incoming generation of the well-bred lies in the changing
economic situation. A similar difference is perceptible
in other respects, as well as in the accepted ideals
of pleasure grounds. In this country as in most
others, until the last half century but a very small
proportion of the population were possessed of such
wealth as would exempt them from thrift. Owing
to imperfect means of communication, this small fraction
were scattered and out of effective touch with one
another. There was therefore no basis for a growth
of taste in disregard of expensiveness. The revolt
of the well-bred taste against vulgar thrift was unchecked.
Wherever the unsophisticated sense of beauty might
show itself sporadically in an approval of inexpensive
or thrifty surroundings, it would lack the “social
confirmation” which nothing but a considerable
body of like-minded people can give. There was,
therefore, no effective upper-class opinion that would
overlook evidences of possible inexpensiveness in
the management of grounds; and there was consequently
no appreciable divergence between the leisure-class
and the lower middle-class ideal in the physiognomy
of pleasure grounds. Both classes equally constructed
their ideals with the fear of pecuniary disrepute
before their eyes.
Today a divergence in ideals is beginning
to be apparent. The portion of the leisure class
that has been consistently exempt from work and from
pecuniary cares for a generation or more is now large
enough to form and sustain opinion in matters of taste.
Increased mobility of the members has also added to
the facility with which a “social confirmation”
can be attained within the class. Within this
select class the exemption from thrift is a matter
so commonplace as to have lost much of its utility
as a basis of pecuniary decency. Therefore the
latter-day upper-class canons of taste do not so consistently
insist on an unremitting demonstration of expensiveness
and a strict exclusion of the appearance of thrift.
So, a predilection for the rustic and the “natural”
in parks and grounds makes its appearance on these
higher social and intellectual levels. This predilection
is in large part an outcropping of the instinct of
workmanship; and it works out its results with varying
degrees of consistency. It is seldom altogether
unaffected, and at times it shades off into something
not widely different from that make-believe of rusticity
which has been referred to above.
A weakness for crudely serviceable
contrivances that pointedly suggest immediate and
wasteless use is present even in the middle-class tastes;
but it is there kept well in hand under the unbroken
dominance of the canon of reputable futility.
Consequently it works out in a variety of ways and
means for shamming serviceability in such
contrivances as rustic fences, bridges, bowers, pavilions,
and the like decorative features. An expression
of this affectation of serviceability, at what is
perhaps its widest divergence from the first promptings
of the sense of economic beauty, is afforded by the
cast-iron rustic fence and trellis or by a circuitous
drive laid across level ground.
The select leisure class has outgrown
the use of these pseudo-serviceable variants of pecuniary
beauty, at least at some points. But the taste
of the more recent accessions to the leisure class
proper and of the middle and lower classes still requires
a pecuniary beauty to supplement the aesthetic beauty,
even in those objects which are primarily admired
for the beauty that belongs to them as natural growths.
The popular taste in these matters
is to be seen in the prevalent high appreciation of
topiary work and of the conventional flower-beds of
public grounds. Perhaps as happy an illustration
as may be had of this dominance of pecuniary beauty
over aesthetic beauty in middle-class tastes is seen
in the reconstruction of the grounds lately occupied
by the Columbian Exposition. The evidence goes
to show that the requirement of reputable expensiveness
is still present in good vigor even where all ostensibly
lavish display is avoided. The artistic effects
actually wrought in this work of reconstruction diverge
somewhat widely from the effect to which the same
ground would have lent itself in hands not guided
by pecuniary canons of taste. And even the better
class of the city’s population view the progress
of the work with an unreserved approval which suggests
that there is in this case little if any discrepancy
between the tastes of the upper and the lower or middle
classes of the city. The sense of beauty in the
population of this representative city of the advanced
pecuniary culture is very chary of any departure from
its great cultural principle of conspicuous waste.
The love of nature, perhaps itself
borrowed from a higher-class code of taste, sometimes
expresses itself in unexpected ways under the guidance
of this canon of pecuniary beauty, and leads to results
that may seem incongruous to an unreflecting beholder.
The well-accepted practice of planting trees in the
treeless areas of this country, for instance, has
been carried over as an item of honorific expenditure
into the heavily wooded areas; so that it is by no
means unusual for a village or a farmer in the wooded
country to clear the land of its native trees and
immediately replant saplings of certain introduced
varieties about the farmyard or along the streets.
In this way a forest growth of oak, elm, beech, butternut,
hemlock, basswood, and birch is cleared off to give
room for saplings of soft maple, cottonwood, and brittle
willow. It is felt that the inexpensiveness of
leaving the forest trees standing would derogate from
the dignity that should invest an article which is
intended to serve a decorative and honorific end.
The like pervading guidance of taste
by pecuniary repute is traceable in the prevalent
standards of beauty in animals. The part played
by this canon of taste in assigning her place in the
popular aesthetic scale to the cow has already been
spokes of. Something to the same effect is true
of the other domestic animals, so far as they are in
an appreciable degree industrially useful to the community as,
for instance, barnyard fowl, hogs, cattle, sheep,
goats, draught-horses. They are of the nature
of productive goods, and serve a useful, often a lucrative
end; therefore beauty is not readily imputed to them.
The case is different with those domestic animals
which ordinarily serve no industrial end; such as
pigeons, parrots and other cage-birds, cats, dogs,
and fast horses. These commonly are items of
conspicuous consumption, and are therefore honorific
in their nature and may legitimately be accounted
beautiful. This class of animals are conventionally
admired by the body of the upper classes, while the
pecuniarily lower classes and that select
minority of the leisure class among whom the rigorous
canon that abjures thrift is in a measure obsolescent find
beauty in one class of animals as in another, without
drawing a hard and fast line of pecuniary demarcation
between the beautiful and the ugly. In the case
of those domestic animals which are honorific and
are reputed beautiful, there is a subsidiary basis
of merit that should be spokes of. Apart from
the birds which belong in the honorific class of domestic
animals, and which owe their place in this class to
their non-lucrative character alone, the animals which
merit particular attention are cats, dogs, and fast
horses. The cat is less reputable than the other
two just named, because she is less wasteful; she
may even serve a useful end. At the same time
the cat’s temperament does not fit her for the
honorific purpose. She lives with man on terms
of equality, knows nothing of that relation of status
which is the ancient basis of all distinctions of worth,
honor, and repute, and she does not lend herself with
facility to an invidious comparison between her owner
and his neighbors. The exception to this last
rule occurs in the case of such scarce and fanciful
products as the Angora cat, which have some slight
honorific value on the ground of expensiveness, and
have, therefore, some special claim to beauty on pecuniary
grounds.
The dog has advantages in the way
of uselessness as well as in special gifts of temperament.
He is often spoken of, in an eminent sense, as the
friend of man, and his intelligence and fidelity are
praised. The meaning of this is that the dog
is man’s servant and that he has the gift of
an unquestioning subservience and a slave’s quickness
in guessing his master’s mood. Coupled
with these traits, which fit him well for the relation
of status and which must for the present
purpose be set down as serviceable traits the
dog has some characteristics which are of a more equivocal
aesthetic value. He is the filthiest of the domestic
animals in his person and the nastiest in his habits.
For this he makes up is a servile, fawning attitude
towards his master, and a readiness to inflict damage
and discomfort on all else. The dog, then, commends
himself to our favor by affording play to our propensity
for mastery, and as he is also an item of expense,
and commonly serves no industrial purpose, he holds
a well-assured place in men’s regard as a thing
of good repute. The dog is at the same time associated
in our imagination with the chase a meritorious
employment and an expression of the honorable predatory
impulse. Standing on this vantage ground, whatever
beauty of form and motion and whatever commendable
mental traits he may possess are conventionally acknowledged
and magnified. And even those varieties of the
dog which have been bred into grotesque deformity
by the dog-fancier are in good faith accounted beautiful
by many. These varieties of dogs and
the like is true of other fancy-bred animals are
rated and graded in aesthetic value somewhat in proportion
to the degree of grotesqueness and instability of the
particular fashion which the deformity takes in the
given case. For the purpose in hand, this differential
utility on the ground of grotesqueness and instability
of structure is reducible to terms of a greater scarcity
and consequent expense. The commercial value
of canine monstrosities, such as the prevailing styles
of pet dogs both for men’s and women’s
use, rests on their high cost of production, and their
value to their owners lies chiefly in their utility
as items of conspicuous consumption. In directly,
through reflection Upon their honorific expensiveness,
a social worth is imputed to them; and so, by an easy
substitution of words and ideas, they come to be admired
and reputed beautiful. Since any attention bestowed
upon these animals is in no sense gainful or useful,
it is also reputable; and since the habit of giving
them attention is consequently not deprecated, it
may grow into an habitual attachment of great tenacity
and of a most benevolent character. So that in
the affection bestowed on pet animals the canon of
expensiveness is present more or less remotely as
a norm which guides and shapes the sentiment and the
selection of its object. The like is true, as
will be noticed presently, with respect to affection
for persons also; although the manner in which the
norm acts in that case is somewhat different.
The case of the fast horse is much
like that of the dog. He is on the whole expensive,
or wasteful and useless for the industrial
purpose. What productive use he may possess,
in the way of enhancing the well-being of the community
or making the way of life easier for men, takes the
form of exhibitions of force and facility of motion
that gratify the popular aesthetic sense. This
is of course a substantial serviceability. The
horse is not endowed with the spiritual aptitude for
servile dependence in the same measure as the dog;
but he ministers effectually to his master’s
impulse to convert the “animate” forces
of the environment to his own use and discretion and
so express his own dominating individuality through
them. The fast horse is at least potentially
a race-horse, of high or low degree; and it is as such
that he is peculiarly serviceable to his owner.
The utility of the fast horse lies largely in his
efficiency as a means of emulation; it gratifies the
owner’s sense of aggression and dominance to
have his own horse outstrip his neighbor’s.
This use being not lucrative, but on the whole pretty
consistently wasteful, and quite conspicuously so,
it is honorific, and therefore gives the fast horse
a strong presumptive position of reputability.
Beyond this, the race-horse proper has also a similarly
non-industrial but honorific use as a gambling instrument.
The fast horse, then, is aesthetically
fortunate, in that the canon of pecuniary good repute
legitimates a free appreciation of whatever beauty
or serviceability he may possess. His pretensions
have the countenance of the principle of conspicuous
waste and the backing of the predatory aptitude for
dominance and emulation. The horse is, moreover,
a beautiful animal, although the race-horse is so
in no peculiar degree to the uninstructed taste of
those persons who belong neither in the class of race-horse
fanciers nor in the class whose sense of beauty is
held in abeyance by the moral constraint of the horse
fancier’s award. To this untutored taste
the most beautiful horse seems to be a form which has
suffered less radical alteration than the race-horse
under the breeder’s selective development of
the animal. Still, when a writer or speaker especially
of those whose eloquence is most consistently commonplace
wants an illustration of animal grace and serviceability,
for rhetorical use, he habitually turns to the horse;
and he commonly makes it plain before he is done that
what he has in mind is the race-horse.
It should be noted that in the graduated
appreciation of varieties of horses and of dogs, such
as one meets with among people of even moderately
cultivated tastes in these matters, there is also discernible
another and more direct line of influence of the leisure-class
canons of reputability. In this country, for
instance, leisure-class tastes are to some extent
shaped on usages and habits which prevail, or which
are apprehended to prevail, among the leisure class
of Great Britain. In dogs this is true to a less
extent than in horses. In horses, more particularly
in saddle horses which at their best serve
the purpose of wasteful display simply it
will hold true in a general way that a horse is more
beautiful in proportion as he is more English; the
English leisure class being, for purposes of reputable
usage, the upper leisure class of this country, and
so the exemplar for the lower grades. This mimicry
in the methods of the apperception of beauty and in
the forming of judgments of taste need not result
in a spurious, or at any rate not a hypocritical or
affected, predilection. The predilection is as
serious and as substantial an award of taste when
it rests on this basis as when it rests on any other,
the difference is that this taste is and as substantial
an award of taste when it rests on this basis as when
it rests on any other; the difference is that this
taste is a taste for the reputably correct, not for
the aesthetically true.
The mimicry, it should be said, extends
further than to the sense of beauty in horseflesh
simply. It includes trappings and horsemanship
as well, so that the correct or reputably beautiful
seat or posture is also decided by English usage,
as well as the equestrian gait. To show how fortuitous
may sometimes be the circumstances which decide what
shall be becoming and what not under the pecuniary
canon of beauty, it may be noted that this English
seat, and the peculiarly distressing gait which has
made an awkward seat necessary, are a survival from
the time when the English roads were so bad with mire
and mud as to be virtually impassable for a horse
travelling at a more comfortable gait; so that a person
of decorous tastes in horsemanship today rides a punch
with docked tail, in an uncomfortable posture and
at a distressing gait, because the English roads during
a great part of the last century were impassable for
a horse travelling at a more horse-like gait, or for
an animal built for moving with ease over the firm
and open country to which the horse is indigenous.
It is not only with respect to consumable goods including
domestic animals that the canons of taste
have been colored by the canons of pecuniary reputability.
Something to the like effect is to be said for beauty
in persons. In order to avoid whatever may be
matter of controversy, no weight will be given in this
connection to such popular predilection as there may
be for the dignified (leisurely) bearing and poly
presence that are by vulgar tradition associated with
opulence in mature men. These traits are in some
measure accepted as elements of personal beauty.
But there are certain elements of feminine beauty,
on the other hand, which come in under this head,
and which are of so concrete and specific a character
as to admit of itemized appreciation. It is more
or less a rule that in communities which are at the
stage of economic development at which women are valued
by the upper class for their service, the ideal of
female beauty is a robust, large-limbed woman.
The ground of appreciation is the physique, while
the conformation of the face is of secondary weight
only. A well-known instance of this ideal of
the early predatory culture is that of the maidens
of the Homeric poems.
This ideal suffers a change in the
succeeding development, when, in the conventional
scheme, the office of the high-class wife comes to
be a vicarious leisure simply. The ideal then
includes the characteristics which are supposed to
result from or to go with a life of leisure consistently
enforced. The ideal accepted under these circumstances
may be gathered from descriptions of beautiful women
by poets and writers of the chivalric times.
In the conventional scheme of those days ladies of
high degree were conceived to be in perpetual tutelage,
and to be scrupulously exempt from all useful work.
The resulting chivalric or romantic ideal of beauty
takes cognizance chiefly of the face, and dwells on
its delicacy, and on the delicacy of the hands and
feet, the slender figure, and especially the slender
waist. In the pictured representations of the
women of that time, and in modern romantic imitators
of the chivalric thought and feeling, the waist is
attenuated to a degree that implies extreme debility.
The same ideal is still extant among a considerable
portion of the population of modern industrial communities;
but it is to be said that it has retained its hold
most tenaciously in those modern communities which
are least advanced in point of economic and civil
development, and which show the most considerable
survivals of status and of predatory institutions.
That is to say, the chivalric ideal is best preserved
in those existing communities which are substantially
least modern. Survivals of this lackadaisical
or romantic ideal occur freely in the tastes of the
well-to-do classes of Continental countries. In
modern communities which have reached the higher levels
of industrial development, the upper leisure class
has accumulated so great a mass of wealth as to place
its women above all imputation of vulgarly productive
labor. Here the status of women as vicarious
consumers is beginning to lose its place in the sections
of the body of the people; and as a consequence the
ideal of feminine beauty is beginning to change back
again from the infirmly delicate, translucent, and
hazardously slender, to a woman of the archaic type
that does not disown her hands and feet, nor, indeed,
the other gross material facts of her person.
In the course of economic development the ideal of
beauty among the peoples of the Western culture has
shifted from the woman of physical presence to the
lady, and it is beginning to shift back again to the
woman; and all in obedience to the changing conditions
of pecuniary emulation. The exigencies of emulation
at one time required lusty slaves; at another time
they required a conspicuous performance of vicarious
leisure and consequently an obvious disability; but
the situation is now beginning to outgrow this last
requirement, since, under the higher efficiency of
modern industry, leisure in women is possible so far
down the scale of reputability that it will no longer
serve as a definitive mark of the highest pecuniary
grade.
Apart from this general control exercised
by the norm of conspicuous waste over the ideal of
feminine beauty, there are one or two details which
merit specific mention as showing how it may exercise
an extreme constraint in detail over men’s sense
of beauty in women. It has already been noticed
that at the stages of economic evolution at which
conspicuous leisure is much regarded as a means of
good repute, the ideal requires delicate and diminutive
bands and feet and a slender waist. These features,
together with the other, related faults of structure
that commonly go with them, go to show that the person
so affected is incapable of useful effort and must
therefore be supported in idleness by her owner.
She is useless and expensive, and she is consequently
valuable as evidence of pecuniary strength. It
results that at this cultural stage women take thought
to alter their persons, so as to conform more nearly
to the requirements of the instructed taste of the
time; and under the guidance of the canon of pecuniary
decency, the men find the resulting artificially induced
pathological features attractive. So, for instance,
the constricted waist which has had so wide and persistent
a vogue in the communities of the Western culture,
and so also the deformed foot of the Chinese.
Both of these are mutilations of unquestioned repulsiveness
to the untrained sense. It requires habituation
to become reconciled to them. Yet there is no
room to question their attractiveness to men into
whose scheme of life they fit as honorific items sanctioned
by the requirements of pecuniary reputability.
They are items of pecuniary and cultural beauty which
have come to do duty as elements of the ideal of womanliness.
The connection here indicated between
the aesthetic value and the invidious pecuniary value
of things is of course not present in the consciousness
of the valuer. So far as a person, in forming
a judgment of taste, takes thought and reflects that
the object of beauty under consideration is wasteful
and reputable, and therefore may legitimately be accounted
beautiful; so far the judgment is not a bona fide judgment
of taste and does not come up for consideration in
this connection. The connection which is here
insisted on between the reputability and the apprehended
beauty of objects lies through the effect which the
fact of reputability has upon the valuer’s habits
of thought. He is in the habit of forming judgments
of value of various kinds-economic, moral, aesthetic,
or reputable concerning the objects with which he has
to do, and his attitude of commendation towards a
given object on any other ground will affect the degree
of his appreciation of the object when he comes to
value it for the aesthetic purpose. This is more
particularly true as regards valuation on grounds
so closely related to the aesthetic ground as that
of reputability. The valuation for the aesthetic
purpose and for the purpose of repute are not held
apart as distinctly as might be. Confusion is
especially apt to arise between these two kinds of
valuation, because the value of objects for repute
is not habitually distinguished in speech by the use
of a special descriptive term. The result is
that the terms in familiar use to designate categories
or elements of beauty are applied to cover this unnamed
element of pecuniary merit, and the corresponding
confusion of ideas follows by easy consequence.
The demands of reputability in this way coalesce in
the popular apprehension with the demands of the sense
of beauty, and beauty which is not accompanied by
the accredited marks of good repute is not accepted.
But the requirements of pecuniary reputability and
those of beauty in the naïve sense do not in any appreciable
degree coincide. The elimination from our surroundings
of the pecuniarily unfit, therefore, results in a
more or less thorough elimination of that considerable
range of elements of beauty which do not happen to
conform to the pecuniary requirement. The underlying
norms of taste are of very ancient growth, probably
far antedating the advent of the pecuniary institutions
that are here under discussion. Consequently,
by force of the past selective adaptation of men’s
habits of thought, it happens that the requirements
of beauty, simply, are for the most part best satisfied
by inexpensive contrivances and structures which in
a straightforward manner suggest both the office which
they are to perform and the method of serving their
end. It may be in place to recall the modern
psychological position. Beauty of form seems to
be a question of facility of apperception. The
proposition could perhaps safely be made broader than
this. If abstraction is made from association,
suggestion, and “expression,” classed
as elements of beauty, then beauty in any perceived
object means that the mid readily unfolds its apperceptive
activity in the directions which the object in question
affords. But the directions in which activity
readily unfolds or expresses itself are the directions
to which long and close habituation has made the mind
prone. So far as concerns the essential elements
of beauty, this habituation is an habituation so close
and long as to have induced not only a proclivity
to the apperceptive form in question, but an adaptation
of physiological structure and function as well.
So far as the economic interest enters into the constitution
of beauty, it enters as a suggestion or expression
of adequacy to a purpose, a manifest and readily inferable
subservience to the life process. This expression
of economic facility or economic serviceability in
any object what may be called the economic
beauty of the object-is best sewed by neat and unambiguous
suggestion of its office and its efficiency for the
material ends of life.
On this ground, among objects of use
the simple and unadorned article is aesthetically
the best. But since the pecuniary canon of reputability
rejects the inexpensive in articles appropriated to
individual consumption, the satisfaction of our craving
for beautiful things must be sought by way of compromise.
The canons of beauty must be circumvented by some
contrivance which will give evidence of a reputably
wasteful expenditure, at the same time that it meets
the demands of our critical sense of the useful and
the beautiful, or at least meets the demand of some
habit which has come to do duty in place of that sense.
Such an auxiliary sense of taste is the sense of novelty;
and this latter is helped out in its surrogateship
by the curiosity with which men view ingenious and
puzzling contrivances. Hence it comes that most
objects alleged to be beautiful, and doing duty as
such, show considerable ingenuity of design and are
calculated to puzzle the beholder to bewilder
him with irrelevant suggestions and hints of the improbable at
the same time that they give evidence of an expenditure
of labor in excess of what would give them their fullest
efficency for their ostensible economic end.
This may be shown by an illustration
taken from outside the range of our everyday habits
and everyday contact, and so outside the range of
our bias. Such are the remarkable feather mantles
of Hawaii, or the well-known cawed handles of the
ceremonial adzes of several Polynesian islands.
These are undeniably beautiful, both in the sense that
they offer a pleasing composition of form, lines,
and color, and in the sense that they evince great
skill and ingenuity in design and construction.
At the same time the articles are manifestly ill fitted
to serve any other economic purpose. But it is
not always that the evolution of ingenious and puzzling
contrivances under the guidance of the canon of wasted
effort works out so happy a result. The result
is quite as often a virtually complete suppression
of all elements that would bear scrutiny as expressions
of beauty, or of serviceability, and the substitution
of evidences of misspent ingenuity and labor, backed
by a conspicuous ineptitude; until many of the objects
with which we surround ourselves in everyday life,
and even many articles of everyday dress and ornament,
are such as would not be tolerated except under the
stress of prescriptive tradition. Illustrations
of this substitution of ingenuity and expense in place
of beauty and serviceability are to be seen, for instance,
in domestic architecture, in domestic art or fancy
work, in various articles of apparel, especially of
feminine and priestly apparel.
The canon of beauty requires expression
of the generic. The “novelty” due
to the demands of conspicuous waste traverses this
canon of beauty, in that it results in making the
physiognomy of our objects of taste a congeries of
idiosyncrasies; and the idiosyncrasies are, moreover,
under the selective surveillance of the canon of expensiveness.
This process of selective adaptation
of designs to the end of conspicuous waste, and the
substitution of pecuniary beauty for aesthetic beauty,
has been especially effective in the development of
architecture. It would be extremely difficult
to find a modern civilized residence or public building
which can claim anything better than relative inoffensiveness
in the eyes of anyone who will dissociate the elements
of beauty from those of honorific waste. The endless
variety of fronts presented by the better class of
tenements and apartment houses in our cities is an
endless variety of architectural distress and of suggestions
of expensive discomfort. Considered as objects
of beauty, the dead walls of the sides and back of
these structures, left untouched by the hands of the
artist, are commonly the best feature of the building.
What has been said of the influence
of the law of conspicuous waste upon the canons of
taste will hold true, with but a slight change of terms,
of its influence upon our notions of the serviceability
of goods for other ends than the aesthetic one.
Goods are produced and consumed as a means to the
fuller unfolding of human life; and their utility consists,
in the first instance, in their efficiency as means
to this end. The end is, in the first instance,
the fullness of life of the individual, taken in absolute
terms. But the human proclivity to emulation has
seized upon the consumption of goods as a means to
an invidious comparison, and has thereby invested
constable goods with a secondary utility as evidence
of relative ability to pay. This indirect or secondary
use of consumable goods lends an honorific character
to consumption and presently also to the goods which
best serve the emulative end of consumption. The
consumption of expensive goods is meritorious, and
the goods which contain an appreciable element of
cost in excess of what goes to give them serviceability
for their ostensible mechanical purpose are honorific.
The marks of superfluous costliness in the goods are
therefore marks of worth of high efficency
for the indirect, invidious end to be served by their
consumption; and conversely, goods are humilific,
and therefore unattractive, if they show too thrifty
an adaptation to the mechanical end sought and do
not include a margin of expensiveness on which to
rest a complacent invidious comparison. This
indirect utility gives much of their value to the “better”
grades of goods. In order to appeal to the cultivated
sense of utility, an article must contain a modicum
of this indirect utility.
While men may have set out with disapproving
an inexpensive manner of living because it indicated
inability to spend much, and so indicated a lack of
pecuniary success, they end by falling into the habit
of disapproving cheap things as being intrinsically
dishonorable or unworthy because they are cheap.
As time has gone on, each succeeding generation has
received this tradition of meritorious expenditure
from the generation before it, and has in its turn
further elaborated and fortified the traditional canon
of pecuniary reputability in goods consumed; until
we have finally reached such a degree of conviction
as to the unworthiness of all inexpensive things,
that we have no longer any misgivings in formulating
the maxim, “Cheap and nasty.” So
thoroughly has the habit of approving the expensive
and disapproving the inexpensive been ingrained into
our thinking that we instinctively insist upon at
least some measure of wasteful expensiveness in all
our consumption, even in the case of goods which are
consumed in strict privacy and without the slightest
thought of display. We all feel, sincerely and
without misgiving, that we are the more lifted up in
spirit for having, even in the privacy of our own household,
eaten our daily meal by the help of hand-wrought silver
utensils, from hand-painted china (often of dubious
artistic value) laid on high-priced table linen.
Any retrogression from the standard of living which
we are accustomed to regard as worthy in this respect
is felt to be a grievous violation of our human dignity.
So, also, for the last dozen years candles have been
a more pleasing source of light at dinner than any
other. Candlelight is now softer, less distressing
to well-bred eyes, than oil, gas, or electric light.
The same could not have been said thirty years ago,
when candles were, or recently had been, the cheapest
available light for domestic use. Nor are candles
even now found to give an acceptable or effective
light for any other than a ceremonial illumination.
A political sage still living has
summed up the conclusion of this whole matter in the
dictum: “A cheap coat makes a cheap man,”
and there is probably no one who does not feel the
convincing force of the maxim.
The habit of looking for the marks
of superfluous expensiveness in goods, and of requiring
that all goods should afford some utility of the indirect
or invidious sort, leads to a change in the standards
by which the utility of goods is gauged. The
honorific element and the element of brute efficiency
are not held apart in the consumer’s appreciation
of commodities, and the two together go to make up
the unanalyzed aggregate serviceability of the goods.
Under the resulting standard of serviceability, no
article will pass muster on the strength of material
sufficiency alone. In order to completeness and
full acceptability to the consumer it must also show
the honorific element. It results that the producers
of articles of consumption direct their efforts to
the production of goods that shall meet this demand
for the honorific element. They will do this
with all the more alacrity and effect, since they
are themselves under the dominance of the same standard
of worth in goods, and would be sincerely grieved
at the sight of goods which lack the proper honorific
finish. Hence it has come about that there are
today no goods supplied in any trade which do not contain
the honorific element in greater or less degree.
Any consumer who might, Diogenes-like, insist on the
elimination of all honorific or wasteful elements
from his consumption, would be unable to supply his
most trivial wants in the modern market. Indeed,
even if he resorted to supplying his wants directly
by his own efforts, he would find it difficult if
not impossible to divest himself of the current habits
of thought on this head; so that he could scarcely
compass a supply of the necessaries of life for a
day’s consumption without instinctively and
by oversight incorporating in his home-made product
something of this honorific, quasi-decorative element
of wasted labor.
It is notorious that in their selection
of serviceable goods in the retail market purchasers
are guided more by the finish and workmanship of the
goods than by any marks of substantial serviceability.
Goods, in order to sell, must have some appreciable
amount of labor spent in giving them the marks of
decent expensiveness, in addition to what goes to
give them efficiency for the material use which they
are to serve. This habit of making obvious costliness
a canon of serviceability of course acts to enhance
the aggregate cost of articles of consumption.
It puts us on our guard against cheapness by identifying
merit in some degree with cost. There is ordinarily
a consistent effort on the part of the consumer to
obtain goods of the required serviceability at as
advantageous a bargain as may be; but the conventional
requirement of obvious costliness, as a voucher and
a constituent of the serviceability of the goods,
leads him to reject as under grade such goods as do
not contain a large element of conspicuous waste.
It is to be added that a large share
of those features of consumable goods which figure
in popular apprehension as marks of serviceability,
and to which reference is here had as elements of conspicuous
waste, commend themselves to the consumer also on
other grounds than that of expensiveness alone.
They usually give evidence of skill and effective
workmanship, even if they do not contribute to the
substantial serviceability of the goods; and it is
no doubt largely on some such ground that any particular
mark of honorific serviceability first comes into
vogue and afterward maintains its footing as a normal
constituent element of the worth of an article.
A display of efficient workmanship is pleasing simply
as such, even where its remoter, for the time unconsidered,
outcome is futile. There is a gratification of
the artistic sense in the contemplation of skillful
work. But it is also to be added that no such
evidence of skillful workmanship, or of ingenious
and effective adaptation of means to an end, will,
in the long run, enjoy the approbation of the modern
civilized consumer unless it has the sanction of the
Canon of conspicuous waste.
The position here taken is enforced
in a felicitous manner by the place assigned in the
economy of consumption to machine products. The
point of material difference between machine-made
goods and the hand-wrought goods which serve the same
purposes is, ordinarily, that the former serve their
primary purpose more adequately. They are a more
perfect product show a more perfect adaptation
of means to end. This does not save them from
disesteem and deprecation, for they fall short under
the test of honorific waste. Hand labor is a more
wasteful method of production; hence the goods turned
out by this method are more serviceable for the purpose
of pecuniary reputability; hence the marks of hand
labor come to be honorific, and the goods which exhibit
these marks take rank as of higher grade than the
corresponding machine product. Commonly, if not
invariably, the honorific marks of hand labor are
certain imperfections and irregularities in the lines
of the hand-wrought article, showing where the workman
has fallen short in the execution of the design.
The ground of the superiority of hand-wrought goods,
therefore, is a certain margin of crudeness. This
margin must never be so wide as to show bungling workmanship,
since that would be evidence of low cost, nor so narrow
as to suggest the ideal precision attained only by
the machine, for that would be evidence of low cost.
The appreciation of those evidences
of honorific crudeness to which hand-wrought goods
owe their superior worth and charm in the eyes of
well-bred people is a matter of nice discrimination.
It requires training and the formation of right habits
of thought with respect to what may be called the
physiognomy of goods. Machine-made goods of daily
use are often admired and preferred precisely on account
of their excessive perfection by the vulgar and the
underbred who have not given due thought to the punctilios
of elegant consumption. The ceremonial inferiority
of machine products goes to show that the perfection
of skill and workmanship embodied in any costly innovations
in the finish of goods is not sufficient of itself
to secure them acceptance and permanent favor.
The innovation must have the support of the canon of
conspicuous waste. Any feature in the physiognomy
of goods, however pleasing in itself, and however
well it may approve itself to the taste for effective
work, will not be tolerated if it proves obnoxious
to this norm of pecuniary reputability.
The ceremonial inferiority or uncleanness
in consumable goods due to “commonness,”
or in other words to their slight cost of production,
has been taken very seriously by many persons.
The objection to machine products is often formulated
as an objection to the commonness of such goods.
What is common is within the (pecuniary) reach of many
people. Its consumption is therefore not honorific,
since it does not serve the purpose of a favorable
invidious comparison with other consumers. Hence
the consumption, or even the sight of such goods, is
inseparable from an odious suggestion of the lower
levels of human life, and one comes away from their
contemplation with a pervading sense of meanness that
is extremely distasteful and depressing to a person
of sensibility. In persons whose tastes assert
themselves imperiously, and who have not the gift,
habit, or incentive to discriminate between the grounds
of their various judgments of taste, the deliverances
of the sense of the honorific coalesce with those
of the sense of beauty and of the sense of serviceability in
the manner already spoken of; the resulting composite
valuation serves as a judgment of the object’s
beauty or its serviceability, according as the valuer’s
bias or interest inclines him to apprehend the object
in the one or the other of these aspects. It
follows not infrequently that the marks of cheapness
or commonness are accepted as definitive marks of
artistic unfitness, and a code or schedule of aesthetic
proprieties on the one hand, and of aesthetic abominations
on the other, is constructed on this basis for guidance
in questions of taste.
As has already been pointed out, the
cheap, and therefore indecorous, articles of daily
consumption in modern industrial communities are commonly
machine products; and the generic feature of the physiognomy
of machine-made goods as compared with the hand-wrought
article is their greater perfection in workmanship
and greater accuracy in the detail execution of the
design. Hence it comes about that the visible
imperfections of the hand-wrought goods, being honorific,
are accounted marks of superiority in point of beauty,
or serviceability, or both. Hence has arisen
that exaltation of the defective, of which John Ruskin
and William Morris were such eager spokesmen in their
time; and on this ground their propaganda of crudity
and wasted effort has been taken up and carried forward
since their time. And hence also the propaganda
for a return to handicraft and household industry.
So much of the work and speculations of this group
of men as fairly comes under the characterization
here given would have been impossible at a time when
the visibly more perfect goods were not the cheaper.
It is of course only as to the economic
value of this school of aesthetic teaching that anything
is intended to be said or can be said here. What
is said is not to be taken in the sense of depreciation,
but chiefly as a characterization of the tendency
of this teaching in its effect on consumption and
on the production of consumable goods.
The manner in which the bias of this
growth of taste has worked itself out in production
is perhaps most cogently exemplified in the book manufacture
with which Morris busied himself during the later years
of his life; but what holds true of the work of the
Kelmscott Press in an eminent degree, holds true with
but slightly abated force when applied to latter-day
artistic book-making generally as to type,
paper, illustration, binding materials, and binder’s
work. The claims to excellence put forward by
the later products of the bookmaker’s industry
rest in some measure on the degree of its approximation
to the crudities of the time when the work of book-making
was a doubtful struggle with refractory materials
carried on by means of insufficient appliances.
These products, since they require hand labor, are
more expensive; they are also less convenient for
use than the books turned out with a view to serviceability
alone; they therefore argue ability on the part of
the purchaser to consume freely, as well as ability
to waste time and effort. It is on this basis
that the printers of today are returning to “old-style,”
and other more or less obsolete styles of type which
are less legible and give a cruder appearance to the
page than the “modern.” Even a scientific
periodical, with ostensibly no purpose but the most
effective presentation of matter with which its science
is concerned, will concede so much to the demands
of this pecuniary beauty as to publish its scientific
discussions in oldstyle type, on laid paper, and with
uncut edges. But books which are not ostensibly
concerned with the effective presentation of their
contents alone, of course go farther in this direction.
Here we have a somewhat cruder type, printed on hand-laid,
deckel-edged paper, with excessive margins and uncut
leaves, with bindings of a painstaking crudeness and
elaborate ineptitude. The Kelmscott Press reduced
the matter to an absurdity as seen from
the point of view of brute serviceability alone by
issuing books for modern use, edited with the obsolete
spelling, printed in black-letter, and bound in limp
vellum fitted with thongs. As a further characteristic
feature which fixes the economic place of artistic
book-making, there is the fact that these more elegant
books are, at their best, printed in limited editions.
A limited edition is in effect a guarantee somewhat
crude, it is true that this book is scarce
and that it therefore is costly and lends pecuniary
distinction to its consumer.
The special attractiveness of these
book-products to the book-buyer of cultivated taste
lies, of course, not in a conscious, naïve recognition
of their costliness and superior clumsiness. Here,
as in the parallel case of the superiority of hand-wrought
articles over machine products, the conscious ground
of preference is an intrinsic excellence imputed to
the costlier and more awkward article. The superior
excellence imputed to the book which imitates the
products of antique and obsolete processes is conceived
to be chiefly a superior utility in the aesthetic
respect; but it is not unusual to find a well-bred
book-lover insisting that the clumsier product is
also more serviceable as a vehicle of printed speech.
So far as regards the superior aesthetic value of the
decadent book, the chances are that the book-lover’s
contention has some ground. The book is designed
with an eye single to its beauty, and the result is
commonly some measure of success on the part of the
designer. What is insisted on here, however,
is that the canon of taste under which the designer
works is a canon formed under the surveillance of
the law of conspicuous waste, and that this law acts
selectively to eliminate any canon of taste that does
not conform to its demands. That is to say, while
the decadent book may be beautiful, the limits within
which the designer may work are fixed by requirements
of a non-aesthetic kind. The product, if it is
beautiful, must also at the same time be costly and
ill adapted to its ostensible use. This mandatory
canon of taste in the case of the book-designer, however,
is not shaped entirely by the law of waste in its
first form; the canon is to some extent shaped in
conformity to that secondary expression of the predatory
temperament, veneration for the archaic or obsolete,
which in one of its special developments is called
classicism. In aesthetic theory it might be extremely
difficult, if not quite impracticable, to draw a line
between the canon of classicism, or regard for the
archaic, and the canon of beauty. For the aesthetic
purpose such a distinction need scarcely be drawn,
and indeed it need not exist. For a theory of
taste the expression of an accepted ideal of archaism,
on whatever basis it may have been accepted, is perhaps
best rated as an element of beauty; there need be
no question of its legitimation. But for the present
purpose for the purpose of determining what
economic grounds are present in the accepted canons
of taste and what is their significance for the distribution
and consumption of goods the distinction
is not similarly beside the point. The position
of machine products in the civilized scheme of consumption
serves to point out the nature of the relation which
subsists between the canon of conspicuous waste and
the code of proprieties in consumption. Neither
in matters of art and taste proper, nor as regards
the current sense of the serviceability of goods,
does this canon act as a principle of innovation or
initiative. It does not go into the future as
a creative principle which makes innovations and adds
new items of consumption and new elements of cost.
The principle in question is, in a certain sense,
a negative rather than a positive law. It is
a regulative rather than a creative principle.
It very rarely initiates or originates any usage or
custom directly. Its action is selective only.
Conspicuous wastefulness does not directly afford
ground for variation and growth, but conformity to
its requirements is a condition to the survival of
such innovations as may be made on other grounds.
In whatever way usages and customs and methods of
expenditure arise, they are all subject to the selective
action of this norm of reputability; and the degree
in which they conform to its requirements is a test
of their fitness to survive in the competition with
other similar usages and customs. Other thing
being equal, the more obviously wasteful usage or
method stands the better chance of survival under
this law. The law of conspicuous waste does not
account for the origin of variations, but only for
the persistence of such forms as are fit to survive
under its dominance. It acts to conserve the fit,
not to originate the acceptable. Its office is
to prove all things and to hold fast that which is
good for its purpose.