“Sibi unitus et simplificatus
esse,” that is the long struggle of the
Imitatio Christi. The spirit which
it forms is the very opposite of that which regards
life as a game of skill, and values things and persons
as marks or counters of something to be gained, or
achieved, beyond them. It seeks to value everything
at its eternal worth, not adding to it, or taking
from it, the amount of influence it may have for or
against its own special scheme of life. It is
the spirit that sees external circumstances as they
are, its own power and tendencies as they are, and
realises the given conditions of its life, not disquieted
by the desire for change, or the preference of one
part in life rather than another, or passion, or opinion.
The character we mean to indicate achieves this
perfect life by a happy gift of nature, without any
struggle at all. Not the saint only, the artist
also, and the speculative thinker, confused, jarred,
disintegrated in the world, as sometimes they inevitably
are, aspire for this simplicity to the last.
The struggle of this aspiration with a lower practical
aim in the mind of Savonarola has been subtly traced
by the author of Romola. As language, expression,
is the function of intellect, as art, the supreme
expression, is the highest product of intellect, so
this desire for simplicity is a kind of indirect self-assertion
of the intellectual part of such natures. Simplicity
in purpose and act is a kind of determinate expression
in dexterous outline of one’s personality.
It is a kind of moral expressiveness; there is an
intellectual triumph implied in it. Such a simplicity
is characteristic of the repose of perfect intellectual
culture. The artist and he who has treated life
in the spirit of art desires only to be shown to the
world as he really is; as he comes nearer and nearer
to perfection, the veil of an outer life not simply
expressive of the inward becomes thinner and thinner.
This intellectual throne is rarely won. Like
the religious life, it is a paradox in the world, denying
the first conditions of man’s ordinary existence,
cutting obliquely the spontaneous order of things.
But the character we have before us is a kind of
prophecy of this repose and simplicity, coming as it
were in the order of grace, not of nature, by
some happy gift, or accident of birth or constitution,
showing that it is indeed within the limits of man’s
destiny. Like all the higher forms of inward
life this character is a subtle blending and interpenetration
of intellectual, moral and spiritual elements.
But it is as a phase of intellect, of culture, that
it is most striking and forcible. It is a mind
of taste lighted up by some spiritual ray within.
What is meant by taste is an imperfect intellectual
state; it is but a sterile kind of culture. It
is the mental attitude, the intellectual manner of
perfect culture, assumed by a happy instinct.
Its beautiful way of handling everything that appeals
to the senses and the intellect is really directed
by the laws of the higher intellectual life, but while
culture is able to trace those laws, mere taste is
unaware of them. In the character before us,
taste, without ceasing to be instructive, is far more
than a mental attitude or manner. A magnificent
intellectual force is latent within it. It is
like the reminiscence of a forgotten culture that
once adorned the mind; as if the mind of one philosophesas
pote met’ erotos,+ fallen into a new cycle,
were beginning its spiritual progress over again,
but with a certain power of anticipating its stages.
It has the freshness without the shallowness of taste,
the range and seriousness of culture without its strain
and over-consciousness. Such a habit may be
described as wistfulness of mind, the feeling that
there is “so much to know,” rather
as a longing after what is unattainable, than as a
hope to apprehend. Its ethical result is an
intellectual guilelessness, or integrity, that instinctively
prefers what is direct and clear, lest one’s
own confusion and intransparency should hinder the
transmission from without of light that is not yet
inward. He who is ever looking for the breaking
of a light he knows not whence about him, notes with
a strange heedfulness the faintest paleness in the
sky. That truthfulness of temper, that receptivity,
which professors often strive in vain to form, is engendered
here less by wisdom than by innocence. Such
a character is like a relic from the classical age,
laid open by accident to our alien modern atmosphere.
It has something of the clear ring, the eternal outline
of the antique. Perhaps it is nearly always found
with a corresponding outward semblance. The
veil or mask of such a nature would be the very opposite
of the “dim blackguardism” of Danton, the
type Carlyle has made too popular for the true interest
of art. It is just this sort of entire transparency
of nature that lets through unconsciously all that
is really lifegiving in the established order of things;
it detects without difficulty all sorts of affinities
between its own elements, and the nobler elements
in that order. But then its wistfulness and a
confidence in perfection it has makes it love the lords
of change. What makes revolutionists is either
self-pity, or indignation for the sake of others,
or a sympathetic perception of the dominant undercurrent
of progress in things. The nature before us is
revolutionist from the direct sense of personal worth,
that chlide,+ that pride of life, which to the Greek
was a heavenly grace. How can he value what
comes of accident, or usage, or convention, whose
individual life nature itself has isolated and perfected?
Revolution is often impious. They who prosecute
revolution have to violate again and again the instinct
of reverence. That is inevitable, since after
all progress is a kind of violence. But in this
nature revolutionism is softened, harmonised, subdued
as by distance. It is the revolutionism of one
who has slept a hundred years. Most of us are
neutralised by the play of circumstances. To
most of us only one chance is given in the life of
the spirit and the intellect, and circumstances prevent
our dexterously seizing that one chance. The
one happy spot in our nature has no room to burst
into life. Our collective life, pressing equally
on every part of every one of us, reduces nearly all
of us to the level of a colourless uninteresting existence.
Others are neutralised, not by suppression of gifts,
but by just equipoise among them. In these no
single gift, or virtue, or idea, has an unmusical predominance.
The world easily confounds these two conditions.
It sees in the character before us only indifferentism.
Doubtless the chief vein of the life of humanity
could hardly pass through it. Not by it
could the progress of the world be achieved.
It is not the guise of Luther or Spinoza; rather
it is that of Raphael, who in the midst of the Reformation
and the Renaissance, himself lighted up by them, yielded
himself to neither, but stood still to live upon himself,
even in outward form a youth, almost an infant, yet
surprising all the world. The beauty of the Greek
statues was a sexless beauty; the statues of the gods
had the least traces of sex. Here there is a
moral sexlessness, a kind of impotence, an ineffectual
wholeness of nature, yet with a divine beauty and
significance of its own.
Over and over again the world has
been surprised by the heroism, the insight, the passion,
of this clear crystal nature. Poetry and poetical
history have dreamed of a crisis, where it must needs
be that some human victim be sent down into the grave.
These are they whom in its profound emotion humanity
might choose to send. “What,” says
Carlyle, of Charlotte Corday, “What if she had
emerged from her secluded stillness, suddenly like
a star; cruel-lovely, with half-angelic, half-daemonic
splendour; to gleam for a moment, and in a moment
be extinguished; to be held in memory, so bright complete
was she, through long centuries!”
Often the presence of this nature
is felt like a sweet aroma in early manhood.
Afterwards, as the adulterated atmosphere of the world
assimilates us to itself, the savour of it faints
away. Perhaps there are flushes of it in all
of us; recurring moments of it in every period of
life. Certainly this is so with every man of
genius. It is a thread of pure white light that
one might disentwine from the tumultuary richness
of Goethe’s nature. It is a natural prophecy
of what the next generation will appear, renerved,
modified by the ideas of this. There is a violence,
an impossibility about men who have ideas, which makes
one suspect that they could never be the type of any
widespread life. Society could not be conformed
to their image but by an unlovely straining from its
true order. Well, in this nature the idea appears
softened, harmonised as by distance, with an engaging
naturalness, without the noise of axe or hammer.
People have often tried to find a
type of life that might serve as a basement type.
The philosopher, the saint, the artist, neither of
them can be this type; the order of nature itself
makes them exceptional. It cannot be the pedant,
or the conservative, or anything rash and irreverent.
Also the type must be one discontented with society
as it is. The nature here indicated alone is
worthy to be this type. A majority of such would
be the regeneration of the world.
July, 1864.