To St. Augustine, Bishop of Hippo
in Africa, belongs the equivocal distinction of having
originated in the Christian Church a controversy respecting
the Divine decrees, a controversy which dates its
origin from the fifth century, and which, after the
lapse of thirteen hundred years, exhibits no symptoms
of approaching to its end. In the Roman Communion,
it was the source of those bitter animosities, which
reciprocally exasperated the Jesuits and Jansenists.
The Protestant Churches, in the early days of the
Reformation, were disturbed by the agitation of this
perplexed and perilous subject. And when Calvin
appeared as the vindicator of the Divine sovereignty
in predetermining the fates of men, he only introduced
to the Churches of the Reformation a doctrine which
had been transmitted from earlier times, but which,
perhaps, he defined with more precision, expounded
with more fearless consistency, and invested with
the authority of his own great and illustrious name.
In the present discussion the word Calvinism
is used, not to signify those doctrines of the Church
which Calvin held in common with the fathers of the
Reformation, but those only which relate to his extreme
views of the Divine decrees, to his predestinarian
theology, and to his modification of other scripture
truths to render them harmonious with his principal
tenets.
Whatever therefore may be the merits
or the final result of this grave and earnest controversy,
it leaves untouched the corruption of human nature,
the deity and atonement of Christ, justification by
faith, the necessity of Divine influence to renew and
purify the heart, and the scriptural doctrine of predestination,
according to the fore-knowledge of God. This
distinction is important; since, if it be overlooked,
the rejectors of Calvinism may be supposed to have
also rejected the capital doctrines of the Reformed
faith. Fuller has unwarrantably, perhaps undesignedly,
given his sanction to this imputation in his “Calvinistic
and Socinian Systems compared.” But
the rejectors of Calvinistic predestination
may be not less remote from Socinianism, and much
nearer to genuine Christianity, than the most rigid
disciple of that eminent Reformer, who, in the protestant
city of Geneva, committed Servetus to the flames.
The Socinian controversy relates to doctrines, which
are the common faith of the Catholic Church; with
the peculiarities of Calvinism it has no concern.
And it is worthy of remark, that if one class of doctrinalists
more than another symbolizes in any instance with
Socinians, the followers of Calvin form that class;
since it is not easy to discover where lies the essential
difference between the doctrine of philosophical
necessity, as held by the greater number of Socinians,
and that of predestination, as maintained by
Calvinists.
Both parties rest their dogmas on
the same metaphysical grounds. At the same time,
as moral reasoners, the palm of superiority must be
awarded to Socinians, who reject most consistently
the doctrine of human corruption, and the atonement
of Christ, together with the correspondent doctrines
of the Gospel, as altogether out of place in a scheme
which denies the freedom of human actions and reduces
all independent agency to that of the Deity alone;
while the Calvinist subjects the human race to an
inevitable necessity of sinning, denies to them individually,
even the semblance of a probationary course makes
them accountable, yet withholds the powers necessary
to a moral agent, and then most unrighteously dooms
to perdition all but the elect! In rejecting
such a theory of religion, we reject not the fundamental
doctrines of Christianity; we only vindicate them
from objections, which, if unanswerable, are fatal;
and we hold to the Gospel with a firmer conviction
and a livelier faith, when we behold its accordance
with the righteousness of the Divine administration
and with the moral constitution of man.
On a subject, which has been so long
and so laboriously investigated, and to the illustration
of which the most vigorous and profound of human intellects
have directed their energies, it would be vain to
expect any novelty of argument. On either side,
it may be presumed, the question has been exhausted,
or, that the human mind has done all that its powers
can accomplish, however unsatisfactory or inconclusive,
in some respects, the result.
It appears to the writer of these
pages, on a calm and summary review of the arguments
by which the doctrines of freedom and necessity
have been respectively supported, that those reasonings
which are purely philosophical or metaphysical
decidedly preponderate on the side of Necessity.
The prescience of the Deity cannot, on any known
principle, be reconciled with the contingency
which attaches to the actions or determinations of
man, on the hypothesis of freedom. And, moreover,
if every event requires a cause, and every volition
is guided by motives, what are called the spontaneous
acts of the mind must be the necessary result of motives
which direct and command its elections. “To
say that in our choice we reject the stronger motive,
and that we choose a thing merely because we choose
it, is sheer nonsense and absurdity. And whoever,
with a sound understanding, will fix his mind upon
the state of the question, will perceive its impossibility.”
But, all correct moral reasoning
ranges on the side of freedom. In opposition
to the subtle or forcible reasonings of the metaphysician,
every individual can plead his inward consciousness
of voluntary agency. He feels, he knows, that
he is free. The exercise of the moral sense,
the judgment which the mind pronounces on its own good
or evil movements, the conviction of having done or
neglected a duty, the calm satisfaction of the virtuous
mind, and the fierce or sullen remorse of the criminal,
are associated with the insuppressible persuasion
of liberty. Destroy this persuasion, and virtue
is despoiled of its loveliness, vice of its deformity.
But it cannot be destroyed. It is the voice of
nature. The Creator has so formed us, that we
cannot throw off from ourselves the sense of responsibility,
nor regard our fellow creatures as unfit for praise
or blame, for love or hatred. Men treat each other
as free agents in all the transactions of human life,
and God administers the government of the world, on
the principle that mankind are capable of self-control,
regulating their conduct by the hope of reward or
fear of punishment. If the consciousness of freedom
be a delusion, it follows that moral obligation, duty,
reward, guilt, punishment, are delusions, and that
religion, however salutary in its effects, is nothing
better than a magnificent imposture.
Calvinism is an attempt to found the
religion of Christ on the doctrine of necessity, and
to accommodate its truths, which suppose and require
free agency in man, to a dark and appalling fatalism.
But in a case like the present, in which metaphysical
reasonings, however profound or conclusive, so far
as they go, are at variance with practical truth,
with consciousness, with the actual state of things,
and with the unquestionable procedures of the Divine
government, as confirmed by the scriptures, wisdom
would seem to dictate our adhesion to that side of
the question, which is supported by moral arguments.
In taking this part, it does not follow
that we are to repudiate, as totally without foundation,
the philosophy and the metaphysics of the necessarian aequo
pretio aestimentur. We may admit, that the
force of his argument, in the present imperfect state
of human knowledge, renders the question perplexed
and difficult; that it accounts for the divided opinions
of the erudite and the devout, and that it precludes
the hope of a speedy termination of the controversy.
But in assigning to moral reasoning the superior authority,
we are governed by a just regard to the nature of the
question at issue, which, being related to the destinies
of moral agents, and the principles on which the Deity
conducts his moral government, must be determined,
not by metaphysical, but by moral arguments.
When brought to this test, Calvinism appears utterly
indefensible, as being a system at variance with the
attributes of the Deity, and irreconcileable with
the moral constitution of human beings, and with the
obligations laid upon them by their Creator. It
is falsified by facts.
That the predestinarian theology,
which denies the freedom of the will, is supported
by names of great consideration, is cheerfully granted.
No man, for example, was ever endowed with a genius
more commanding, with logical powers more acute, with
a faculty more surprising of writing on recondite
subjects with force, perspicuity, and nervous eloquence,
than President Edwards. Nevertheless, the correctness
of his views is not implicitly to be inferred from
his transcendant intellect and fervent piety.
All the great errors, which have been
propagated in the Christian Church, have found advocates
in men of the first character for intellectual power
and moral dignity, or they would have passed away
with their authors into immediate oblivion.
In estimating the authority of Edwards
as a theologian, it is requisite that we should know
the temperament and habits of that very remarkable
person. It is not, perhaps, generally considered,
that great as were the energy and acuteness of his
reasoning powers, he was less under the dominion of
these than of his imagination and feelings. In
early life this is not unfrequently the case with
persons of imaginative character; but, commonly, the
ardent enthusiasm of youth gives way afterwards to
the ascendancy of the higher faculties. Edwards
was, constitutionally, too much the creature of dreams
and impulses ever to escape from their control.
His gigantic mind was held in perpetual bondage.
His natural temperament was fostered throughout the
whole period which moulds and fixes the character,
by his holding little converse with human beings beyond
the sphere of a particular religious community in an
obscure American town, and by an almost uninterrupted
contemplation of nature in her gloomy and awful forms,
amid the silence of uncultivated plains, and the solitude
of interminable forests. The profound feeling,
the intense excitement, which accompanied his early
devotional exercises, were such as to insure a permanent
attachment to every principle and every impression
of that susceptible age. The visions of a warm,
and often morbid, imagination continued to be cherished
with religious confidence and love for ever afterwards.
Every doubt, of what he once had received for truth,
was anxiously suppressed in the manhood of his mind
as an infernal suggestion; and the acuteness of his
reasoning powers, by supplying him at all times with
an argument, for what he conceived it his duty
to believe, served, not to emancipate him from false
apprehensions of truth, but to rivet upon him more
firmly the chains of ignorance or error. When
argument was doubtful, a dogged fanaticism supplied
its place. This may be illustrated by a particular
instance, and bearing directly on the subject of our
present discussion.
It cannot be doubted, by any person
qualified to appreciate his writings, that his views
of the Divine sovereignty are resolvable into a system
of absolute fatalism, so far as the actions and destinies
of men are concerned. Reason and conscience revolt
from the consequences involved in such a system; all
our moral instincts condemn it. But it was instilled
into his mind by Calvinistic instructors in the days
of his boyhood; his imagination was perpetually haunted
by it; and having identified it with the truth of
divine revelation, which he held in religious veneration
and awe, he finally vanquished every doubt respecting
it, not by the deliberate exercise of his judgment,
on a calm investigation of evidence, but by the force
of his religious feelings, and of his ascendant imagination.
Let him tell his own story.
“From my childhood up,”
he says, “my mind had been full of objections
against the doctrine of God’s sovereignty, in
choosing whom He would to eternal life, and rejecting
whom He pleased; leaving them eternally to perish,
and to be everlastingly tormented in hell. It
used to appear like a horrible doctrine to me.
But I remember the time very well, when I seemed to
be convinced and fully satisfied as to this sovereignty
of God, and his justice in thus eternally disposing
of men, according to his sovereign pleasure. But
never could give any account, how, or by what means
I was thus convinced, not in the least imagining
at the time, nor a long time after, that there was
any extraordinary influence of God’s Spirit in
it; but only that now I saw further, and my reason
apprehended the justice and reasonableness of it.”
In this extraordinary passage, the most instructive
he ever penned, he confesses, undesignedly but clearly,
that his faith in the Calvinistic theology did not
rest on those arguments by which he has confirmed
so many others in that tremendous creed, but was the
result of supposed supernatural illumination.
The true solution would be, “Sit pro ratione
voluntas!”
Much as we find to admire and revere
in this eminent man, the history of his mind forbids
us to rely on him with implicit confidence as an expositor
of divine truth. His religion was exalted, his
genius wonderful, but the subordination of his judgment
to his imagination was an immense evil, producing an
almost superstitious dread of the operations of his
own mighty mind, suppressing its energies, its growth,
and its expansion. He presents an example, not
less of the weakness than of the majesty of human
nature. We cease to wonder, when he describes
the happiness of the spirits of the redeemed in heaven,
as being derived, in part, from their listening to
the groans and lamentations of lost souls in hell.
Nor can we doubt, that if he had been born and educated
a member of the Church of Rome, he would have lived
and died, like Fenelon or Pascal, a splendid ornament
of that impure communion, a conscientious advocate
of that servile faith.
Calvinism has never had another advocate
equally qualified with Edwards to vindicate its awful
dogmata; and if, by his own confession, his most potent
arguments would have failed to produce conviction
in his own mind, without God’s special influence,
we see reason to suspect the validity of these arguments,
until we have proof that he did indeed receive from
heaven miraculous illumination. Such special
influence we may with propriety question, since
a claim to inspiration can be supported only by the
exercise of miraculous powers. Deny, therefore,
the inspiration of this profound writer, of which
there is no proof, and we have his own authority against
the conclusiveness of his own arguments; since he
confesses that by their cogency alone they are insufficient
to produce conviction in opposition to our just and
natural conceptions of the righteous character of
God.
Let us not, therefore, crouch with
timid servility to great names. The opinions
of men of erudition, and genius, and holy zeal for
religion, are to be examined with modest deference,
but not to be received with implicit credulity.
In the most enlightened and holy men, who, since the
decease of the apostles, have served God and his Christ;
in the fathers of the ancient Church; in those who
headed the Protestant Reformation, and lived as saints,
or died as martyrs; in Luther, Calvin, Cranmer, Knox,
we discover humiliating proofs of imperfection and
fallibility. And, while the fundamental truths
of Christianity have been preserved in the Catholic
Church, those truths have been mingled or associated
with errors so injurious and degrading, that no blind
faith is to be rested on any human authority.
Let us uphold the majesty of divine revelation, and
vindicate our right and our duty to interpret the sacred
page not by the traditions of fallible
men, not by the metaphysics of the schools, not by
the “special influences” which an enthusiastic
mind may construe into divine teaching, and which
may be pleaded, with equal truth or falsehood, for
every form of error; but by a sober reference to those
moral perfections of the Deity, and to those essential
attributes of human nature, the knowledge of which
lies at the foundation of all sound religious belief.
These are to be learned from the Scriptures, and are
the key to their right interpretation.
Edwards, incomparably the most able
advocate of Calvinism, since the days of the reformer
himself, is not a solitary example of the way in which
a zealous pleader may, unwarily, betray and weaken
his own cause.
Mr. Scott, in his “force of
truth,” gives an account of his own conversion
to Calvinism not very dissimilar to that of Edwards,
and not in any degree more honourable to the cause
he proposes to defend. The argument of that work
may be summed up in few words. Mr. Scott entertained
a great dislike of Calvinistic doctrines. He
rejected the evidence by which they were supported,
as being insufficient to establish a creed which appeared
to him most objectionable. Yet, strong as were
his prejudices against it, they ultimately gave way,
and, therefore, Calvinism must be the truth.
But, in both instances, the impression designed to
be made on the mind of the reader is the same, that
is, that the Spirit of God accomplished what the force
of argument had failed to do. Mr. Scott, therefore,
adds his testimony to that of President Edwards, confessing
that Calvinism is not supported by proofs sufficient
in themselves to carry conviction to the human mind,
without special illumination from above; an illumination,
which, assuredly, the religious opposers may
as righteously claim, as the religious defenders of
Calvinism. For what Christian man does not pray
for the guidance of God’s good Spirit?
The dispassionate reader of “The Force of
Truth,” will naturally say, that the arguments
for the Calvinistic creed were either sound or unsound.
If the former, then Mr. Scott was either very obtuse
or very obstinate to resist so long their power.
If the latter, he acted with great weakness in yielding
at length to insufficient evidence, on the score of
an undefinable impulse. In either case, his name
is divested of commanding authority in the view of
reasonable men. Yet it can hardly be doubted,
that this claim to special teaching from the
fountain of wisdom and of truth, has done more, incalculably
more, to awe the minds of men into submission, and
thus to obtain currency for their opinions, than the
joint confession of these popular writers, to
the insufficiency of their own arguments, has availed
to render suspected the force of their reasoning.
The impression made on the generality of minds would
be, that men so good, and so candid in confessing
their own obstinacy, could not be mistaken, in believing
themselves, at a subsequent period, to be inspired
and infallible.
The advocates of Calvinism differ
remarkably from each other in the tone and spirit
of their writings, as their habits of thought and
feeling are modified by circumstances. The American
divines of the school of Edwards have carried out
his principles with unflinching consistency, not hesitating
to impute to the Deity, in unqualified terms, the
eternal decrees which fix the weal or woe of the human
race for ever. The cold and heartless manner in
which these men treat the subject, and the stoical
apathy with which they contemplate the result of their
hard metaphysics, are extremely remote from our usual
conceptions of piety and humanity. Well might
that superlative woman, Mrs. Susanna Wesley, say, “The
doctrine of predestination, as maintained by
rigid Calvinists, is very shocking, and ought utterly
to be abhorred.” The dark spirit of inflexible
wrath which the American Calvinists have imputed to
the Deity, together with their coarse caricatures
of the Gospel, may account for, but cannot justify,
the terms in which Dr. Chancing has thought fit to
assail the orthodox faith, confounding on all
occasions scriptural Christianity, as held by the Catholic
Church, with the dogmas of an extravagant creed.
To understand his eloquent and indignant declamations,
we must read the transatlantic expounders of the Calvinistic
theology.
In general, the English writers of
any name, are more guarded and less unfeeling.
They do not at once and directly charge God with being
the author of sin. The late Dr. Williams of Rotherham
composed a voluminous work on the subject, entitled
“equity and sovereignty,” in which he
gives, what he considers, a new theory of the origin
of moral evil. To redeem the divine character
from the imputation of harshness in the decree of
reprobation, he supposes mankind under a necessary
tendency to moral defection, as dependent and created
beings; and that it was in mere equity, that
the wicked were left, not decreed, to perdition.
The hypothesis of Dr. Williams is already exploded.
It was examined and refuted by the Rev. William Parry,
of Wymondly, in a piece entitled “Strictures
on the Origin of Moral Evil.” For reasoning,
acute, profound, and perspicuous, both metaphysical
and moral, this work has seldom been surpassed.
And the devout and courteous spirit in which it is
written, presents an example, beautiful and instructive,
of dispassionate controversy.
“Upon a review of the argument,”
Mr. Parry writes, “there appear to be strong
reasons for considering the whole of Dr. Williams’
hypothesis, to account for the origin of evil, as highly
objectionable, and worthy of rejection; because it
is founded on a false principle, which identifies
physical and moral tendency; is incompatible with
the nature and phenomena of mind; involves the existence
of an antecedent fate or absolute necessity, which
controlled the divine operations; is inconsistent with
the natural and moral perfections of God, and the
scriptural account of the state in which man was created;
is expressed in obscure and inapplicable language;
and is so far from agreeing with equity, that,
when taken together, it represents the Divine Being
as having at first, created intelligent and accountable
creatures with such powers as would enable them to
sin, but with none which would enable them to avoid
it.”
The theory of Dr. Williams found favour
with many Calvinists, because it assumed somewhat
of a philosophical aspect, and was put forth as a
clear “demonstration.” But
some of its ablest defenders have since abandoned
it to that oblivion, from which no efforts can save
an elaborate speculation, ungrounded in reason or revelation,
and repugnant to common sense.
In England the public mind has been
so powerfully and happily influenced by the anti-calvinistic
genius of the liturgy, offices, and discipline of
the Anglican Church, that the grossness and extravagancy
of the American divines have been tolerated chiefly
by those who have not fallen under her instructions,
or who have not had the advantage of a liberal education
and extensive reading. In general, whether within
or without the pale of the Church, its more intelligent
advocates have, until lately, exhibited it in a modified
form, and thrown over it a veil of mystery which has
hidden its most appalling deformities from the sight,
while by the less skilful or sagacious only, it has
been adapted more to the fears or affections of women,
than to the understandings of men. Unhappily,
the grosser representations of this doctrine are now
coming into repute in quarters where, formerly, they
would not have been endured, and thus afford another
warning example of the “facilis descensus
Averni.”
But under all possible modifications,
it is essentially erroneous; and this small treatise
has originated in no love of discord, or taste for
polemic excitement, but in a solemn sense of duty, the
duty of aiding, in some humble measure, the more learned
and important labours of others who are “set
for the defence of the truth.” The writer
aims only at a common sense view of the subject,
showing that Calvinism is a dangerous speculation,
useless for every holy and salutary purpose, inapplicable
to the hopes and the duties of a religious life, at
variance with our knowledge of God, our obligations
as Christians, and all our finer sentiments and more
generous sympathies as men. So far as its influence
is exerted, it contracts the understanding and hardens
the heart.
Bishop Tomline’s “Refutation
of Calvinism,” is too well known and justly
appreciated to need recommendation from the writer
of these papers. Faber “on the Primitive
Doctrine of Election,” is an important work,
composed with logical precision, and founded on a
laborious analysis of the Scriptures. The intelligent
reader will be instructed and deeply interested by
“An Inquiry into the Doctrines of Necessity
and Predestination,” by Dr. Copleston, the Bishop
of Llandaff.
From the latter work is extracted
the following summary of the peculiar and distinctive
doctrines of the Calvinistic creed, in which it is
exhibited, not in a moderated and qualified form, as
it sometimes appears in the writings of individuals,
but in its true and undisguised character, as maintained
by a grave assembly of predestinarian divines.