‘A force d’esprit tout
lui paroit matière.’
In one of his interesting ‘Lay
Sermons,’ the most interesting perhaps of the
whole interesting series, Professor Huxley, taking
for his theme the ‘Physical Basis of Life,’
combats ’the widely-spread conception of life
as a something which works through matter, but is independent
of it;’ affirming, on the contrary, ’that
matter and life are inseparably connected, and that
there is one kind of matter which is common to all
living beings.’ The preacher may be safely
allowed to have satisfactorily made out the second
portion of this affirmation. With his own singular
felicity of illustration, he shows how all vegetable
and animal tissues, without exception, from that of
the brightly coloured lichen looking so like a mere
mineral incrustation on the rock that bears it, to
that of the painter who admires or the botanist who
dissects it, are, however diverse in aspect, essentially
one in composition and structure. He explains
how the microscopic fungi clustering by millions within
the body of a single fly, the giant pine of California
towering to the height of a cathedral spire, the Indian
fig-tree covering acres with its profound shadow, the
animalcules of ocean’s lowest deep, minute
enough to dance in myriads on the point of a needle,
and the Finner whale, hugest of beasts, that disports
its ninety feet of bone and blubber on ocean’s
billowy heights, the flower that a girl wears in her
hair, and the blood that courses through her veins,
are, each and all, smaller or larger multiples or aggregates
of one and the same structural unit, which, again,
is invariably resolvable into the same identical elements.
That unit, he tells us, is an atom or corpuscle composed
of oxygen, nitrogen, hydrogen, and carbon, which, and
which alone, seem to be required by nature for laying
withal the foundations of vitality, inasmuch as no
substance from which any one of these ingredients
is totally absent, ever exhibits any sign of life,
while, on the other hand, not only are these four ingredients
sufficient of themselves to form a substance capable
of living, but they actually do with very little (when
any) foreign admixture, form all substances whatsoever
that are ever found vivified. All such substances,
he informs us, are but varieties of protoplasm,
differing indeed from each other in texture, colour,
and general appearance, even as a diamond differs
from granite, yet all being equally protoplasm, just
as a diamond and a block of granite are equally stones,
or as heart of oak and the outer case of a nettle’s
sting are equally wood. The human ovum, he gives
us to understand, is in its earliest stage but a single
particle of protoplasm; the human foetus but an aggregation
of such particles, variously modified; the human body
perfectly matured, but a larger aggregation of such
particles still further modified.
He proceeds to point out, as following
from these premises, that a solution of smelling salts,
together with an infinitesimal quantity of certain
other salts, contains all the elements that enter into
the composition of protoplasm, and consequently of
whatever substance the very highest animal requires
for sustenance. He does not, however, leave us
to suppose that any abundance of the fluid in question
would avail aught to save a hungry creature of any
sort from starving, but continues his exposition to
the following effect. Not only is there no animal,
there is not even any vegetable organism, to which
the elements of food can serve as food, as long as
they remain elementary. It is indispensable that
hydrogen and oxygen should combine to form water,
nitrogen and hydrogen to form ammonia, carbon and oxygen
to form carbonic acid; and even then, even at a table
groaning under whole hogsheads of these primitive
compounds, there is no single animal that would not
find itself at a Barmecide feast. There are many
plants likewise, which in the midst of such uncongenial
plenty would be equally without a drop to drink; but
there are also multitudes of others which, without
the aid of any more elaborated nutriment, would be
able to grow into a million, nay million million fold
of their original bulk. Provided there be in
the seed or germ of any of these latter one single
particle of living protoplasm to begin with, that single
particle may convert into animated protoplasm an indefinite
quantity of inanimate ammonia, carbonic acid, and
water. The protoplasm thus created in the first
instance, and created, let us suppose, in the form
of a lichen or a fungus, is converted by decay into
vegetable mould, in which grass may take root and
grow, and which, in that case, will be converted into
herbaceous protoplasm; which, being eaten by sheep
or oxen, becomes ovine or bovine protoplasm, commonly
called mutton or beef; which, again, being eaten by
man, becomes human protoplasm, and, if eaten by a
philosopher, becomes part of a mass of protoplasm capable
of investigating and of expounding in lectures or
lay sermons, the changes which itself and its several
components have undergone.
So far we advance with willing steps
like dutiful disciples along the path of knowledge
indicated by our distinguished biological teacher,
who here, however, pulls us up short by suddenly intimating
that he sees no break in the series of transubstantiations
whereby precisely such oxygen, hydrogen, nitrogen,
and carbon as he is lecturing upon, have become metamorphosed
into him, the lecturer, and us, the lectured audience,
and cannot ’understand why the language which
is applicable to any one term of the series should
not be used in regard to any of the others.’
Oxygen and hydrogen, he reminds us, are gases, whose
particles, at and also much below 32 deg.
Fahrenheit, tend to rush away from each other with
great force; and this tendency we call a property of
each gas. Let oxygen and hydrogen be mixed in
certain proportions, and an electric spark passed
through them, and they will disappear, and a quantity
of water equal in weight to the sum of their weights
will appear in their place. But amongst the properties
of the water will be some, the direct opposites of
those of its components; watery particles, for example,
at any temperature not higher than 32 deg.
Fahrenheit, tending not to rush asunder, but to cohere
into definite geometrical shapes or to build up frosty
imitations of vegetable foliage. And let the water
be brought into conjunction with ammonia and carbonic
acid, and the three will, under certain conditions,
give rise to protoplasm, which again, if subjected
to a certain succession of processes, will rise by
successive stages from protoplasm that gives no other
signs of life than those of feeding and reproducing
its kind, to protoplasm endowed with the power of
spontaneous motion, and finally to protoplasm that
thinks and reasons, speculates and philosophises.
Now why should any of the various phenomena of life
exhibited by these varieties of protoplasm be supposed
to be of a different class from the appearances of
activity exhibited by any of the varieties of lifeless
matter? What reason is there why, for instance,
thought should not be termed a property of thinking
protoplasm, just as congelation is a property of water,
and centrifugience of gas? Professor Huxley protests
that he is aware of no reason. We call, he says,
the several strange phenomena which are peculiar to
water, ’the properties of water, and do not hesitate
to believe that in some way or other they result from
the properties of the component elements of water.
We do not assume that something called aquosity
entered into and took possession of the oxide of hydrogen
as soon as it was formed, and then guided the aqueous
particles to their places in the facets of the crystal
or among the leaflets of the hoar frost. On the
contrary, we live in the hope and faith that, by the
advance of molecular physics, we shall by-and-by be
able to see our way as clearly from the constituents
of water to the properties of water, as we are now
able to deduce the operations of a watch from the form
of its parts or the manner in which they are put together.’
Why, then, when carbonic acid, water, and ammonia
disappear, and an equivalent weight of the matter
of life makes its appearance in their place, should
we assume the existence in the living matter of a
something which has no representative or correlative
in the unliving matter that gave rise to it?
Why imagine that into the newly formed hydro-nitrogenised
oxide of carbon a something called vitality entered
and took possession? ’What better philosophical
status has vitality than aquosity?’ ’If
scientific language is to possess a definite and constant
signification, we are,’ he considers, ’logically
bound to apply to protoplasm or the physical basis
of life the same conceptions as those which are held
to be legitimate elsewhere.’ Wherefore,
he concludes, that ’if the phenomena exhibited
by water are its properties, so are those presented
by protoplasm its properties,’ and that
if it be correct to describe ’the properties
of water as resulting from the nature and disposition
of its component molecules,’ there can be no
’intelligible ground for refusing to say that
the properties of protoplasm result from the nature
and disposition of its molecules.’
Here, however, our lay preacher candidly
warns us that by the vast majority of his clerical
brethren this doctrine would be denounced as rankest
heresy, and that whoever accepts it is placing his
foot on the first rung of a ladder which, in most
people’s estimation, is the ‘reverse of
Jacob’s, and leads to the antipodes of heaven.’
He frankly owns that the terms of his propositions
are distinctly materialistic: nay, that whoever
commits himself to them will be temporarily landed
in ‘gross materialism.’ Not the less,
however, does he, mingling consolation with admonition,
recommend us to plunge boldly into the materialistic
slough, promising to point out a way of escape from
it, and insisting, indeed, that through it lies the
only path to genuine spiritualistic truth.
In pronouncing this to be exceedingly
evil counsel, as with the most unfeigned respect for
its author I feel bound at once to do, it might not
be necessary for me to undertake a detailed topographical
survey of the path alluded to. It might, perhaps,
suffice to specify the conclusions to which the path
is represented as leading, in order to show that those
conclusions cannot possibly be reached by any such
route. By Professor Huxley himself they are thus
described: We know nothing of matter ’except
as a name for the unknown and hypothetical cause of
states of our own consciousness,’ nor of spirit,
except that ’it also is a name for an unknown
and hypothetical cause of states of consciousness.
In other words matter and spirit are but names for
the imaginary substrata of groups of natural
phenomena.’
But if matter be not a thing, but
a name, and a name too not for a real, but only an
imaginary thing, one perfect certainty is that matter
cannot possibly be composed either wholly or in part
of molecules, and, by necessary consequence, that
life cannot possibly be ’the product of any
disposition of material molecules,’ nor the phenomena
of life be ‘expressions of molecular changes
in the matter of life.’ Of the particular
Huxleian doctrine which we are considering, the two
moieties are absolutely irreconcileable; so that on
the assumption that either moiety were true, the truth
of that moiety would be decisive against the other.
If matter have no real, and only a nominal existence,
life, which is undeniably a reality, cannot be a property
of matter. If life, being an undisputed reality,
be a property of matter, matter must needs be a reality
also, and not merely a name. Any one, however,
who, like myself, is thoroughly convinced that both
halves of the doctrine are equally and utterly erroneous,
is precluded from employing one for the refutation
of the other, and in order to prove, as I shall now
attempt to do, that life is in no sense either a product
or a property of matter, must resort for the purpose
to independent reasoning.
I commence by defining one of the
principal terms occurring in the debate. When
in scientific discourse we speak of anything as a property
of an object, we mean thereby not simply that it is
a thing belonging to the object, but also that it
is a thing without which the object could not subsist.
We mean that it is one of the constituents inherent
in and inseparable from the object, whose union gives
to the object its distinctive character. When
we call fluidity at one temperature, solidity at another,
and vaporisation at a third, properties of water,
we mean that matter which did not liquefy, congeal,
and evaporate at different temperatures would not
be water. The habits of exhibiting these phenomena,
in conjunction with certain other habits, make up the
aquosity or wateriness of water. They are parts
of water’s nature, and, in the absence of any
one of them, water would not be its own self, and
could not exist. But in no such sense, nor in
any sense whatever, is the life or vitality whereby
what we are accustomed to call animated are distinguished
from inanimate objects, essential to the existence
of the species of matter termed matter of life or
protoplasm. Take from water its aquosity, and
water ceases to be water; but you may take away vitality
from protoplasm, and yet leave protoplasm as much protoplasm
as before. Vitality, therefore, evidently bears
to protoplasm a quite different relation from that
which aquosity bears to water. Protoplasm can
do perfectly well without the one, but water cannot
for a moment dispense with the other. Protoplasm,
whether living or lifeless, is equally itself; but
unaqueous water is unmitigated gibberish. But
if protoplasm, although deprived of its vitality,
still remains protoplasm, vitality plainly is not
indispensable to protoplasm, is not therefore a property
of protoplasm.
And that it is not a product
of protoplasm, or a result of any particular arrangement
of protoplasmic particles or molecules, is not less
easily or unanswerably demonstrable. For if it
were, as long as the particular molecular arrangement
remained unaltered, life would necessarily be in attendance;
an amputated joint would, until decomposition set
in, be as much alive as the trunk from which it had
been lopped, even as water poured from a jug into a
glass is quite as much liquid as the water remaining
in the jug. There would be no such thing as dead
meat, which was not putrid as well as dead, any more
than water can freeze without changing from a fluid
to a solid; and there would moreover be production
antecedent in origin to its own producer. The
force of the last at least of these objections is not
to be resisted. Water, ammonia, and carbonic
acid cannot, it is admitted, combine to form protoplasm,
unless a principle of life preside over the operation.
Unless under those auspices the combination never takes
place. At present, whenever assuming its presidential
functions, the principle of life seems to be invariably
embodied in a portion of pre-existing protoplasm;
but there certainly was a time when the fact was otherwise.
Time was, as geology places beyond all doubt, when
our globe and its appurtenances consisted wholly of
inorganic matter, and possessed not one single animal
or vegetable inhabitant. In order, then, that
any protoplasm or the substance of any organism should
have been brought into existence in the first instance,
life plainly must have been already existent.
It must at one time have been possible for life, without
being previously embodied, to mould and vivify inert
matter; and it must needs have been by unembodied
life that inorganic matter was first organised and
animated. There is no possible alternative to
this conclusion, except that of supposing that death
may have given birth to life that absolutely
lifeless and inert matter may have spontaneously exerted
itself with all the marvellous energy requisite for
its conversion into living matter, exerting for the
purpose powers which, under the conditions of the
case, it could not have acquired without exercising
before it acquired them. Whoever declines to swallow
such absurdity has no choice but to admit that unembodied
life must have been the original manufacturer of protoplasm:
but to admit this, and yet to suppose that when now-a-days
embodied life is observed to give birth to new embodied
life, the credit of the operation belongs not to the
life itself but to its protoplasmic embodiment, is
much the same as to suppose that when a tailor, dressed
in clothes of his own making, makes a second suit
of clothes, this latter is the product not of the tailor
himself but of the clothes he is wearing.
Thus, irrespectively of whatever grounds
there may be for believing that life still does,
it is incontestable that life once did, exist
apart from protoplasm; and that protoplasm both may
and continually does exist apart from what is commonly
understood by life, must be obvious to every one who
is aware that protoplasm is the substance of which
all plants and all animals are composed, and has observed
also that plants and animals are in the habit of dying.
That matter and life are inseparably connected cannot,
therefore, it would seem, be asserted except in total
disregard of the teachings both of reason and observation,
and ’the popular conception of life as a something
which works through matter but is independent of it,’
would seem to be as true as it is popular. If
the only choice allowed to us be between ’the
old notion of an Archaeus governing and directing
blind matter,’ and the new conception of life
as the product of a certain disposition of material
molecules, the absolute certainty that the latter
conception is wrong, may be fairly urged as equivalent
to certainty, equally absolute, that the former notion
is right.
How far soever it may be true that,
as Professor Huxley says, ’the progress of physical
science means, and has in all ages meant, the extension
of the province of matter and causation,’ it
is certainly not true that, as he proceeds to predict,
the same province will ever be extended sufficiently
to banish from the region of human thought not ‘spontaneity’
simply, but likewise ‘spirit.’ In
one direction at least, limits are clearly discernible
which scientific investigation need not hope to overleap.
How much soever we may eventually discover of the
changes whereby inorganic matter becomes gradually
adapted for the reception of life, physical science
can never teach us what or whence is the life that
eventually takes possession of the finished receptacle.
Possibly we at length may, as Professor Huxley doubts
not that we by-and-by shall, see how it is that the
properties peculiar to water have resulted from the
properties peculiar to the gases whose junction constitutes
water; and similarly how the characteristic properties
of protoplasm have sprung from properties in the water,
ammonia, and carbonic acid that have united to form
protoplasm; but knowing all this, we shall not be
a hair’s breadth nearer to the more recondite
knowledge up to which it is expected to lead.
To extract the genesis of life from any data that
completest acquaintance with the stages and processes
of protoplasmic growth can furnish, is a truly hopeless
problem. Given the plan of a house, with samples
of its brick and mortar, to find the name and nationality
of the householder, would be child’s play in
comparison. Life, as we have seen, is not the
offspring of protoplasm, but something which has been
superinduced upon, and may be separated from, the
protoplasm that serves as its material basis.
It is, therefore, distinct from the matter which it
animates, and, being thus immaterial, cannot possibly
become better known by any analysis of matter.
Of this emphatically vital question
Professor Huxley, as has been already intimated, takes
a diametrically opposite view. He does not merely,
in sufficiently explicit terms, deny that there is
any intrinsic difference between matter and spirit,
and affirm the two to be, in spite of appearances,
essentially identical. If this were all, I at
any rate should not be entitled to object, for I shall
myself presently have occasion to use very similar
language, although attaching to it a widely different
meaning from that with which it is used by Professor
Huxley. But the latter goes on to avow his belief
that the human body, like every other living body,
is a machine, all the operations of which will sooner
or later be explained on physical principles, insomuch
that we shall eventually arrive at a mechanical equivalent
of consciousness, even as we have already arrived
at a mechanical equivalent of heat. He considers
that with the same propriety with which the amount
of heat which a pound weight produces by falling through
the distance of a foot, may be called its equivalent
in one sense, may the amount of feeling which the
pound produces by falling through a foot of distance
on a gouty big toe, be called its equivalent in another
sense, to wit, that of consciousness. Yet he
protests against these tenets being deemed materialistic,
which, he declares, they certainly neither are nor
can be, for that while he himself certainly holds
them, he as certainly is not himself a materialist.
Professor Huxley is among the last to be suspected
of talking anything, as Monsieur Jourdain did prose,
without knowing it. He knows perfectly well that
he has here been talking materialism, but he insists
that his materialism is only another form of idealism.
He seeks to evade the seemingly inevitable deduction
from his premises by representing both matter and
spirit as mere names, and names, too, not for real
things, but for fanciful hypotheses which may be spoken
of indifferently in materialistic or in spiritualistic
terms, thought in the one case being treated as a
form of matter, and matter in the other as a form
of thought. The identity of matter and spirit
is, in short, represented by him as consisting in
this: that the existence of both is merely nominal,
or at best merely ideal.
Ordinary folk may perhaps be somewhat
slow to derive from this compromising theory all the
comfort which its author deems it capable of affording.
Most of us may, probably, be inclined to think that
we might as well have been left to fret in the frying-pan
of materialism as be cast headlong into idealistic
fire, to no better end than that of being there fused
body and soul together, and sublimated into inapprehensible
nothingness. Our immediate concern, however, is
not with the pleasantness of the theory, but with
its truth; in proceeding to test which we shall probably
find that there is as little warrant for idealising
matter after this fashion as we have already seen that
there is for materialising mind.
The originator of the theory about
to be examined, or rather, perhaps, of a somewhat
different theory out of which this has been developed not
to say perverted may, without much inaccuracy,
be pronounced to be Descartes. He it was who,
perceiving that we are surrounded on all sides by
illusions of all sorts, that not only is there no authority
or testimony implicitly to be depended on, but that
our senses likewise often play the traitor, and that
we can never be perfectly sure whether we are really
seeing, hearing, or feeling, or merely thinking or
dreaming that we see, hear, or feel, and looking anxiously
around for one single point at least on which complete
confidence might be placed, discovered such a point
in thought. Whatever else we may doubt about,
we cannot, he justly argued, doubt that there are
thoughts. If it were possible to doubt this,
our very doubt would be thought, constituting and
presenting as evidence the very existence doubted of.
Our thoughts, then, are unquestionably real existences.
They may be delusive, but they cannot possibly be
fictitious.
We may perhaps hereafter have occasion
to note how Descartes, having thus secured one firm
foothold and solid resting-place, outwent the farthest
stretch of Archimedean ambition by using it, not as
a fulcrum from whence to move the world, but as a
site for logical foundations whereon he might, if
he had persevered, have raised the superstructure
of an universe at once mental and material. Intermediately,
however, we have to observe how two pre-eminent disciples
of the Cartesian school have perverted the fundamental
proposition of their great master by treating its
converse as its synonyme. Descartes having
demonstrated that all thought is existence, Bishop
Berkeley and Professor Huxley infer that all existence
is thought. So says the Professor in so many
words, and to precisely the same effect is the more
diffuse language of the Bishop, where, speaking of
’all the choir of heaven and furniture of earth,
of all the bodies which compose the mighty frame of
the world,’ he declares that their esse
is percipi, that their ‘being’ consists
in their being ‘perceived or known,’ and
that unless they were actually perceived by, or existed
in, some created or uncreate mind, they could not
possibly exist at all.
The reasoning in support of these
assertions is in substance as follows: We
know nothing of any material object except by the
sensations which it produces in our minds. What
we are accustomed to call the qualities of
an object are nothing else but the mental sensations
of various kinds which the object produces within us.
Some of these qualities, such as extension, figure,
solidity, motion, and number, are classed as primary;
others, as, for instance, smell, taste, colour, sound,
as secondary. Now that these latter have no existence
apart from mind can readily be shown thus. If
I prick my finger with a needle, the pain I suffer
in consequence is surely in myself, not in the needle,
nor anywhere else but in myself. If an orange
be placed on my open hand, my sensation of touching
it is in myself, not in the orange. If the orange
could feel, what it would feel would be a hand, while
what I am feeling is an orange. Nor are my sensations
of pain and touch merely confined to myself; they
are also confined to a particular part of myself,
viz., to the brain, the seat of my consciousness,
which it is, and not the finger or hand, that really
feels when the one is hurt, or when anything comes
in harmless contact with the other. To prove
this, let the fine nervous threads, which, running
up the whole length of the arm, connect the skin of
the finger with the spinal marrow and brain, be cut
through close to the spinal cord, and no pain will
be felt, whatever injury be done: while if the
ends which remain in connection with the cord be pricked,
the sensation of pricking in the finger will arise
just as distinctly as before. Or let a walking-stick
be held firmly by the handle, and its other end be
touched, and the tactile sensation will be experienced
as if at the end of the stick, where, however, it
plainly cannot be. It is the mind alone which
feels, but which, by a peculiar faculty of localisation
or extradition, seems to remove a feeling exclusively
its own, not only to the outside of itself, but to
the outside also of the walls of its fleshly tenement.
And as it is with pain or touch, so it is with every
sensation with which any of the so-called secondary
qualities of matter are identical. If I look
at, or smell, or taste a blood orange, the sensation
of colour, or scent, or flavour I receive is entirely
and exclusively my own, the orange remaining quite
unconscious of its own redness, or fragrance, or sweetness,
and not, indeed, possessing in itself any real qualities
of the kind. For to take redness as an example;
how does the sensation of it or of any other colour
arise? The waves of a certain very attenuated
medium, the particles of which are vibrating with vast
rapidity but with very different velocities, strike
upon an object and are thrown off in all directions.
Of the particles which vibrate with any particular
velocity, some are gathered by the optical apparatus
of the eye, and deflected so as to impinge on the
retina and on the fibres of the optic nerve therewith
connected, producing in these fibres a change which
is followed by other changes in the brain, which, again,
by virtue of some inscrutable union between the brain
and the mind, create a feeling or consciousness of
colour. What the particular colour shall be,
depends either on the rate of motion in the vibrating
medium or on the character of the retina; and if,
while the former remained the same, the other were
to be altered, or if two persons, with differently
formed retinas, and one of the two colour-blind, were
to be looking, what had first seemed red might now
seem green, or what seemed red to one spectator might
seem green to the other. But as the same object
cannot itself be both red and green at the same time,
it follows that what are called its redness and greenness
are not in it, but in the spectator. Similarly,
the sounds which an object appears to give forth neither
are nor ever were in it: they originate in the
mind of the hearer, and have not, and never have had
any existence elsewhere. ’If the whole body
were an eye, where,’ asks St. Paul, ’were
the hearing? If the whole were hearing, where
were the smelling?’ and Professor Huxley more
than meets the drift of the Apostle’s questions
by pronouncing it ’impossible to imagine but
that if the universe contained only blind and deaf
beings, darkness and silence would reign everywhere.’
And as with the secondary qualities
of matter, so, on the same showing, must it be with
the primary. If colour, taste, scent, and the
like, exist nowhere but in the mind, so neither do
extension, solidity, and the like. If the former
could not exist unless there were intelligent minds
to perceive them, then neither could the latter.
For, by extension and its cognates, we understand
simply relations which we conceive to exist between
certain qualities of objects identical with certain
of our own visual and tactile sensations, or between
these and our consciousness of muscular effort; but
inasmuch as all sensations and all consciousness are
purely mental, and exist nowhere but in the mind,
it follows necessarily that ideas of relation between
different sensations, or between sensations and consciousness,
must also be purely mental, and non-existent save
in the mind. All the qualities of matter, therefore,
primary as well as secondary, are alike conceptions
of the mind, and consequently could not exist without
a mind for them to be conceived by and to exist in.
But if the qualities did not exist, then matter, which
cannot be conceived otherwise than as an assemblage
of qualities, could not exist either. Wherefore
in respect of matter itself, as well as of the qualities
of matter, esse is percipi, essence
is perception, to be is to be perceived. Wherefore,
finally, if there were no mind to perceive matter,
matter could not exist. Q. E. D.
Although in the foregoing summary
of an argument to which not Berkeley and Huxley alone,
but others of the deepest and acutest thinkers that
this country has produced, have contributed, I have
strenuously laboured to state all its points as convincingly
as the obligations of brevity would permit, I am not
myself by any means convinced by it. On the contrary,
although to say so may seem to imply a considerable
overstock of modest assurance, still I do say that
whatever portion of it is sound is irrelevant, and
that whatever portion is relevant is not sound.
So much of it as relates to the nature of the qualities
of matter, is, however interesting or otherwise important,
very little, if at all, to the purpose. No doubt
if I prick my finger with a needle, or to
take in preference an illustration employed by Locke if
my fingers ache in consequence of my handling snow,
it would be supremely ridiculous to talk of the pain
I feel being in the snow; yet not a whit more ridiculous
than to call the snow itself white or cold, if, by
so speaking, I mean that anything in the slightest
degree resembling my sensation of either snowy whiteness
or snowy coldness resides in the snow itself.
And as of coldness and whiteness, so of all the other
so-styled secondary qualities. If I smell a rose,
or listen to a piano, the rose or the piano is quite
insensible to the scent or sounds by which my sense
is ravished. And of primary qualities, also, precisely
the same thing may with equal confidence be alleged.
A stone which I perceive to be large, round, hard,
and either rotating or motionless, has no more perception
of its own extension, figure, solidity, motion, or
rest than a snowball has of its colour or temperature.
But all this, though perfectly true, has nothing to
do with the question, which is not what qualities
of matter are, but where they are, and whether
they can exist anywhere but in mind; and this question,
I submit, is distinctly begged by those who assume,
as is done throughout the reasoning under examination,
that our sensations with regard to material
objects, and the qualities of those objects,
are synonymous and convertible terms. Incontestably,
sensations are affections of the mind which neither
have nor can have any existence outside the mind.
If, then, the qualities of objects are identical with
the sensations which arise in the mind concerning
those objects, why, of course, the qualities likewise
can exist nowhere but in the mind. On narrowly
scrutinising, however, the supposed identity, we shall
find that it involves somewhat reckless confusion
of diametrical opposites. When I look at or smell
a rose, or eat a beefsteak, or listen to a piano, the
sensations which thereupon arise within me, whether
immediately or subsequently, either are the results
of my seeing, smelling, eating, or hearing, or they
are not. To say that they are not is equivalent
to saying that an object need not be within reach
of the perceptive faculties in order to be perceived;
that I may see or smell a rose, though there be no
rose to be seen or smelt; may dine sumptuously off
empty dishes, and be raised to the seventh heaven of
delight by the audible strains of a music which is
not being executed. Fortunati nimium only
too lucky would mankind be, did this turn out to be
a correct theory, affording as it would a solution
of every social problem, and serving as a panacea
for every social evil. Psychology would then
be the only science worth attention, for of whatever
things proficiency in that branch of study had qualified
any one to form mental images, of those same things
would he simultaneously become possessor in full property.
Whoever had succeeded in training himself to imagine
vigorously might at once have, do, or be whatever it
pleased him to imagine, becoming ipso facto,
as the Stoics used to say an acquirer of virtue does,
‘rich, beautiful, a king.’ Woe betide
any one, however, who, as long as the cosmical constitution
remains what it is, shall attempt to put the theory
into practice, and desisting from all those animal
functions, involving intercourse with a real or imaginary
external world, which are vulgarly supposed essential
to animal existence, shall obstinately restrict himself
to the sensations which he believes the mind to be,
without any such intercourse, capable of creating
for the body’s sustenance and delectation.
The physical extinction inevitably consequent on such
devotion to principle would speedily render all the
devotees physically incapable of testifying in behalf
of their peculiar opinion, and, clearing them away,
would leave no witnesses surviving but such as were
signifying by deeds if not in words their hearty adherence
to the popular belief. Practically, then, there
may be assumed to be entire unanimity of assent to
the truism that for our senses to be affected by the
presence of external objects, the objects must needs
be present to affect them. On all hands it is
in effect admitted that in some mode or other external
objects exist, but if so, and if the sensations resulting
from operations performed by the bodily organs with
external objects would not have resulted unless the
objects had been present to operate or to be operated
upon, clearly there must be resident in, or inseparably
bound up with, the objects a power or powers of producing
sensation in conscious mind. But the power of
producing sensation, and sensation itself, are not
one and the same thing, but two separate and distinct
things, intrinsically distinct and locally separate.
The feeling, agreeable or painful, according to its
intensity, which heat occasions, is not the same thing
as the heat by which it is occasioned. The twofold
taste, sweet to a healthy, bitter to a distempered
palate, of one and the same aliment, cannot be identical
with the single property of the aliment whereby the
taste is produced. In the sense of seeming red
to a spectator with normally constructed eyes, and
green to one who is colour-blind, a ruby or a Siberian
crab is at once both red and green, but the two colours
which it causes to be perceived cannot be identical
with the peculiar structure, or whatever else it be,
whereby the ruby or Siberian crab communicates to
circumambient ether the one self-same motion that terminates
in different impressions on differently constructed
eyes. In these and in all cases of the kind the
feeling is in the mind, the source of the feeling
in matter. The one is a perception, the other
a quality, and to mistake the quality, not merely
for a perception, but for the very perception to which
the quality gives rise; and to infer thence that the
quality must likewise be in the mind, is an instance
as glaring as can well be imagined of that most heinous
of logical offences, the confounding of cause with
effect.
By what steps Berkeley was led, and
has since led so many after him, into so grave an
error, he has himself acquainted us. Thus it is
that he argues: By sensible things can be meant
only such as can be perceived immediately by sense:
and sensible qualities are of course sensible
things. But the only perceptions of sense
are sensations, and all perceptions are purely mental.
Wherefore, sensible qualities being, as such, perceptible
immediately by the senses, must be sensations, and
being sensations must be perceptions, and being perceptions
they are of course purely mental, and existent nowhere
save in the mind. Carefully, however, as Berkeley
fancied he was picking his way, he really had tripped,
and that fatally, at the second step. He calls
the qualities of objects sensible things; but
sensible they are not according to his definition,
for they are not capable of being immediately perceived
by the senses. It is not sense which perceives,
but reason which infers them. The senses, as
Berkeley elsewhere repeatedly and earnestly insists,
receive nothing from objects but sensations, and these
they communicate to the mind without accompanying
them by the slightest hint as to whence they originally
came. The senses suggest nothing as to any qualities
resident in or appertaining to an object corresponding
with the sensations derived from the object.
The existence of such qualities is an inference of
reason which, taking for granted that sensations, in
common with all other occurrences, must have causes,
and observing that certain of them commonly occur
in the presence of certain objects, and never occur
in the absence of those objects, infers that the causes
of the sensations must exist in the objects.
To the causes thus inferred the name of qualities
is given, to distinguish them from the sensations
whereof they are causes; and the Berkeleian transgression
consists in overlooking the distinction between things
so diametrically opposite.
By the commission of such a sin the
most powerful intellect becomes inevitably committed
to further enormities. Except by neglecting to
distinguish between sight and hearing, the effects,
and light and sound, their respective causes, it would
surely have been impossible for Professor Huxley to
come to the strange conclusion that if all living
beings were blind and deaf, ’darkness and silence
would everywhere reign.’ Had he not himself
previously explained that light and sound are peculiar
motions communicated to the vibrating particles of
an universally diffused ether, which motions, on reaching
the eye or ear, produce impressions, which, after
various modifications, result eventually in seeing
or hearing? How these motions are communicated
to the ether matters not. Only it is indispensable
to note that they are not communicated by the percipient
owner of the eye or ear, so that the fact of there
being no percipient present cannot possibly furnish
any reason why the motions should not go on all the
same. But as long as they did go on there would
necessarily be light and sound; for the motions are
themselves light and sound. If, on returning to
his study in which, an hour before, he had left a
candle burning and a clock ticking, Professor Huxley
should perceive from the appearance of candle and clock
that they had gone on burning and ticking during his
absence, would he doubt that they had likewise gone
on producing the motions constituting and termed light
and sound, notwithstanding that no eyes or ears had
been present to see or hear? But if he did not
doubt this, how could he any more doubt that, although
all sentient creatures suddenly became eyeless and
earless, the sun might go on shining, and the wind
roaring, and the sea bellowing as before?
Akin to the inadvertence which, as
I presume to think, has led Professor Huxley thus
to misconceive secondary qualities, is an inattention
to the differences between our ideas, or mental pictures,
and the originals whereof those pictures are copies,
which seems to me seriously to vitiate his reasoning
with regard to primary qualities. With
admirable perspicuity he shows how it is that
our notions of primary qualities are formed; how the
mind, by localising on distinct points of the
sensory surface of the body its various, tactile sensations,
obtains the idea of extension, or space in two dimensions,
of figure, number, and motion: how the power,
combined with consciousness of the power, of moving
the hand in all directions over any substance it is
in contact with, adds the idea of geometrical solidity,
or of space in three dimensions: how the ideas
thus formed with the aid of the sense of touch are
confirmed by, and blended with, others derived from
visual sensations and muscular movements of the eye:
and, finally, how the idea of mechanical solidity,
or impenetrability, arises from experience of resistance
to our muscular exertions. All these details,
however, interesting as they are, are nevertheless
quite out of place. What we are at present concerned
with is the nature of the things themselves, not the
nature of our knowledge of them. No question that
this latter is purely mental. If figure, motion,
and solidity were really, as Professor Huxley says,
each of them nothing but a perception of the relation
of two or more sensations to one another, no question
but that, since the mind is the sole seat of perception,
they could exist nowhere else. But if all these
suppositions be incorrect, if, as we have seen, there
be in matter and apart from mind, potentialities of
producing sensations, it follows that, in matter,
and outside of mind, there must be relations between
different potentialities, and there must, moreover,
be limits to, and there may be changes in, those relations.
Wherefore, since there is in matter a potentiality
of imparting to the mind those sensations whence it
derives its ideas of place and distance, and since
figure is but a ‘limitation of distance,’
and motion but a ‘change of place,’ it
necessarily follows that there is in matter a potentiality
of conveying to the mind those sensations whence it
derives its ideas of figure and motion. And a
similar remark applies equally to solidity, and to
every other so-called quality of matter. All
of them are substantive potentialities of producing
in the mind those sensations whence our ideas of themselves
(the qualities) are derived. No doubt all these
qualities would be inconceivable in the absence
of a mind by which they might be conceived,
but it is not necessary that, in order to be,
they should be conceived. In discussions
of any abstruseness we cannot be too precise in our
use of words, and we shall inevitably be going astray
here if we allow ourselves for a moment to forget that
a quality and the conception of that quality are not
one single thing, but two things. Can it be seriously
supposed that if all the conscious creatures, of every
description, by which the universe is peopled, were
to fall temporarily into complete stupor, the material
universe would, at the commencement of the trance,
be deprived of its extension, solidity, figure, and
all its other constituent properties, recovering them
again as soon as its inhabitants woke up again?
Can it be doubted that, on the contrary, all potentialities
resident in its material composition would pursue
the even tenor of their way just as if nothing had
happened; performing, during the temporary absence
of external percipient minds, precisely those operations
which, as soon as consciousness returned to those
minds, would be followed by the perceptions of sight,
hearing, and touch? But if so, then plainly it
is exceedingly derogatory to matter to charge it with
such absolute dependence on external support that
its very being consists in being perceived from without.
That matter cannot exist without mind I cheerfully
admit, or rather most earnestly affirm, proposing presently
to explain in what sense I make the affirmation.
Meanwhile let it suffice to have ascertained that
the mental service with which matter cannot dispense,
whatever else it be, is at any rate not, as the whole
Berkeleian school so positively insist, that of mental
testimony to its existence.
Let us pause here for a moment to
report progress. We have seen, on the one hand,
that unless mind and matter have been eternally coexistent,
mind must have preceded matter, and that it is idle,
therefore, to expect, by any researches into matter,
to discover how mind (or life) originated. We
have seen that from a materialism which represents
mind as in any sense a property or product of matter
there is no possible outlet to an idealism which represents
matter as owing its being to mind. To see this
is simply to see that the builder of a house cannot
possibly have been born in the house he has himself
built. On the other hand, we have seen that the
idealism which represents being or existence as consisting
of perception is utterly incompatible with materialism
of any sort or kind, unless, indeed, with a materialistic
nihilism wherein would be no room for a solitary molecule,
still less for any molecular structure, and least
of all for that motion of molecular structures into
which consistent materialists are logically bound to
attempt to resolve all natural phenomena. We
have, in short, seen that materialism and idealism,
in the senses in which those terms are commonly used,
are utterly incapable of amalgamation, or indeed of
even being harmoniously approximated, without being
first deprived of all the characteristic traits which
at present entitle them to their distinguishing appellations.
To which of the two belongs the larger
share of blame for this implacable hostility is easily
determined. Materialism, in dealing with mental
phenomena, begins by setting chronology at defiance;
but between idealism and the phenomena of matter there
is no such aboriginal incongruity. From principles
common to every form of idealism a theory is deducible
which, while frankly acknowledging the reality of matter,
may, with perfect consistency, maintain that reality
to be mental although mental in the sense
of being, not a perception by, but a metamorphosis
of, mind. Of such a theory the outlines seem to
me to have been sketched, and the foundations partly
laid, by Descartes, and it cannot be otherwise than
interesting to inquire in what manner and how far
so consummate an artificer advanced in the work, and
where and wherefore he suddenly stopped short in it.
When Descartes, after convincing himself
of the hollow pretentiousness of most human knowledge,
proceeded to dig away the accumulated drift and sand
of ages in quest of any clay or rock there might be
below, the first indubitable verity he came to was
thought, about whose reality there could, as already
explained, be no possibility of doubt, inasmuch as
any doubt concerning it, being itself thought, would
be but an additional proof of it. On the bit
of firm ground thus thoroughly tested, he proceeded
to place a formula not less carefully verified, his
famous ‘Cogito, ergo sum’ ’I
think, therefore I am.’ By many of his
followers, however, this second verification of his
is deemed to be by no means so satisfactory as it
was by himself, Professor Huxley more especially taking
vehement, though, as I make bold to add, somewhat
gratuitous, exception to every single word of the most
celebrated of Cartesian formulae. No doubt the
premiss of the formula assumes the conclusion, but
it likewise includes as well as assumes it. No
doubt, since ‘I think’ is but another
way of saying ‘I am thinking,’ to say
that ‘I think’ is to assume that ‘I
am;’ nay, the same thing is equally assumed
by the mere introduction of the pronoun ‘I.’
But Descartes was fully warranted in taking for granted
the truth of his conclusion. For by previously
showing incontestably that thought and consciousness
are real existences, he had completely proved the
premiss wherein his conclusion is included. What
though, as Professor Huxley suggests, ‘thought’
may possibly ‘be self-existent,’ ’or
a given thought the result of its antecedent thought,
or of some external power’? Be thought
what else it may, it must needs be, also, either an
affection or an operation; if not performed, it must
be felt; there must needs be, therefore, something
by which it is either performed or felt, and that
something cannot possibly be other than a thinking
and conscious thing. As surely as thought is,
so surely must there be a thinker. This is, in
substance, affirmed even by many who deny it in terms,
and Hume, in particular, when saying, as he somewhere
does, that ’all we are conscious of is a series
of perceptions,’ denies and affirms it at one
and the same time. For how can there be perception
without a percipient? or how consciousness without
a conscious entity? or how can that entity be conscious
of feeling without being simultaneously conscious that
it is itself which feels, without knowing, consequently,
that it has a self, or without being warranted, if
it possess the gift of speech, in declaring, in words
even more emphatic than those of Descartes, ’I
myself am’? And how, if these questions
do not admit of reply, can Professor Huxley be warranted
in declaring self and non-self to be mere ‘hypotheses
by which we account for the facts of consciousness,’
and adding that of their existence we ’neither
have, nor by any possibility can have’ the same
’unquestionable and immediate certainty as we
have of the states of consciousness which we consider
to be their effects’? Surely the existence
of self is one of the most direct and immediate subjects
of consciousness; yet it does not depend for evidence
on consciousness alone, but is as unanswerably demonstrable
as that two straight lines cannot enclose space or
that parallel lines cannot meet, or as any other mathematical
negation. No ratiocinative deduction can be more
incontestable than that, since I have thoughts,
there must be an I to have them.
Whoever thus assures himself of the
existence of self obtains simultaneously equal assurance
of the existence of non-self; for feeling that his
conscious self is not boundless, but is confined within
limits, he cannot doubt that beyond those limits there
must be space, and, receiving continual sensations
from without, he perceives that there are, in external
space, potentialities of imparting sensations.
Thus, I repeat, Descartes in laying down the first
principles of his philosophy created an intellectual
basis for the external universe. Unfortunately,
however, instead of proceeding to place its proper
superstructure on the foundation thus laid, he wilfully
stepped aside from what he had just pronounced the
only firm ground in existence, and undertook to raise
a rival edifice on part of the formless void beyond.
Deeply struck by the grand discoveries of his illustrious
contemporaries, Galileo and Harvey, and thence discovering
for himself that the phenomena of remotest worlds
and also the involuntary phenomena of our own bodily
frames take place in accordance with forces of uniform
operation, he leaped suddenly to the conclusion that
those forces are purely mechanical. The circulation
of the blood, he says, ’is as much the necessary
result of the structure of the parts one can see in
the heart, and of the heat which one may feel there,
and of the nature of the blood which may be experimentally
ascertained, as is the motion of a clock the result
of the force, situation, and figure of its wheels
and of its weight.’ Nor, in his view, does
the heart, by virtue of its structure and composition,
merely cause the blood to circulate. ‘It
also generates animal spirits,’ which, ’ascending
like a very subtle fluid, or very pure and vivid flame,
into the brain as into a reservoir, pass thence into
the nerves, where, according as they more or less
enter, or tend to enter, they have the power of altering
the figures of the muscles into which the nerves are
inserted, and of so causing all the organs and limbs
to move.’ He puts the case thus: Even
as the ordinary movements of a water-clock or of a
mill are kept up by the ordinary flow of the water,
and even as ’in the grottoes and fountains of
royal gardens, the force wherewith the water issues
from its reservoirs suffices to move various machines,
and even to make them play instruments or pronounce
words according to the different disposition of the
pipes which lead the water’ even so
do pulsation, respiration, digestion, nutrition, and
growth, and ’other such actions as are natural
and usual in the body,’ result naturally from
the usual course of the animal spirits. Moreover,
even as intruders upon the waterworks aforesaid unconsciously
by their mere presence cause special movements to
take place, even as, for example, ’if they approach
a bathing Diana, they tread on certain planks so arranged
as to make her hide among the reeds, and, if they
attempt to follow her, see approaching a Neptune who
threatens with his trident, or rouse some other monster
who vomits water into their faces’ even
so do external objects, by their mere presence, act
upon the organs of sense; even so do ’the reception
of light, sounds, odours, flavours, heat, and such
like qualities in the organs of the external senses,
the impression of the ideas of these in the intellect,
the imagination, and the memory, the internal movements
of the appetites and passions, and the external movements
which follow so aptly on the presentation of objects
to the senses, or on the resuscitation of impressions
by the memory,’ yea, even so do all these ’functions
proceed naturally from the arrangement of the bodily
organs, neither more nor less than do the movements
of a clock or other automaton from that of its weights
and its wheels, without the aid of any other vegetative
or sensitive soul or any other principle of motion
or of life than the blood and the spirits agitated
by the fire which burns continually within the heart,
and which differs in no wise from the fire existing
in inanimate bodies.’
Quite fairly it may be urged that
the writer of passages like these would, if writing
in modern language, and with the aid of modern conceptions,
have expressed himself much as Professor Huxley does
when, declaring that the circulation of the blood
and the regular movements of the respiratory, alimentary,
and other internal organs are simply ‘affairs
of mechanism, resulting from the structure and arrangement’
of the bodily organs concerned, from ’the contractility
of those organs, and from the regulation of that contractility
by an automatically acting nervous apparatus;’
that muscular contractility and the automatic activity
or irritability of the nerves are ’purely the
results of molecular mechanism;’ and that ’the
modes of motion which constitute the physical bases
of light, sound, and heat are transmuted by the sensory
organs into affections of nervous matter,’ which
affections become ’a kind of physical ideas
constituting a physical memory,’ and may be
combined in a manner answering to association and imagination,
or may give rise to muscular contractions in those
reflex actions which are the mechanical representatives
of volition.’ Quite fairly may a doctrine,
capable of being thus translated, be described as leading
’straight to materialism.’ Quite
justly may its author be claimed by Huxley as joint
professor of a materialistic creed. True, Descartes
lodges within his human mechanism a chose pensante
or rational soul, whose principal seat is in the brain,
and who is treated as corresponding to a hydraulic
engineer stationed in the centre of waterworks for
the purpose of increasing, slackening, or otherwise
altering their movements. But this rational soul
is a very needless appendage to either the Cartesian
or the Huxleian system, wherein, if its post be not
a literal sinecure, there is, at any rate, little
or nothing for it to do which might not quite as well
be done without it. The hydraulic engineer, sitting
in his central office, has to wind up the whole machinery
from time to time, and to turn now this tap, now that,
when he wishes to set this or that particular machine
in motion. But, as no one need be told, our chose
pensante has nothing to do with the winding up
of our digestive, circulatory, or respiratory apparatus;
and so far from internally arranging those other internal
organs from the mere arrangement of whose parts, according
to Descartes, the reception, conversion, and retention
of sensations, and the movements, whether internal
or external, thereupon consequent, naturally proceed,
or from regulating the molecular mechanism, whence,
according to Professor Huxley, results the automatic
nervous activity which, in his opinion, governs the
movements of the limbs not less absolutely than those
of the intestines, it, nine times out of ten, neither
knows nor suspects that any such organs or mechanism
exist. If the functions above attributed to the
human frame could be shown really to belong to it,
pure, not to say crass, materialism, would require
no further proof. Those particular functions
undoubtedly take place without the cognisance of that
particular sensitive soul which we call ourself, so
that if no other sensitive soul take cognisance of
them, they must needs be, not simply automatic performances,
but performances of an automaton of such marvellous
powers as to be quite equal to the performance likewise
of whatever human operations are vulgarly classed
as mental. Assume, however illogically, that
motion is a function of matter, and from that premiss,
whether true or false, the conclusion that thought
likewise is a function of matter may be quite logically
deduced. ’That thought is as much a function
of matter as motion is’ must needs be conceded
to Professor Huxley, who, therefore, if he could show
that motion is really such a function, would be fully
justified in adding, that ’the distinction between
spirit and matter vanishes,’ that ‘we
lose spirit in matter.’
Undeniably, then, of the Cartesian
philosophy one moiety is, as Professor Huxley says,
materialistic; but from the self-contradictions inseparable
from every species of materialism the Cartesian variety
is, of course, no more exempt than any other, and
it has besides one self-contradiction peculiar to
itself. A clock’s pendulum vibrates, and
its hands move, not simply by reason of the situation
and figure of its weight and wheels, but also because
some intelligent person, by winding up the clock,
has communicated an impulsive force to the weight and
wheels. Waterworks perform all sorts of antics,
not solely because the pipes are skilfully constructed
and arranged with a view to such end, but because
also an intelligent engineer has turned running water
into the pipes. But the only intelligent agent
to whom Descartes allows access to his corporeal machinery
is one who not only has no notion how to apply a moving
force except to some few portions of the machinery,
but with regard to the other portions has most likely
no suspicion that they even exist. But how in
the absence of some other intelligence, of some other
’vegetative or sensitive soul or principle of
motion or of life,’ is it possible for the inert
and inanimate heart to generate animal spirits? how
is it possible for death thus to give birth to life? or,
if the generative faculty be supposed to be the necessary
result of a particular molecular structure, how is
it that when the animal spirits become from any cause
extinct, they are not immediately regenerated by the
same molecular structure? or rather, how is it possible
for animal spirits to become extinct as long as the
molecular structure of which they are necessary concomitants
remains unaltered? In these questions the old
insuperable difficulties reappear in new forms, but
on these we need not dwell. Apart from anti-materialistic
arguments of general applicability, there is a mode
of refutation specially adapted to the Cartesian form
of materialism, which, besides flatly contradicting
itself, contradicts not less flatly a twin system of
unimpeachable veracity. Truth cannot be opposed
to truth: a doctrine cannot be true, even
though propounded by Descartes and Huxley, if it conflict
irreconcileably with doctrines which Descartes and
Huxley have unanswerably demonstrated. Now one-half
of Cartesian philosophy shows conclusively that amidst
the countless infinity of human notions, the one single
and solitary certainty of independent and self-evident
authority is the existence of thought, and nothing
else whatever, therefore, can be entitled to be regarded
as absolutely certain which cannot be shown to rest
mediately or immediately upon this. One thing
which can, by strictest logical process, be shown so
to rest, is the existence of a thinking self; and
another is the existence of a non-self or external
universe; but of this external universe we know scarcely
anything beyond the bare fact that it exists.
We know that outside the thinking self there are potentialities
capable of somehow or other communicating sensations
to the thinking self; but of the nature of these potentialities
our senses teach us absolutely nothing, and the few
particulars that reason is able to discover, are, with
one single though very momentous exception, to which
we are rapidly approaching, purely negative.
We do know to a certain extent what qualities of objects
are not. We know that they are not and cannot
be in the least like the sensations which we call
by the same names. We know that what we call
the whiteness and coldness of snow or the hardness
and weight of marble, can no more resemble the feelings
we receive from looking at or handling snow or marble
than the mental exaltation produced within us on hearing
one of Bach’s fugues is like the organ on
which, or the organist by whom, it is played.
We know that of the pictures which our senses form
for us not one can possibly be a correct likeness.
We know that what we fancy we see in matter we do
not see; that what we seem to feel we do not feel;
that the apparent structure and composition of matter
cannot therefore possibly be real. To this conviction
we are irresistibly drawn by a chain of idealistic
reasoning of which Descartes forged the first link,
and every link of which will stand the severest strain.
But if this be the teaching of an idealism occupying
as its base the only morsel of solid ground to be
found in the mental universe, what scrap of footing
is there left for an antagonistic materialism purporting
to rest on what we can see and feel of a structure
and composition which, as we have just satisfied ourselves,
we cannot see or feel at all?
As plainly then as one half of Descartes’
philosophy is materialistic, so plainly, that half,
instead of a necessary outgrowth and exact correlative
of the other or idealistic moiety is, on the contrary,
the latter’s diametrical and implacable opponent.
As plainly, therefore, as the one is true, must the
other be false, and Cartesian idealism, in so far
as its character has been exhibited above, has, I submit,
been demonstrated to be true. The greater the
pity that it was not brought to maturity by its author.
In enumerating its first principles, Descartes, as
I must once again observe, was forming a logical basis
whereon a comprehensive and consistent conception
of an external universe might forthwith have been
securely deposited, had he not unluckily, instead of
himself proceeding to build on his own foundations,
with congruous materials, left them free for others
to build upon with gold, silver, precious stones,
wood, hay, or stubble, as chance might determine.
May I, without presumption, hazard a conjecture as
to the sort of fabric that might have arisen, if he
had steadily prosecuted his original design?
At the stage which we are supposing
him to have reached, very little remained to complete
the work. Around man, around every individual
man, or other conscious intelligence, as its centre,
is ranged infinitely extended space, filled with,
or, as it were, composed of various kinds of matter,
every kind and every separate portion of which is endowed
with special qualities capable of communicating corresponding
sensations to the central intelligence. So far
all that can be predicated of any material object
or portion of matter is that it is a collection of
qualities; but from hence we may advance boldly to
the further negative discovery that it is nothing
else; that there is not and cannot be, in addition
to those qualities, any substance in or to which the
qualities inhere, or are in any way attached.
The absence from matter of any such
substance is evidenced by the absurdity involved in
the idea of its presence. Suppose the substance
to exist: the qualities inherent in it must needs
be as completely distinct from itself as pins are
from a pincushion; the extension and solidity of an
extended, solid substance can no more be identical
with the substance than the nominative is identical
with the genitive case. The substance, therefore,
although deprived of all its qualities will still retain
its essence unimpaired, will still be equally a substance,
just as a pincushion continues equally a pincushion
after its last pin has been abstracted. Conceive,
then, all the qualities of matter to be abstracted,
and consider what remains a substance without
qualities of any sort. But a substance neither
solid, nor fluid, nor yet gaseous; neither coloured
nor colourless; neither singular nor plural; without
form and void, without even extension what
is it? not something, but nothing; a nonentity or
non-existence. The qualities of matter in being
removed from the substance have therefore left nothing
behind, and, consequently, although carrying with
them nothing but themselves, have yet carried with
them all the constituents of matter, which is thus
seen to be composed exclusively of qualities without
a single particle of foreign admixture. And since,
moreover, the qualities of matter are clearly not
themselves substances, that is to say do not themselves
stand under or uphold anything, it follows that
their compound, matter, must likewise be purely unsubstantial.
The edifice begun by Descartes has
now been raised high and strong enough to have its
layer of negations crowned with an affirmation of
pre-eminent importance. The qualities of matter,
being known only by their effects, are evidently causes:
and, being causes, must necessarily be either themselves
forces, or, at the least, manifestations of force;
and inasmuch as force involves exertion, it cannot
be inert; and inasmuch as deadness must be incapable
of exertion, all force must be alive; and life without
substance cannot be conceived otherwise than as some
species of spirit or mind. Such therefore must
be matter. Matter can be nothing else than pure
spirit of some kind.
And may we not with good reason congratulate
ourselves on this result of our investigations?
Instead of the vision we were threatened with, of
mind losing itself in matter, our eyes are gladdened
with that of the converse operation, of the transmutation
of matter into mind. And on no account is this
metamorphosis to be mistaken for annihilation of matter,
whose stolid grossness has vanished, not in order to
give place to empty nominalism or to a thin mist of
mere mental perceptions existing only in virtue of
being perceived, but in order to reappear gloriously
etherealised into living energy. By the change
that has taken place, corruption has put on incorruption;
the natural body has become a quickening spirit; death
is swallowed up in victory. Matter reappears
converted, not into a perception of percipient mind,
but into percipient mind itself; yet although thus
presumably percipient of its own existence, it not
the less has an existence perfectly independent of
perception, either by itself or by any other intelligence.
Under what head the mind, or combination
of living forces, thus constituting all matter, ought
to be classed, is a question, which the imperfection
of human faculties may as well be content to leave
unanswered, though to its being supposed to emanate
directly from the mind of Omnipresent Deity, one insuperable
objection may be mentioned, which should be kept steadily
in view. There are few of us who will not shrink
with horror from a notion, according to which man,
whenever doing as he pleases with any material object,
applying it, as likely as not, to some base or criminal
purpose, is disposing at his pleasure of a portion
of the Divine essence: few who will not greatly
prefer to believe that the vital principle which manifests
itself in the form of a dunghill or of a poisoned
dagger, may be, for the time, as completely individualised
and separate from all other life or mind, as every
human being perceives his own conscious mind or self
to be. At all events, we have now reached a point
beyond which it would be rash to rush hastily on.
For a while we may be well content to rest where we
are. That matter is nothing else but a peculiar
manifestation, or avatar, of some species of mind,
whatever that species be, is a proposition as demonstrably
true as its converse is demonstrably false. Unless
it be possible for death to give birth to life, it
is impossible for living mind to be the offspring
of inanimate matter; but so surely as mind is mind,
and that living force alone can act either on mind
or aught else, so surely must all matter that imparts
sensation to mind, be itself a species of living force
and consequently a species of mind.
An unexpected conclusion this, and
widely different, I confess, from that to which I
was myself looking forward at the outset of the discussion;
yet, at the same time, one of which there is the best
possible proof in the impossibility of conceiving its
contrary. It is besides a conclusion to which
not only ought Descartes in consistency to have come,
but at which both Locke and Berkeley, though advancing
from opposite points of the compass, did very nearly
arrive; nay, which the latter did almost touch, and
must apparently have grasped, had not his hands been
already full of other things. It is, moreover,
one from which I do not apprehend that Professor Huxley
himself will seriously dissent. Indeed, I almost
hope that he may object chiefly to its having been
moved by me as an amendment on his original motion,
and that he may be disposed to claim it for himself
as a portion of genuine Huxleyism. If so, I shall
readily recognise the claim so far as to admit that
things very similar to many of those said by me above
had already been said by Professor Huxley; though,
in justice to myself, I must add that their complete
opposites had likewise been said by him. But the
office which I here proposed to myself was mainly
that of an eclectic, who, going over a field which
another husbandman has tilled, separates the wheat
from the tares, and binds up the former into
shapely and easily portable sheaves; and no more satisfactory
assurance can be given of my having been usefully
employed in such subordinate capacity than that Professor
Huxley, who, amongst all his numerous admirers, has
not one sincerer than myself, should welcome me as
a coadjutor, instead of repelling me as an antagonist.