In the first month of 1820 George
III. died. His had been an eventful reign, strangely
checkered with disaster and glory; but, if we compare
its close with its commencement, it was still more
remarkably distinguished by a development of the resources
and an increase in the wealth and power of the nation,
to which the history of no other country in the same
space of time affords any parallel.
Regarded from the first point of view,
our successes greatly outweighed our disasters.
The loss of our North American Colonies, the only event
which can be so described, was far more than counterbalanced
by our vast acquisitions in India, at the Cape of
Good Hope, and Malta; while to our maritime supremacy,
in the complete establishment of which Rodney and
Nelson had crowned the work of Anson and Hawke, was
now added a splendor of military renown far surpassing
that achieved by any other of the nations which had
borne their share in the overthrow of Napoleon.
The increase of our resources is sufficiently
shown by a single fact. At his accession George
III. found the kingdom engaged in the great seven
years’ war; one British army employed beyond
the Rhine, another in India; fleets traversing the
seas in every direction, capturing the Havana, in
the West Indies; Manilla, in the East; and routing
French squadrons in sight of their own harbors.
While, to maintain these varied armaments, supplies
were voted by Parliament in 1761 to what Lord Stanhope
calls “the unprecedented amount of almost twenty
millions.” In 1813 the supplies reached
nearly six times that amount, and that prodigious
sum was raised with greater ease than the revenue of
1761, the interest on the necessary loans being also
lower than it had been on the former occasion.
The philosophical man of science will
point with at least equal exultation to the great
discoveries in art and science; to the achievements
of the mechanic, the engineer, and the chemist; to
the labors of Brindley and Arkwright and Watts, to
which, indeed, this great expansion of the resources
and growth of the wealth of the country is principally
owing.
While, as the preceding chapters of
this work have been designed to show, our political
progress and advancement had been no less steady or
valuable; yet, important from a constitutional point
of view as were many of the labors of our legislators
in these sixty years, they are surpassed in their
influence on the future history of the nation, as
well as in the reality and greatness of the changes
which were produced by them in the constitution, by
the transactions of the reigns of the next two sovereigns,
though the two united scarcely equalled in their duration
a quarter of that of their venerable father.
It has been seen how Pitt was baffled
in his efforts to remodel the House of Commons, and
to remove the disabilities under which the Roman Catholics
labored, the reasons for which, even granting that
they had been sufficient to justify their original
imposition, had, in his judgment, long passed away.
His pursuit of the other great object of his domestic
policy, the emancipation of trade from the shackles
which impeded its universal development, was rudely
interrupted by the pressure of the war forced upon
him by that very nation which he had desired to make
the first partner, if one may use such an expression,
in the prosperity which he hoped to diffuse by his
commercial treaty with her. But, as in the case
of other men in advance of their age, the principles
which he had asserted were destined to bear fruit at
a later period. And the mere fact of a change
in the person of the sovereign seemed to make a change
in the policy hitherto pursued less unnatural.
Yet, memorable as the reforms which
it witnessed were destined to make it, no reign ever
commenced with more sinister omens than that at which
we have now arrived. The new King had not been
on the throne a month, when a conspiracy was discovered,
surpassing in its treasonable atrocity any that had
been heard of in the kingdom since the days of the
Gunpowder Plot; and, even before those concerned in
that foul crime had been brought to punishment, the
public mind was yet more generally and profoundly
agitated by a scandal which, in one point of view,
was still more painful, as in some degree involving
the whole kingdom in its disgrace.
The marriage of the present sovereign
to Mrs. Fitzherbert has already been mentioned.
A few years afterward, in the year 1795, regarding
that marriage as illegal, he had contracted a second
with his cousin, the Princess Caroline of Brunswick.
But, even in royal families, a more unfortunate alliance
had never taken place. They had never met till
she arrived in England for the wedding; and, as he
had never professed any other motive for consenting
to the match than a desire to obtain the payment of
his debts, he did not think it necessary to disguise
his feelings, or to change his habits, or even to
treat her with decency for a single day. On his
very first introduction to her he behaved to her with
marked discourtesy. Shortly after the marriage
he formally separated himself from her, and, both
before and after the separation, lived in undisguised
licentiousness. She, on her part, indignant at
his neglect and infidelity, and exasperated at the
restrictions which he presently placed on her intercourse
with their only child, made no secret of her feelings,
and on many occasions displayed such disregard of
the ordinary rules of prudence and propriety, that
he had some color for charges of infidelity to her
marriage vows which, after a few years, he brought
against her. The King, her uncle, could not refuse
to appoint a commission to investigate the truth of
the accusation; but the commissioners unanimously
acquitted her of any graver fault than imprudence.
She was again received at court, from which she had
been excluded while the inquiry was pending; but her
husband’s animosity toward her was not appeased.
As time wore on, and as the King’s derangement
deprived her of her only protector, it even seemed
as if he desired to give it all the notoriety possible,
till at last, wearied out by his implacable persecution,
she sought and obtained his permission to quit the
country and take up her abode abroad. It was a
most unfortunate resolution on her part. She
fixed her residence in Italy, where she gradually
learned to neglect the caution which she had observed
in England, till, after a year or two, reports arose
of her intimacy with a servant whom she had raised
from a menial situation to that of the chief officer
of her household, and whom she admitted to a familiarity
of intercourse which others besides her husband thought
quite incompatible with innocence. He sent agents
into Italy to inquire into the truth of those rumors;
and their report so greatly confirmed them that, even
before the King’s death, he laid it before the
Prime-minister, with a demand that he should at once
take steps to procure him a divorce, in which he professed
to believe that the Princess herself would willingly
acquiesce. He was so far correct, that her legal
advisers were willing to advise her to consent to
“a formal separation, to be ratified by an act
of Parliament.” But such an arrangement
fell far short of the Prince’s wishes.
The Princess Charlotte, the heiress to his throne,
had died in childbirth two years before, and he was
anxious to be set free to marry again. The ministers
were placed in a situation of painful embarrassment.
There was an obvious difficulty in pointing out to
one who already stood toward them in the character
of their sovereign, and who must inevitably soon become
so, that his own conduct made the prospect of obtaining
a divorce from the Ecclesiastical Courts hopeless;
and the only other expedients calculated to attain
his end, “a direct application to Parliament
for relief, founded upon the special circumstances
of the case,” or “a proceeding against
the Princess for high-treason,” were but little
more promising. Indeed, it was afterward ascertained
to be the unanimous opinion of the judges that the
charge of high-treason could not be legally sustained,
since the individual who was alleged to be the partner
in the criminality imputed to her was a foreigner,
and therefore, “owing no allegiance to the crown,”
could not be said to have violated it.
He chafed under their resistance to
his wish, and would have deprived them of their offices,
could he have relied on any successors whom he might
give them proving more complaisant; but, before he
could make up his mind, the death of George III. forced
upon both him and them the consideration of his and
his wife’s position, since it made it necessary
to remodel the prayer for the royal family, and instantly
to decide whether her name and title as Queen were
to be inserted in it. He was determined that
they should not be mentioned; and, as the practice
of praying for a Queen Consort by name appeared not
to have been invariable, they were willing to gratify
him on this point, though it was evidently highly
probable that she would consider this as a fresh insult,
sufficient to justify her in carrying out a threat,
which she had recently held out, of returning to England.
Her ablest advisers did not, indeed, regard it in
this light, since the prayer as now framed implored
the Divine protection for “all the royal family”
in general terms, in which she might be supposed to
be included, and made no separate mention of any member
of the family. But, unfortunately, she was much
more under the influence of counsellors who were neither
lawyers nor statesmen, but who only desired to use
her as a tool to obtain notoriety for themselves.
A long negotiation ensued. It was inevitable
that some application should be made to Parliament
in connection with her affairs, since the annuity
which had been settled upon her by Parliament in 1814,
on the occasion of her departure from England, had
expired with the life of the late King. And the
ministers proposed that that annuity should now be
raised from L35,000 to L50,000, on condition of her
remaining abroad, having, by their positive refusal
to concur in any proceedings against her while she
remained abroad, extorted the King’s acquiescence
in this proposal, though he called it a “great
and painful sacrifice of his personal feelings.”
They sought to conciliate her acceptance of it by
mentioning her in it by her title of “Queen,”
and by coupling with it a sanction to her appointment
of her law-officers, an Attorney and Solicitor General,
an act which could only be exercised by a Queen.
And, though a part of the condition of her residence
abroad required that she should do so under some other
title, that seemed only a conforming to an ordinary
practice of royal princes on their travels. At
the same time, the ministers stated frankly to Mr.
Brougham, a lawyer of the highest reputation as an
advocate, whom she had appointed her Attorney-general,
that, if she should reject the offer, and come to
England, as she had already announced her intention
of doing, such a course would leave them no alternative,
but would compel them to institute proceedings against
her.
Eventually she preferred the advice
of others to that of Mr. Brougham, or, as it may,
perhaps, be more consistent with the real fact to say,
she yielded to her own feelings of hatred of her husband,
which, it must be confessed, were far from unnatural.
She believed, or professed to believe, that he had
more to dread from an exposure of his conduct than
she had from any revelations of her actions; and, under
this impression, in the spring she crossed the Channel
and took up her residence in London. It was a
step which seemed to Lord Liverpool to leave him no
alternative, and, in consequence, he at once took the
course which he had from the beginning conceived her
arrival would render indispensable. He brought
down to Parliament a royal message from the King, announcing
that her return to England had made it necessary to
communicate to the Houses documents relating to her
conduct since her departure from the kingdom, which
he recommended to their immediate and serious attention.
He proposed the appointment by ballot of a committee
of the House of Lords to examine those documents;
and when the committee had reported that the documents
containing “allegations deeply affecting the
honor of the Queen, etc., ... appeared to the
committee calculated to affect not only the honor
of the Queen, but also the dignity of the crown and
the moral feelings and honor of the country, so that
in their opinion, they should become the subject of
a solemn inquiry, which might be best effected in
the course of a legislative proceeding,” he introduced
a “Bill of Pains and Penalties” to deprive
her of her title of Queen, and to annul her marriage.
No one would willingly dwell on so
melancholy and disgraceful a subject. As far
as the Queen was concerned, a protracted investigation,
during which a number of witnesses, favorable and
unfavorable, were examined, left no doubt on the mind
of almost all dispassionate people that the misconduct
alleged against her had been abundantly proved.
At the same time there was a feeling equally general
that the King’s treatment of her from the very
beginning of their married life had disentitled him
to any kind of relief; and this sentiment was so strongly
shown by the gradual diminution of the majority in
favor of the bill, as it proceeded through its several
stages, that Lord Liverpool, who had already abandoned
the clause annulling the marriage, eventually withdrew
the whole bill, perceiving the impossibility of inducing
the House of Commons to pass it when it should go
down to that House.
No act of Lord Liverpool’s ministry
has been attacked with greater bitterness than that
of allowing any proceedings whatever to be taken against
the Queen, partly on the ground that, however profligate
her conduct had been, it had certainly not been more
gross than that of her husband, which had provoked
and given opportunity for her errors; partly because
a great scandal was thus published to the world, and
a shock was given to the national decency and morality
which the ministers, above all men, were bound to
avoid; partly, also, because the mode of proceeding
adopted was alleged to be wholly unprecedented; and
because, as was contended, the power of Parliament
ought not to be invoked to inflict penalties which,
if deserved, should have been left to the courts of
law. It cannot be denied that there is weight
in these objections; but, in estimating their force,
it must be considered that every part of the conduct
of the ministers showed that their motive was not
the gratification of the King’s private feelings,
whether directed to the object of indulging his enmity
against his wife or to that of obtaining freedom to
contract a second marriage; on the contrary, so long
as the Queen remained abroad, no language could be
more distinct, consistently with the respect due to
his royal dignity, than that in which they expressed
to him their insurmountable objection to every mode
of proceeding against her which he had suggested, founded
almost equally on considerations of “the interests
of his Majesty and of the monarchy," and “the
painful obligation” under which they conceived
themselves to lie “of postponing their regard
for his Majesty’s feelings to great public interests.”
But when the Queen came to England
the case was greatly altered. The question now
forced on the consideration of the cabinet was, not
the mode of avoiding an intolerable scandal, but the
choice between two scandals, both of the gravest character.
The scandal to be dreaded from the revelations of
the conduct of both King and Queen, that could not
fail to result from the investigation which, in justice,
must precede any attempt to legislate on the subject,
was, indeed, as great as ever; but it had now to be
compared with the alternative scandal of allowing a
woman lying under such grievous imputations to preside
over the British court, as, if resident in England,
and in undisturbed possession of her royal rank, she
of necessity must preside. The consequence would
evidently have been that the court would have been
deserted by all who could give lustre and dignity
to it by their position and character; and, in the
slights thus offered to her, royalty and the monarchy
themselves would seem to be brought into contempt.
The latter scandal, too, would be the more permanent.
Grievous and shameful as might be the disclosures
which must be anticipated from an investigation in
which the person accused must be permitted the employment
of every means of defence, including recrimination,
the scandal was yet one which would, to a certain
extent, pass away with the close of the inquiry.
But, if she were left undisturbed in the enjoyment
of her royal rank, and of privileges which could not
be separated from it, that scandal would last as long
as her life longer, in all probability,
than the reign. It is hardly too much to say
that the monarchy itself might have been endangered
by the spectacle of such a King and such a Queen; and
the ministers might fairly contend that, of two great
dangers and evils, they had, on the whole, chosen
the least.
Lastly, if the Queen’s conduct
was to be investigated, though the mode adopted was
denounced as unconstitutional by the Opposition (for,
not greatly to their credit, the leading Whigs made
her guilt or innocence a party question), it does
not seem to deserve the epithet, though it may be
confessed to have been unsupported by any direct precedent.
Isabella, the faithless wife of Edward II., had, indeed,
been condemned by “the Lords” to the forfeiture
of many of the estates which she had illegally appropriated;
but it does not appear that her violation of her marriage
vows, or even her probable share or acquiescence in
her husband’s murder, formed any portion of
the grounds of her deprivation. And the Parliament
which attainted Catherine Howard proceeded solely on
her confession of ante-nuptial licentiousness, without
giving her any opportunity of answering or disproving
the other charges which were brought against her.
Unprecedented, therefore, the course now adopted may
be admitted to have been. But it was the only
practicable one. The different minutes of the
cabinet, which the Prime-minister laid before the
King, established most conclusively the correctness
of their opinion that no impeachment for high-treason
could lie against her. She could not be an accomplice
in such an offence of one who, being a foreigner,
could not have committed it. It was equally impossible
for the King to sue for a divorce, as one of his subjects
might have done; because it was the established practice
of Parliament not to entertain a bill of divorce without
the judgment of the Ecclesiastical Court being previously
obtained and produced. And, under the circumstances,
to obtain from the Ecclesiastical Court such a sentence
as could alone lay the foundation for a bill of divorce
was clearly out of the question.
The case was a new and extraordinary
one, and, being such, could only be dealt with in
some new and extraordinary manner. And in all
such cases an appeal to Parliament seems the most,
if not the only, constitutional mode of solving the
difficulty. Where the existing laws are silent
or inapplicable, the most natural resource clearly
is, to go back to the fountain of all law; that is,
to the Parliament, which alone is competent to make
a new law. In one point of view the question may
seem unimportant, since we may well hope that no similar
case will ever arise to require the precedent now
set to be appealed to; but not unimportant, if it
in any way or degree contributes to establish the great
principle, that the solution of all matters of moment
to the state belongs to the Parliament alone:
a principle which, in its legitimate completeness,
carries with it a condemnation of many a modern association
whose object, whether avowed or disguised, is clearly
to supersede where it fails to intimidate the sole
constitutional Legislature.
The abandonment of the bill was naturally
hailed as a triumph by the Queen and her partisans;
but with the excitement of the struggle against the
government the interest taken in her case died away.
The next year, when she demanded to be crowned with
her husband, his refusal to admit her claim elicited
scarcely any sympathy for her under this renewed grievance;
in truth, it was one as to which precedent was unfavorable
to her demand. And the mortification at finding
herself already almost forgotten contributed to bring
on an illness of which she died in less than a year
after the termination of what was called her trial;
and in a short time both she and it were forgotten.
For the next few years the history
of the kingdom is one of progressive correction of
abuses or defects. The King paid visits to Ireland
and Scotland, parts of his dominions which his father
had never once visited, and in both was received with
the most exultant and apparently sincere acclamations.
And, though one great calamity fell on the ministry
in the loss of Lord Castlereagh who, in
a fit of derangement, brought on by the excitement
of overwork, unhappily laid violent hands on himself his
death, sad as it was, could not be said to weaken or
to affect the general policy of the cabinet.
Indeed, as he was replaced at the Foreign Office by
his old colleague and rival, Mr. Canning, in one point
of view the administration may be said to have been
strengthened by the change, since, as an orator, Canning
had confessedly no equal in either House of Parliament.
Another change was productive of still more practical
advantage. Lord Sidmouth retired from the Home
Office, and was succeeded by Mr. Peel, previously
Secretary for Ireland; and the transfer of that statesman
to an English office facilitated reforms, some of
which were as yet little anticipated even by the new
Secretary himself. The earliest of them, and
one not the least important in its bearing on the
well-doing of society, the mitigation of the severity
of our Criminal Code, was, indeed, but the following
up of a series of measures in the same direction which
had been commenced in the time of the Duke of Portland’s
second administration, and, it must be added, in spite
of its resistance. The influence of various trades,
and of the owners of different kinds of property,
pressing in turns upon our legislators, had rendered
our code the most sanguinary that had, probably, ever
existed in Christendom. Each class of proprietor
regarded only the preservation of his own property,
and had no belief in the efficacy of any kind of protection
for it, except such as arose from the fear of death;
nor any doubt that he was justified in procuring the
infliction of that penalty to avert the slightest loss
to himself. The consequence was that, at the
beginning of the present century, there were above
two hundred offences the perpetrators of which were
liable to capital punishment, some of a very trivial
character, such as cutting down a hop-vine in a Kentish
hop-garden, robbing a rabbit-warren or a fish-pond,
personating an out-pensioner of Greenwich Hospital,
or even being found on a high-road with a blackened
face, the intention to commit a crime being inferred
from the disguise, even though no overt act had been
committed. An act of Elizabeth made picking a
pocket a capital offence; another, passed as late
as the reign of William III., affixed the same penalty
to shop-lifting, even when the article stolen might
not exceed the value of five shillings. And the
fault of these enactments was not confined to their
unreasonable cruelty; they were as mischievous even
to those whom they were designed to protect as they
were absurd, as some owners began to perceive.
In the list of capital offences was that of stealing
linen from a bleaching-ground. And a large body
of bleachers presented a petition to Parliament entreating
the repeal of the statute which made it such on the
ground that, practically, it had been found not to
strike terror into the thieves, but almost to secure
them impunity from the reluctance of juries to find
a verdict which would sentence a fellow-creature to
the gallows for such an offence.
Nor was this by any means the only
instance in which the barbarity of the law defeated
its object. And its combined impolicy and inhumanity
had some years before attracted the notice of Sir Samuel
Romilly, who had been Solicitor-general in the administration
of 1806, and who, shortly after its dissolution, began
to apply himself to the benevolent object of procuring
the repeal of many of the statutes in question, and
in the course of a few years did succeed in obtaining
the substitution of milder penalties for several of
the less flagitious offences. He died in 1818;
but the work which he had began was continued by Sir
James Mackintosh, a man of even more conspicuous ability,
and one who could adduce his own experience in favor
of the changes which he recommended to the Parliament,
since he had filled the office of Recorder of Bombay
for eight years, and had discharged his duties with
a most diligent and consistent avoidance of capital
punishment, which he had never inflicted except for
murder; his lenity, previously unexampled in that land,
having been attended with a marked diminution of crime.
He procured the substitution of milder penalties in
several additional cases; and at last, in 1822, he
carried a resolution engaging the House of Commons
“the next session to take into its serious consideration
the means of increasing the efficacy of the criminal
law by abating its undue rigor.” And this
success had the effect of inducing the new minister
to take the question into his own hands. Peel
saw that it was one which, if it were to be dealt
with at all, ought to be regulated by the government
itself, and not be left to independent members, who
could not settle it with satisfactory completeness;
and therefore, in 1823, he introduced a series of
bills to carry out the principle implied in Mackintosh’s
resolution of the preceding year, not only simplifying
the law, but abolishing the infliction of capital
punishment in above a hundred cases. He was unable
to carry out his principle as fully as he could have
desired. The prejudice in favor of still retaining
death as a punishment for forgery was too strong for
even his resolution as yet to overbear, though many
private bankers supplied him with the same arguments
against it in their case which had formerly been alleged
by the bleachers. But the example which he now
set, enforced as it was with all the authority of
the government, was followed in many subsequent sessions,
till at last our code, instead of the most severe,
has become the most humane in Europe, and death is
now never inflicted except for murder, or crimes intended
or calculated to lead to murder. It is worth
remarking, however, that neither Romilly, Mackintosh,
nor Peel ever entertained the slightest doubt of the
right of a government to inflict capital punishment.
In the last address which Mackintosh delivered to
the grand-jury at Bombay he had said: “I
have no doubt of the right of society to inflict the
punishment of death on enormous crimes, wherever an
inferior punishment is not sufficient. I consider
it as a mere modification of the right of self-defence,
which may as justly be exercised in deterring from
attack as in repelling it." And in his diary,
when speaking of a death-warrant which he had just
signed, he says: “I never signed a paper
with more perfect tranquillity of mind. I felt
agitation in pronouncing the sentence, but none in
subscribing the warrant; I had no scruple of conscience
on either occasion.”
And it seems that his position is
unassailable. The party whose interest is to
be kept in view by the Legislature in imposing punishments
on offences is society, the people at large, not the
offender. The main object of punishment is to
deter rather than to reform; to prevent crime, not
to take vengeance on the criminal. And, if crime
be more effectually prevented by moderate than by
severe punishments, society has a right to demand,
for its own security (as a matter of policy, not of
justice), that the moderate punishment shall, on that
ground, be preferred. That punishments disproportioned
in their severity to the magnitude of the offence
often defeated their object was certain. Not
only had jurymen been known to confess that they had
preferred violating their oaths to doing still greater
violence to their consciences, by sending a man to
the gallows for a deed which, in their opinion, did
not deserve it, but the very persons who had been
injured by thefts or forgeries were often deterred
from prosecution of the guilty by the knowledge that
the forfeiture of their lives must follow their conviction.
It was almost equally certain that criminals calculated
beforehand on the chance of impunity which the known
prevalence of these feelings afforded them. Wherever
the sympathy of the public does not go along with
the law, it must, to a great extent, fail; and that
the terrible frequency of sanguinary punishment had
failed in all its objects, was proved by the fact
that, in spite of the numerous executions which took
place, crimes increased in a still greater proportion
than the population. Under the reformed system,
now first inaugurated on an extensive scale, crimes
have become rarer, detection and punishment more certain a
combination of results which must be the object equally
of the law-giver and the philanthropist.
It is not quite foreign to this subject
to relate that, a year or two before, a mode of trial
had been abolished which, though long disused, by
some curious oversight had still been allowed to remain
on the statute-book. In the feudal times either
the prosecutor or the prisoner, in cases of felony,
had a right to claim that the cause should be decided
by “wager of battle;” but it was an ordeal
which, with one exception in the reign of George II.,
had not been mentioned for centuries. In 1817,
however, the relatives of a woman who had been murdered,
being dissatisfied with the acquittal of a man who
had been indicted as her murderer, sued out “an
appeal of murder” against him, on which he claimed
to have the appeal decided by “wager of battle,”
and threw down a glove on the floor of the court to
make good his challenge. The claim was protested
against by the prosecutor; but Lord Ellenborough,
the Chief-justice, pronounced judgment that, “trial
by battle having been demanded, it was the legal and
constitutional mode of trial, and must be awarded.
It was the duty of the judges to pronounce the law
as it was, and not as they might wish it to be."
He gave sentence accordingly; and, had the two parties
been of equal stature and strength, the Judges of
the Common Pleas might have been seen, in their robes,
presiding from sunrise till sunset over a combat to
be fought, as the law prescribed, with stout staves
and leathern shields, till one should cry “Craven,”
and yield up the field. Fortunately for them,
the alleged murderer was so superior in bodily strength
to his adversary, that the latter declined the contest.
But the public advancement of the claim for such a
mode of decision was fatal to any subsequent exercise
of it; and, in spite of the Common Council of London,
who, confiding, perhaps, in the formidable appearance
presented by some of the City Champions on Lord Mayor’s
Day, petitioned Parliament to preserve it, the next
year the Attorney-general brought in a bill to abolish
it, and the judges were no longer compelled to pronounce
an absurd sentence in obedience to an obsolete law,
framed at a time when personal prowess was a virtue
to cover a multitude of sins, and might was the only
right generally acknowledged.
The foundation, too, was laid for
other reforms. Lord Liverpool was more thoroughly
versed than any of his predecessors, except Pitt, in
the soundest principles of political economy; and
in one of the first speeches which he made in the
new reign he expressed a decided condemnation, not
only of any regulations which were designed to favor
one trade or one interest at the expense of another,
but generally of the whole system and theory of protection;
and one of his last measures made an alteration in
the manner of taxing corn imported from foreign countries,
which was greatly to the advantage of the consumer.
It was known as the “sliding-scale,” the
tax on imported corn varying with the price in the
market, rising when the price fell, and falling when
it rose; the design with which it was framed being
to keep the price to the consumer at all times as
nearly equal as possible. At first, however, it
was vehemently denounced by the bulk of the agriculturists,
who were re-enforced on this occasion by a large party
from among the Whigs, and especially by some of those
connected with Ireland. But a more suitable period
for discussing the establishment of Free-trade as the
ruling principle of our financial policy will occur
hereafter.
The introduction of the sliding-scale
was almost the last act of Lord Liverpool’s
ministry. At the beginning of 1827 he was preparing
a fresh measure on the same subject, the effect of
which was intended to diminish still farther the protection
which the former act had given, and which was in consequence
denounced by many landholders of great wealth and
influence, led, on this subject, by the King’s
favorite brother, the Duke of York. But, a few
days after the meeting of Parliament, he was struck
down by an attack of paralysis, from which he never
recovered.
In his post as Prime-minister he was
succeeded by Canning, not without great reluctance
on the part of the King; not, probably, so much because
he feared to find in him any desire to depart from
the policy of Lord Liverpool, except on the Catholic
question (for even on matters of foreign policy, on
which Canning had always been supposed most to fix
his attention, he had adopted the line which Lord Liverpool
had laid down for the cabinet with evident sincerity),
as because his Majesty had never wholly forgiven him
for the attitude which he had taken, differing on
one or two points from that of his colleagues on the
Queen’s case. And, as has been mentioned
in a former chapter, he even, with the object of evading
the necessity of appointing him, suggested to the
Duke of Wellington the singular scheme of allowing
the remaining members of Lord Liverpool’s cabinet
to select their own chief, which the Duke, though
coinciding with him in his dislike of Canning, of
whom he entertained a very causeless suspicion, rejected
without hesitation, as an abandonment of the royal
prerogative in one of its most essential duties or
privileges. Another of his Majesty’s notions,
if it had been carried out, would have been one of
the strangest violations of constitutional principle
and practice which it is possible to conceive.
The Duke of York, who had for many years been Commander-in-chief,
died in January of the same year, and on his death
the King actually proposed to take that office on himself.
For the moment Lord Liverpool was able to induce him
to abandon the idea, and to confer the post on the
Duke of Wellington. But it had taken such possession
of his mind that he recurred to it again when, on Canning
becoming Prime-minister, the Duke resigned the office;
and he pressed it on the Cabinet with singular pertinacity
till, on Canning’s death, the Duke was prevailed
on to resume the command. It is evident that no
arrangement could possibly be more inconsistent with
every principle of the constitution. The very
foundation of parliamentary government is, that every
officer of every department is responsible to Parliament
for the proper discharge of his duties. But the
investiture of the sovereign with ministerial office
of any kind must involve either the entire withdrawal
of that department from parliamentary control, or the
exposure of the sovereign to constant criticism, which,
however essential to the efficiency of the department,
and consequently to the public service, would be wholly
inconsistent with the respect due to the crown.
The first alternative it is certain that no Parliament
would endure for a moment; the second, by impairing
the dignity of the monarch, could scarcely fail in
some degree to threaten the stability of the monarchy
itself.
Canning’s ministry was too brief
to give time for any transaction of internal importance.
That of Lord Goderich, who succeeded him, though longer
by the almanac, was practically briefer still, since
it never met Parliament at all, but was formed and
fell to pieces between the prorogation and the next
meeting of the Houses. But that which followed,
under the presidency of the Duke of Wellington, though
after a few months its composition became entirely
Tory, is memorable for the first great departure from
those maxims of the constitution which had been reckoned
among its most essential principles ever since the
Revolution. Of the measures which bear that character,
one was carried against the resistance of the ministry,
the other by the ministers themselves. And it
may at first sight appear singular that the larger
measure of the two was proposed by the Duke after
those members of his cabinet who had originally been
supposed to give it something of a Liberal complexion
had quitted it. The Reform Bill of 1832 to
which we shall come in the next chapter has
been often called a peaceful revolution. The
Toleration Acts, as we may call the bills of 1828 and
1829, are scarcely less deserving of that character.
The constitution, as it had existed
for the last hundred and forty years, had been not
only a Protestant but a Church of England constitution.
Not only all Roman Catholics, but all members of Protestant
Non-conforming sects, all who refused to sign a declaration
against the doctrine of Transubstantiation, and also
to take the Sacrament according to the rites of the
one Established Church, were disqualified for any
appointment of trust. That the object with which
the Test Act had been framed and supported was rather
political than religious is notorious; indeed, it
was supported by the Protestant Dissenters, though
they themselves were to suffer by its operation, so
greatly at that time did the dread of Popery and the
French King overpower every other consideration.
On the Roman Catholics, after the reign of James II.
had increased that apprehension, the restrictions
were tightened. But those which inflicted disabilities
on the Protestant Non-conformists had been gradually
relaxed. The repeal of two, the Five Mile and
the Conventicle Acts, had, as we have seen in the last
chapter, been recent measures of Lord Liverpool.
But the Test Act still remained, though it had long
been practically a dead letter. The Union with
Scotland, where the majority of the population was
Presbyterian, had rendered it almost impossible to
maintain the exclusion of Englishmen resembling the
Scotch in their religious tenets from preferments,
and even from seats in the House of Commons, to which
Scotchmen were admissible. And though one Prime-minister
(Stanhope) failed in his attempt to induce Parliament
to repeal the Test Act, and his successor (Walpole)
refused his countenance to any repetition of the proposal,
even he did not reject such a compromise as was devised
to evade it; and in the first year of George II.’s
reign (by which time it was notorious that many Protestant
Non-conformists had obtained seats in municipal corporations,
and even in the House of Commons, who yet had never
qualified themselves by compliance with the act of
1673) a bill of indemnity was introduced by the minister,
with at least the tacit consent of the English bishops,
to protect all such persons from the penalties which
they had incurred. And the bill, which was only
annual in its operation, was renewed almost every
year, till, in respect of all such places or dignities
(if a seat in the House of Commons can be described
by either of those names), no one thought of inquiring
whether a man, so long as he were a Protestant, adhered
to the Established Church or not; members of the House
of Commons even openly avowing their nonconformity,
and at times founding arguments on the fact.
The practical nullification of the
Test Act by these periodical bills of indemnity had
been for some time used by two opposite parties both
that which regarded the maintenance of the exclusive
connection of the constitution with the Church of
England as of vital importance to both Church and
constitution, and that which was opposed to all restrictions
or disqualiflcations on religious grounds as
an argument in their favor. The one contended
that there could be no sufficient reason for repealing
a law from which no one suffered; the other, that it
was a needless provocation of ill-feeling to retain
a law which no one ever dreamed of enforcing.
Hitherto the latter had been the weaker party.
One or two motions for the repeal of the Test Act,
which had been made in former years, had been
defeated without attracting any great notice; but
in the spring of 1828 Lord John Russel, then a comparatively
young member, but rapidly rising into influence with
his party, carried a motion in the House of Commons
for leave to bring in a bill to repeal the act, so
far as it concerned the Protestant Non-conformists,
by a very decisive majority, in spite of all the
efforts of Peel and his colleagues.
The ministry was placed in a difficult
position by his success, since the usual practice
for a cabinet defeated on a question of principle was
to resign; and it is probable that they would not have
departed from that rule now, had not this defeat occurred
so early in their official life. But on this
occasion it seemed to them that other questions had
to be considered besides the constitutional doctrine
of submission on the part of a ministry to the judgment
of the Parliament. Theirs was now the fourth
administration that had held office within twelve months;
and their resignation, which would compel the construction
of a fifth, could hardly fail not only to embarrass
the sovereign, but to shake public confidence in government
generally. It was also certain that they could
rely on a division in the House of Lords being favorable
to them, if they chose to appeal from one House to
the other. Under these circumstances, they had
to consider what their line of conduct should be,
and there never were two ministers better suited to
deal with an embarrassment of that kind than the Duke
of Wellington and Mr. Peel. The Duke’s
doctrine of government was that “the country
was never governed in practice according to the extreme
principles of any party whatever;" while Peel’s
disposition at all times inclined him to compromise.
He was quite aware that on this and similar questions
public feeling had undergone great alteration since
the beginning of the century. There was a large
and increasing party, numbering in its ranks many
men of deep religious feeling, and many firm supporters
of the principle of an Established Church, being also
sincere believers in the pre-eminent excellence of
the Church of England, who had a conscientious repugnance
to the employment of the most solemn ordinance of a
religion as a mere political test of a person’s
qualifications for the discharge of civil duties.
In the opinion of the Bishop of Oxford (Dr. Lloyd),
this was the feeling of “a very large majority
of the Church itself,” and of the University.
Peel, therefore, came to the conclusion to
which he had no difficulty in bringing his colleague,
the Prime-minister that “it might
be more for the real interests of the Church and of
religion to consent to an alteration in the law”
than to trust to the result of the debate in the House
of Lords to maintain the existing state of things.
Accordingly, after several conferences with the most
influential members of the Episcopal Bench, he framed
a declaration to be substituted for the Sacramental
test, binding all who should be required to subscribe
it a description which included all who
should be appointed to a civil or corporate office never
to exert any power or influence which they might thus
acquire to subvert, or to endeavor to subvert, the
Protestant Church of England, Scotland, or Ireland,
as by law established. The declaration was amended
in the House of Lords by the addition of the statement,
that this declaration was subscribed “on the
true faith of a Christian,” introduced at the
instigation of Lord Eldon, who had not held the Great
Seal since the dissolution of Lord Liverpool’s
administration, but who was still looked up to by
a numerous party as the foremost champion of sound
Protestantism in either House.
Not that the addition of these words
at all diminished the dissatisfaction with which the
great lawyer regarded the bill. On the contrary,
he believed it to be not only a weapon wilfully put
into the hands of the enemies of the Established Church,
but a violation of the constitution, of which, as
he regarded it “the existing securities were
a part.” He pointed out that “the
King himself was obliged to take the sacrament at
his coronation;” and he argued from this and
other grounds that “the Church of England, combined
with the state, formed together the constitution of
Great Britain; and that the acts now to be repealed
were necessary to the preservation of that constitution.”
With every respect for that great
lawyer, his argument on this point does not appear
sustainable. For the bill in question did not
sweep away securities for the Established Church,
but merely substituted, for one which long disuse
and indemnity had rendered wholly inoperative, a fresh
security, which, as it would be steadily put in force,
might fairly be expected to prove far more efficacious.
And it can hardly be contended that it was not within
the province of the Legislature to modify an existing
law in this spirit and with this object, however important
might be the purpose for which that law had originally
been framed. Nay, it might fairly be argued that
the more important that object was, the more were
they who strengthened the means of attaining that object
entitled to be regarded as faithful servants and supporters
of the principle of the constitution.
The measure, however, relieved the
Protestant Dissenters alone. Not only did Lord
Eldon’s amendment preserve the Christian character
of the Legislature, but the requirement to sign the
declaration against Transubstantiation, which was
unrepealed, left the Roman Catholics still under the
same disqualifications as before. But the
days of those disqualifications were manifestly
numbered. Indeed, many of those who had followed
the ministers in their original resistance to the repeal
of the Test Act had been avowedly influenced by the
conviction that it could not fail to draw after it
the removal of the disabilities affecting the Roman
Catholics. As has been said before, the disabilities
in question had originally been imposed on the Roman
Catholics on political rather than on religious grounds.
And the political reasons for them had been greatly
weakened, if not wholly swept away, by the extinction
of the Stuart line of princes. Their retention
or removal had, therefore, now become almost wholly
a religious question; and the late bill had clearly
established as a principle that, though the state
had a right to require of members of other religious
sects that they should not abuse the power which might
arise from any positions or employments to which they
might be admitted, to the subversion or injury of
the Established Church of England, yet, when security
for their innocuousness in this respect was provided,
it was not justified in inquiring into the details
of their faith. And if this were to be the rule
of government for the future, the conclusion was irresistible
that a similar security was all that the state was
justified in demanding from Roman Catholics, and that
it could have no warrant for investigating their opinion
on Transubstantiation, or any other purely theological
tenet. There could be no doubt that the feelings
of the public had been gradually and steadily coming
round to this view of the question. The last
House of Commons had not only passed a bill to remove
Roman Catholic disabilities (which was afterward thrown
out in the House of Lords), but had also passed, by
a still larger majority, a resolution, moved by Lord
Francis Leveson Gower (who was now the Secretary for
Ireland), in favor of endowing the Roman Catholic priests
in Ireland. And at the late general election the
opinions of the candidates on what was commonly called
Catholic Emancipation had been the great cardinal
question with a great number, probably a majority,
of the constituencies.
It may be remarked that it was not
the Test Act which excluded Roman Catholics from Parliament,
but a bill which, fifteen years later, had been passed
(probably under the influence of Lord Shaftesbury)
at the time when the whole kingdom was excited by
the daily expanding revelations of the Popish Plot.
And this bill had a loop-hole which was never discovered
till now but the discovery of which totally changed
the whole aspect of the question. Even before
the bill repealing the Test Act had passed through
all its stages, Sir Francis Burdett had again induced
the House of Commons to pass a resolution condemning
the continuance of the Roman Catholic disabilities;
to which, however, the peers, by a far larger majority,
refused their concurrence. But, within a month
of this division, the aspect of the whole question
was changed by the shrewdness of an Irish barrister,
who had discovered the loop-hole or flaw in the bill
of 1678 already alluded to, and by the energy and
promptitude with which he availed himself of his discovery.
Mr. O’Connell had a professional reputation scarcely
surpassed by any member of the Irish Bar. He
was also a man of ancient family in the county of
Kerry. And, being a Roman Catholic, he had for
several years been the spokesman of his brother Roman
Catholics on most public occasions. He now, on
examination of the bill of 1678, perceived that, though
it forbade any Roman Catholic from taking a seat in
either House of Parliament, it contained no prohibition
to prevent any constituency from electing him its
representative. And when, on the occasion of some
changes which were made in the cabinet, the representation
of the County Clare was vacated by its member, Mr.
Vesey Fitzgerald, accepting the office of President
of the Board of Trade, O’Connell instantly offered
himself as a candidate in opposition to the new minister,
who, of course, sought re-election.
Mr. Fitzgerald was a man who had always
supported the demands of the Roman Catholics; he was
also personally popular, and had the undivided support
of nearly all the gentlemen and principal land-owners
of the county, in which he himself had large property.
But O’Connell’s cause was taken up by
the entire Roman Catholic priesthood; addresses in
his favor were read at the altars of the different
churches; and, after five days’ polling, Mr.
Fitzgerald withdrew from the contest. The Sheriff,
in great perplexity, made a special return, reporting
that “Mr. Fitzgerald was proposed, being a Protestant,
as a fit person to represent the county in Parliament;
that Mr. O’Connell, a Roman Catholic, was also
proposed; that he, Mr. O’Connell, had declared
before the Sheriff that he was a Roman Catholic, and
intended to continue a Roman Catholic; and that a
protest had been made by several electors against his
return.”
It was accepted as a return of O’Connell,
who, however, made no attempt to take his seat, though
when he first stood he had assured the electors that
there was no law to prevent him from doing so; but
the importance of his success was not to be measured
by his actual presence or absence in the House of
Commons for the remainder of a session. It had
made it absolutely impossible to continue the maintenance
of the disabilities; what one Irish constituency had
done, other Irish constituencies might be depended
on to do. And it was quite certain that, as opportunity
offered, almost every constituency in Munster and Connaught,
and many in Leinster, would follow the example of
Clare, and return Roman Catholic representatives;
while to retain a law which prevented forty or fifty
men duly elected by Irish constituencies from taking
their seats must have appeared impossible to all but
a few, whom respect for the undoubted sincerity of
their attachment to their own religion and to the
constitution, as they understood it, is the only consideration
which can save them from being regarded as dangerous
fanatics. At all events, the ministers were not
among them. And the Duke of Wellington, though
he had previously hoped, by postponing the farther
consideration of the question for a year or two, to
gain time for a calmer examination of it when the
existing excitement had cooled down, at once admitted
the conviction that the result of the Clare election
had rendered farther delay impossible. In his
view, and that of those of his colleagues whose judgment
he estimated most highly, the Irish constituencies
and their probable action at future elections were
not the only parties whose opinions or feelings must
be regarded by a responsible statesman; but to them
must be added the constituencies of the larger island
also, since, while, to quote the language of Mr. Peel,
“the general election of 1826 had taken place
under circumstances especially calculated to call forth
the manifestation of Protestant feeling throughout
the country,” they had returned a majority of
members in favor of concession, as was proved by the
recent division on Sir F. Burdett’s motion.
Moreover, apart from the merits or demerits of concession,
taken by itself, there was a manifest danger that
the keeping up of the excitement on the subject by
a continued adherence to the policy of restriction
might, especially among such a people as the Irish,
so impulsive, and, in the lower classes, so absolutely
under the dominion of the priests, kindle an excitement
on other subjects also, still more difficult to deal
with. It was even already certain that the Roman
Catholic priests were endeavoring to tamper with the
loyalty of the soldiers of their persuasion.
Nor was it clerical influence alone that the government
had to dread. A year or two before a Catholic
Association had been formed, which included among
its members all the wealthiest and ablest of the Roman
Catholic laymen, noblemen, squires, and barristers.
Its organization had been so skilfully conducted,
and all its measures had been so carefully kept within
the requirements of the law, that the crown lawyers,
on being consulted, pronounced it impossible to interfere
with it; and, by what may be called a peaceful agitation,
it had attained such extraordinary power over the
minds of the bulk of the Roman Catholics, that the
Lord-lieutenant reported that “he was quite
certain that they could lead on the people to open
rebellion at a moment’s notice, and that their
organization was such that, in the hands of desperate
and intelligent leaders, they would be extremely formidable.”
Under all these circumstances, the
Duke had no hesitation in deciding that it had become
absolutely necessary to concede the demands of the
Roman Catholics and their supporters for a removal
of their political disabilities. And it was equally
obvious that, the more promptly the concession was
made, the more gracious it would seem, and the greater
was the probability of its having the conciliatory
and tranquillizing effect the hope of which made it
so desirable. He was not a man to lose time when
he had once made up his mind. It was already too
late in the session for anything to be done in 1828;
but the Parliament had scarcely been prorogued before
he put his views on the subject before the King, and
began, in concert with the Home-secretary, to frame
a bill such as he hoped might settle the long-agitated
question, without doing more violence than was necessary
to the feelings of those whose opposition or reluctance
he was aware he should have to encounter: among
whom was the King himself, who, though thirty years
before he had, with an ostentation rather unbecoming,
considering his position, put himself forward as an
advocate of Emancipation, had subsequently changed
his opinion, and had recently taken more than one
occasion to declare that he had never doubted that,
as the head and protector of the Protestant religion,
he was bound to refuse his assent to any relaxation
of the existing law. The Duke, however, was too
well acquainted with his royal master’s character
to apprehend any real firmness of resistance from
him; but he knew that a great majority of the clergy,
and no small portion of the country gentlemen, were
conscientiously and immovably fixed in opposition
to any concession at all, some refusing to regard
the question in any but a purely religious light, and
objecting to associate in the task of legislation
for those whom they regarded as adherents of an idolatrous
superstition; while those who mingled political reasoning
with that founded on theology dwelt also on the danger
to be apprehended to the state, if political power
were given to those whose allegiance to the King was
divided with another allegiance which they acknowledged
to a foreign prelate. And he had presently an
unmistakable proof afforded him how great was the strength
of this party in the country. Peel was one of
the representatives of the University of Oxford; and,
as from his earliest enjoyment of a seat in Parliament
he had been a prominent opponent of the Roman Catholic
claims, he considered that it was to that maintenance
of a policy identified in their eyes with that Protestant
ascendency which his supporters took to be both the
chief bulwark and one of the most essential parts of
the constitution that he owed his position as their
member. With a conscientiousness which was rather
overstrained, and not quite consistent with the legitimate
position of a member of the House of Commons as a
representative, and not a delegate, he now conceived
that his change of view on the subject made it proper
for him to give his constituents an opportunity of
making choice of some one else who should more faithfully
represent them. He accordingly resigned his seat,
offering himself at the same time for re-election.
But he was defeated by a very large majority, though
his competitor was one who could not possibly be put
on a level with him either for university distinction
or for parliamentary eminence.
Not the less, however, for all their
difficulties and discouragements, did the ministers
proceed in the course on which they had resolved.
They inserted in the speech with which the King opened
the session of 1829 a recommendation to the Houses
“to take into consideration the whole condition
of Ireland, and to review the laws which imposed civil
disabilities on his Majesty’s Roman Catholic
subjects.” And with as little delay as
possible they introduced a bill to remove those disabilities.
But there was another measure which they felt it to
be indispensable should precede it. A previous
sentence of the royal speech had described the Catholic
Association as one “dangerous to the public
peace, and inconsistent with the spirit of the constitution,
keeping alive discord and ill-will among his Majesty’s
subjects, and one which must, if permitted to continue,
effectually obstruct every effort permanently to improve
the condition of Ireland.” And the ministers
naturally regarded it as their first duty to suppress
a body which could deserve to be so described.
They felt, too, that the large measure of concession
and conciliation which they were about to announce
would lose half its grace, and more than half its
effect, if it could possibly be represented as a submission
to an agitation and intimidation which they had not
the power nor the courage to resist. They determined,
therefore, to render such an imputation impossible,
by previously suppressing the Association. It
was evident that it could not be extinguished by any
means short of an act of Parliament. And the course
pursued, with the discussions which took place respecting
it, show in a very clear and instructive manner the
view taken by statesmen of the difference between
what is loyal or illegal, constitutional or unconstitutional;
their apprehension that conduct may be entirely legal,
that is to say, within the letter of the law, but
at the same time perfectly unconstitutional, outside
of and adverse to the whole spirit of the constitution.
The royal speech had not ventured to describe the
Association as illegal. The Duke of Wellington
expressly admitted that “in the original institution
and formation of the society there was nothing strictly
illegal." And its founder and chief, Mr. O’Connell,
had been at all times careful to inculcate on his
followers the necessity of avoiding any violation
of the law. But the speech had also declared the
association to be “inconsistent with the spirit
of the constitution.” And its acts, as
the Duke proceeded to describe them, certainly bore
out that declaration. “Those acts consisted
principally in levying a tax upon certain of his Majesty’s
subjects called Catholic rent, and this by means and
acts of extreme violence; by appointing persons to
collect these rents; and farther by adopting measures
to organize the Catholic population; by appointing
persons to superintend that organization; and by assuming
to themselves the government of the country; and, still
more, affecting to assume it. Besides, they expended
this rent in a manner contrary to, and utterly inconsistent
with, all law and order and the constitution of the
country.” No member of either House denied
the accuracy of this description of the Association’s
proceedings. And if it were correct, it was incontrovertible
that the denunciation of it as an utterly unconstitutional
body was not too strong. Indeed, the fact of
its “levying a tax” upon a portion of the
King’s subjects (to say nothing of the intimidation,
amounting to compulsion, by which, as was notorious,
it was in many instances exacted) was the assumption
of one of the most important functions of the Imperial
Parliament; it was the erection of an imperium
in imperio, which no statesmen intrusted with
the government of a country can be justified in tolerating.
And this was felt by the Opposition as well as by
the ministers; by the Whigs as fully as by the Tories.
The most eloquent of the Whig party, Mr. Stanley,
was as decided as Mr. Peel himself in affirming that
the existence of the Association was “inconsistent
with the spirit of the constitution,” and that
it was “dangerous that the people of a country
should look up to any public body distinct from the
government, opposed to the government, and monopolizing
their attachment and obedience."
It was, therefore, with the almost
unanimous approval of both parties that the bill framed
for the suppression of the Association was received.
The framing of such a bill was not unattended by difficulties,
as Peel acknowledged, since “no one wished
to declare that every political meeting was illegal;”
while at the same time it was necessary to guard against
“having its enactments evaded, since a more dangerous
precedent than the successful evasion of acts of the
Legislature could scarcely be conceived.”
But the measure, as it was proposed, skilfully steered
clear of these difficulties. It met them by intrusting
“the enforcement of the law to be enacted to
one person alone.” The bill proposed “to
give to the Lord-lieutenant, and to him alone, the
power of suppressing any association or meeting which
he might think dangerous to the public peace, or inconsistent
with the due administration of the law; together with
power to interdict the assembly of any meeting of
which previous notice should have been given, and which
he should think likely to endanger the public peace,
or to prove inconsistent with the due administration
of the law.” And farther, “to interdict
any meeting or association which might be interdicted
from assembling, or which might be suppressed under
this act, from receiving and placing at their control
any moneys by the name of rent, or any other name.”
But the act was not to be one of perpetual duration.
It could not be concealed that such a prohibition
or limitation of the general right of public meeting
and public discussion was a suspension of a part of
the constitution; and therefore the ministers were
content to limit its operation “to one year
and the end of the then next session of Parliament,”
feeling “satisfied that there would be no objection
to continue it, if there should be any necessity for
its continuance.” And this limitation was
a substantial mitigation of its severity. It
made the bill, as Mr. Stanley correctly described
it, “not a permanent infringement on the constitution,
but a temporary deviation from it, giving those powers
which were necessary at the moment,” but not
maintaining them an hour longer than they were necessary.
And this seems to be the course most
in accordance with the spirit of the constitution,
with former practice, with common-sense. Deeds
which violate the letter of the law can be dealt with
by the law. But actions or courses of action
which, even if they may be thought to overstep the
law, transgress it so narrowly as to elude conviction,
can only be reached by enactments which also go in
some degree beyond the ordinary law; and, so going
beyond it, are to that extent encroachments on the
ordinary privileges and rights of the subject, and
suspensions of the constitution. But the very
term “suspension” shows that the power
conferred is but temporary, otherwise it would be synonymous
with abrogation. And all parties may wisely agree,
as they did in this instance, to a temporary suspension
of the people’s rights, though there would be
none to whom their permanent abrogation would not be
intolerable.
The bill, then, for the suppression
of the Association passed with universal approval,
and it may be regarded as furnishing a model for dealing
with similar associations, if ever they should arise.
And as soon as it was passed Mr. Peel introduced the
greater measure, that for the repeal of the disabilities.
In drawing the necessary bill the ministers had had
two questions of special importance to consider:
firstly, whether it should be unlimited concession
which should be granted, such as would throw open
to the Roman Catholics every kind of civil office;
and, secondly, whether it should be accompanied by
any other measure, which might render it more palatable
to its adversaries, as diminishing a portion at least
of the dangers which those who regarded the question
in a purely political light most apprehended.
On the first point it was determined that, with the
exception of three civil offices, those of the Lord
Chancellors of England and Ireland and the Lord-lieutenant
of Ireland, and some of a purely ecclesiastical
character, such as the Judge of the Court of Arches,
every kind of preferment should be opened to the Roman
Catholics. The declaration against Transubstantiation
and the oath of supremacy, certain expressions in
which were the obstacles which had hitherto kept the
Roman Catholics out of office and out of Parliament,
were to be repealed, and another to be substituted
for them which should merely bind him who took it
to defend the King, to maintain the Protestant succession,
and to declare that “it was not an article of
his faith, and that he renounced, rejected, and abjured
the opinion, that princes excommunicated or deposed
by the Pope might be deposed and murdered; and that
he disclaimed, disavowed, and solemnly abjured any
intention to subvert the present Church Establishment
as settled by law within this realm, and that he would
never exercise any privilege to which he was or might
become entitled to disturb or weaken the Protestant
religion or Protestant government in this kingdom."
The second question was, it will probably
be confessed, even more important. Pitt, who
had always contemplated, and had encouraged the Irish
Roman Catholics to contemplate, the abolition of their
political disabilities as an indispensable appendage
to, or, it may be said, part of the Union, had designed,
farther, not to confine his benefits to the laymen,
but to endow the Roman Catholic clergy with adequate
stipends, a proposal which was received with the greatest
thankfulness, not only by the Irish prelates and clergy
themselves, but also by the heads of their Church
at Rome, who were willing, in return, to give the crown
a veto on all the ecclesiastical appointments of their
Church in the two islands. The justice of granting
such an endowment could hardly be contested.
The Reformation in Ireland, if what had taken place
there could be called a reformation at all, had been
wholly different from the movement which had almost
extinguished Popery in England. The great majority
of the Irish people had never ceased to adhere to the
Romish forms, and the Reformation there had been simply
a transfer of the property of the Romish Church to
the Church of England, unaccompanied by any corresponding
change of belief in the people, who had an undeniable
right to claim that the state, while making this transfer,
should not deprive of all provision the clergy to
whose ministrations they still clung with a zeal and
steadiness augmented rather than diminished by the
discouragements under which they adhered to them.
The policy of granting such endowment
was equally conspicuous. No measure could so
bind the clergy to the government; and no such security
for the loyalty and peaceful, orderly behavior of the
poorer classes could be provided, as might be expected
from the attachment to the government of those who
had over them an influence so powerful in its character
and so unbounded in its strength as their priests.
And the Duke of Wellington, who had at one time been
himself the Irish Secretary, and, as an intimate friend
of Lord Castlereagh, who held that office at the time
of the Union, had a perfect knowledge of what had
been intended at that time and who was,
of course, aware of the very decided favor which the
House of Commons had so lately shown to the project proposed
to follow out Pitt’s plan in that particular,
and to connect a provision for the Roman Catholic
clergy with the removal of their political disabilities
from the laymen. Unluckily, Peel, who, throughout
the whole transaction, was, of all the cabinet, the
counsellor on whose judgment he most relied, took a
different view of the expediency of making such a
provision, having, indeed, “no objection to
it in point of principle.” But he saw many
practical difficulties, which he pressed on the Duke
with great earnestness. He argued that for the
government “to apply a sum of money to the payment
of the ministers of the Church of Rome in Ireland,
granting a license for the performance of their spiritual
functions, would be a virtual and complete supersession,
if not repeal, of the laws which prohibit intercourse
with Rome;” and asked, “Could the state
affect to be ignorant that the bishop whom it paid
derived his right to be a bishop from the See of Rome?”
Another difficulty he found in the apprehension that
“the admission of the right of the Roman Catholic
clergy to an endowment might produce similar claims
on the part of the Dissenters in England, who contribute
in like manner to the support of their own religion
and of the established religion also.”
He suggested, farther, that, if the Roman Catholic
priest were allowed, in addition to his stipend, “to
receive dues, Easter offerings, etc., from his
parishioners, his condition would then be better than
that of the ministers of the Established Church in
many of the parishes in Ireland.” And, finally,
he urged the practical objection, that the endowment
would greatly strengthen the opposition to the whole
measure, by the reluctance which, “on purely
religious grounds,” many would feel to the endowment
of the Roman Catholic faith, who would yet be inclined
to acquiesce in the removal of the disabilities, “on
grounds rather political than religious.”
He was “not insensible to the importance of
establishing some bond of connection between the Roman
Catholic clergy and the state;” but he believed
that the omission of a provision for their endowment
“was important to the ultimate success of the
government in proposing the measure before them.”
It is not probable that the Duke was
greatly influenced by the first, or what may be called
the constitutional, objection that any concert
with the Papal Court with respect to the appointments
or endowments of its clergy would be a violation of
the act which prohibited any intercourse with Rome.
The removal of the disabilities required the repeal
of one act of Parliament; and, if the holding communications
with Rome on the subject of clerical appointments
should be so construed as to require the repeal of
another, it would hardly seem that there could be any
greater violation of or departure from the principles
of the constitution in repealing two acts than in
repealing one. As to the second of Peel’s
objections, the English Dissenters could not possibly
be said to stand on the same ground as the Irish Roman
Catholics, since their ministers had certainly never
been deprived by any act of the state of any provision
which they had previously enjoyed; but their position
as unendowed ministers was clearly one of their own
making. The possible inferiority in point of
emolument of some of the Protestant cures in Ireland
to that which might be enjoyed by some of the Roman
Catholic clergy could hardly be regarded as the foundation
of any argument at all, since no law had ever undertaken,
or ever could undertake, to give at all times and
under all circumstances equal remuneration to equal
labors. But the consideration last suggested was
exactly the one to influence such a mind as that of
the Duke of Wellington, generally contented to deal
with a present difficulty. He was determined
to carry Emancipation, because he saw that the Clare
election had made it impossible to withhold or even
to delay it; and, being so determined, he was desirous
to avoid encumbering it with any addition which might
increase the opposition to it. At the same time
he was far from being sanguine of its effect, “with
whatever guards or securities it might be accompanied,
to pacify the country or to avert rebellion,"
which, in his apprehension, was undoubtedly impending;
and, under the influence of these combined feelings,
he eventually withdrew that clause from the bill.
It was accompanied by another bill, disfranchising
the forty-shilling freeholders in Ireland. They
were a class of voters sunk in the deepest poverty,
and such as certainly could not well be supposed capable
of forming, much less of exercising, an independent
judgment on political matters. Yet this bill is
remarkable as having been the only enactment passed
since the Revolution to narrow the franchise.
It had no opposition to anticipate from English or
Scotch members, and was accepted by the Irish members
as the price of Emancipation.
No measure that had ever been framed
since the Revolution had caused such excitement in
the country; but the preponderance of feeling in its
favor was equally marked in both Houses of Parliament.
In the House of Commons 320 supported it, while only
142 could be marshalled against it. In the House
of Lords 213 divided for it against 109. And in
April it received the royal assent.
The general policy of removing the
disabilities it is not necessary to discuss here.
It is quite clear that the Clare election had rendered
it impossible to maintain them. And if some of
those who judge of measures solely by their effects
still denounce this act, as one which has failed in
its object of tranquillizing Ireland, many of those
who admit the failure ascribe it to the omission to
accompany it by one securing a state endowment for
the Roman Catholic clergy, pronouncing it, without
that appendage, a half measure, such as rarely succeeds,
and never deserves success. However that may
be, it is certain that the measure, coupled with the
repeal of the Test Act of the previous year, was one
which made a great and permanent change in the practical
working of the constitution of the kingdom, as it
had been interpreted for the last one hundred and
fifty years. Of that constitution one of the leading
features, ever since the Restoration, had been understood
to be the establishment and maintenance of the political
as well as the ecclesiastical ascendency of the Church
of England. On that ascendency the repeal of
the Test Act in 1828 had made the first, and that a
great, inroad, and the present statute entirely abolished
it as a principle of government. So far as political
privileges went, every Christian sect was now placed
on a footing of complete equality. But so to place
them may fairly be regarded as having been required
not only by justice and expediency, but by reasons
drawn from the history of the nation and from the
circumstances under which these disabilities had been
imposed. Before the Rebellion no one was excluded
from the English Parliament on account of his religion,
whether he was a Roman Catholic, a Presbyterian, or
a member of any other of the various sects which were
gradually arising in the country. It was not till
after the Restoration that a recollection of the crimes
of the Puritans, when they had got the upper-hand,
and the fear of machinations and intrigues, incompatible
with the freedom and independence of the people, which
were imputed to the Roman Catholics, gave birth to
the statutes depriving both Protestant and Roman Catholic
Non-conformists of all legislative and political power.
The restrictions thus imposed on the Presbyterians
and other Protestant sects had, as we have seen, been
gradually relaxed by a periodical act of indemnity.
Indeed, after the Union with Scotland, it was impossible
with any show of consistency to maintain them, since,
as it has been already pointed out, after Presbyterianism
had been recognized as the established religion of
Scotland, it would have seemed strangely unreasonable
to regard it as a disqualification on the southern
side of the Border. But, as long as the Stuart
princes were from time to time disquieting the government
by their open invasions or secret intrigues, no such
relaxation could with safety be granted to the Roman
Catholics, since it could hardly be expected that they
would forbear to employ any power which they might
acquire for the service of a prince of their own religion.
That danger, however, which ever since 1745 had been
a very shadowy one, had wholly passed away with the
life of the last Stuart lay prince, Charles Edward;
and his death left the rulers of the kingdom and advisers
of the sovereign free to take a different and larger
view of their duty to the nation as a whole.
It was notorious that the number of
Non-conformists was large. In the middle of the
last century it had received a considerable accession
through the institution of the new sect of Wesleyan
Methodists; which, through the supineness of the clergy
of the Established Church in that generation, had
gradually increased, till it was estimated that the
various Dissenting sects in England equalled at least
half the number of the members of the Established
Church. In Wales they were believed to form the
majority. In Scotland three-fourths of the people
were Presbyterians; and in Ireland the Roman Catholics
outnumbered the Protestants in nearly the same proportion.
Taking England, Wales, Scotland, and Ireland together,
a calculation which reckoned the different sects of
Protestant and Roman Catholic Non-conformists united
at half the entire population would probably not have
erred very widely from the truth.
It must have been the aim of every
statesman deserving of the name to weld these different
religious parties into one harmonious whole, as far
as their civil position went. And measures which
had that tendency could not be foreign to the constitution,
properly understood. A constitution which confines
its benefits to one-half of a nation hardly merits
the title of a constitution at all. For every
constitution ought to extend its protection and its
privileges equally to every portion of the people,
unless there be some peculiarity in the principles
or habits of any one portion which makes its participation
in them dangerous to the rest. It had undoubtedly
been the doctrine of Pitt, and of the greater part
of those who since his time had held the reins of government,
that if any portion of the King’s subjects did
cherish a temper dangerous to the rest, it was because
they were debarred from privileges to which they conceived
themselves to have a just right, and that their discontent
and turbulence were the fruit of the restrictions imposed
on them. In proposing to remove such a grievance
Pitt certainly conceived himself to be acting in accordance
with the strictest principles of the constitution,
and not so much innovating upon it as restoring it
to its original comprehensiveness. And so of
the measure, as it was now carried, it will apparently
be correct to say that, though it did make an important
change in the practical working of the constitution,
it made it only by reverting to the fundamental principles
of civil and religious liberty, to which every subject
had a right; which had only been temporarily restrained
under the apprehension of danger to the state, and
which the cessation of that apprehension made it a
duty to re-establish in all their fulness.
But it is by no means clear that in
the conduct of the measure the constitution was not
violated in one very important point, the proper relation
subsisting between a constituency and its representative,
by Mr. Peel’s resignation of his seat for the
University of Oxford. That he was sensible that
the act stood in need of explanation is proved by the
careful statement of the motives and considerations
that determined him to it, which he drew up twenty
years afterward. They were of a twofold character.
To quote his own words: “When I resolved
to advise, and to promote to the utmost of my power,
the settlement of that question, I resolved at the
same time to relinquish, not only my official station,
but the representation of the University of Oxford.
I thought that such decisive proofs that I could have
no object, political or personal, in taking a course
different from that which I had previously taken,
would add to my influence and authority, so far, at
least, as the adjustment of the particular question
at issue was concerned.” “I cannot
deny that in vacating my seat I was acting upon the
impulse of private feelings, rather than upon a dispassionate
consideration of the constitutional relations between
a representative and his constituents. I will
not seek to defend the resolution to which I came
by arguments drawn from the peculiar character of the
academic body, or from the special nature of the trust
confided to its members; still less will I contend
that my example ought to be followed by others to
whom may be offered the same painful alternative of
disregarding the dictates of their own consciences,
or of acting in opposition to the opinions and disappointing
the expectations of their constituents. I will
say no more than that my position was a very peculiar
one, that I had many painful sacrifices to make, and
that it would have been a great aggravation of them,
if it could have said with truth that I was exercising
an authority derived from the confidence of the University
to promote measures injurious, in her deliberate judgment,
either to her own interests or to those of the Church.”
No one would willingly censure too
severely an act dictated by a sense of honor, even
if somewhat overstrained and too scrupulously delicate;
but when Mr. Peel speaks of “defending”
or not defending his deed, he clearly admits it to
be one open to impeachment. And when he forbears
to “contend that his example ought to be followed,”
he seems practically to confess a consciousness that
any defence against such impeachment must fail; while
the last sentence quoted above involves an assertion
that a constituency (in this instance one of the two
most important constituencies in the kingdom) could
be justified in regarding a measure required by the
safety, or at least by the welfare, of the state, as
injurious to its own interests; and so far admits a
possible severance between the interests of a particular
class or body and those of the whole community, which
can have no real existence. That, however, is
not the point to be investigated here. The charge,
as it seems, to which Mr. Peel’s deed lays him
open is, that by it he lowered the position and character
of a member of Parliament from those of a representative
to those of a delegate. It was an adoption of
the principle laid down for his own guidance by a
colleague of Mr. Burke above fifty years before, and
indignantly repudiated by that great political philosopher,
as proceeding from an entire misapprehension of the
rights of a constituency and of a member of Parliament.
He told the electors of Bristol that “when they
had chosen their member, he was not a member of Bristol,
but a member of Parliament; and that if the local constituent
should have an interest, or should form an opinion,
evidently opposite to the real good of the rest of
the community, the member for that place ought to
be as far as any other from any endeavor to give it
effect;” that a representative “owes to
his constituents, not his industry only, but his judgment,
and betrays instead of serving them, if he sacrifices
it to their opinion.” And in so saying he
carried with him the concurrence and approval of all
his contemporaries whose sentiments on such a question
were entitled to weight.
In the States-general of France each
member was, by the original constitution of that body,
a delegate, and not a representative. He could
not even remonstrate against the most oppressive grievance
of which the previous instructions of the constituent
body had not instructed him to complain; and this
limitation of his duties and powers was, undoubtedly,
one very principal cause which led to the States-general
so rapidly falling into utter disrepute. It was
no light thing to take a step which had a tendency
to bring down the British Parliament to the level
of the despised and long-disused States-general.
And it is the more necessary to put the case in a clear
and true light, because at the present day there is
an evident disposition on the part of constituencies
to avail themselves of Peel’s conduct in this
instance as a precedent, in spite of his protest against
its being so regarded, and to fetter their representatives
with precise instructions; and a corresponding willingness
on the part of candidates to purchase support at elections
by a submissive giving of pledges on a variety of subjects,
so numerous as to leave themselves no freedom of judgment
at all. On the great majority of subjects which
come before Parliament, a member of Parliament, if
he be a sensible and an honest man, has a far better
opportunity of obtaining correct information and forming
a sound opinion than can be within reach of any constituency,
whose proneness to misjudge is usually in exact proportion
to the magnitude of its numbers. Every elector
justifiably may, and naturally will, seek to ascertain
that between the candidate whom he supports and himself
there is a general conformity of opinion; an absolute
identity he will never find, and he has no right to
ask.