In his deeply-interesting Romanes
lecture, Professor Huxley has stated the opinion that
the ethical progress of society depends upon our combating
the “cosmic process” which we call the
struggle for existence. Since, as he adds, we
inherit the “cosmic nature” which is the
outcome of millions of years of severe training, it
follows that the “ethical nature” may
count upon having to reckon with a tenacious and powerful
enemy as long as the world lasts. This is not
a cheerful prospect. It is, as he admits, an
audacious proposal to pit the microcosm against the
macrocosm. We cannot help fearing that the microcosm
may get the worst of it. Professor Huxley has
not fully expanded his meaning, and says much to which
I could cordially subscribe. But I think that
the facts upon which he relies admit or require an
interpretation which avoids the awkward conclusion.
Pain and suffering, as Professor Huxley
tells us, are always with us, and even increase in
quantity and intensity as evolution advances.
The fact had been recognised in remote ages long before
theories of evolution had taken their modern form.
Pessimism, from the time of the ancient Hindoo philosophers
to the time of their disciple, Schopenhauer, has been
in no want of evidence to support its melancholy conclusions.
It would be idle to waste rhetoric in the attempt to
recapitulate so familiar a position. Though I
am not a pessimist, I cannot doubt that there is more
plausibility in the doctrine than I could wish.
Moreover, it may be granted that any attempt to explain
or to justify the existence of evil is undeniably
futile. It is not so much that the problem cannot
be answered, as that it cannot even be asked in any
intelligible sense. To “explain” a
fact is to assign its causes that is, to
give the preceding set of facts out of which it arose.
However far we might go backwards, we should get no
nearer to perceiving any reason for the original fact.
If we explain the fall of man by Adam’s eating
the apple, we are quite unable to say why the apple
should have been created. If we could discover
a general theory of pain, showing, say, that it implied
certain physiological conditions, we shall be no nearer
to knowing why those physiological conditions should
have been what they are. The existence of pain,
in short, is one of the primary data of our problem,
not one of the accidents, for which we can hope in
any intelligible sense to account. To give any
“justification” is equally impossible.
The book of Job really suggests an impossible, one
may almost say a meaningless, problem. We can
give an intelligible meaning to a demand for justice
when we can suppose that a man has certain antecedent
rights, which another man may respect or neglect.
But this has no meaning as between the abstraction
“nature” and the concrete facts which are
themselves nature. It is unjust to meet equal
claims differently. But it is not “unjust”
in any intelligible sense that one being should be
a monkey and another a man, any more than that part
of me should be a hand and another head. The
question would only arise if we supposed that the man
and the monkey had existed before they were created,
and had then possessed claims to equal treatment.
The most logical theologians, indeed, admit that as
between creature and creator there can be properly
no question of justice. The pot and the potter
cannot complain of each other. If the writer
of Job had been able to show that the virtuous were
rewarded and the vicious punished, he would only have
transferred the problem to another issue. The
judge might be justified, but the creator would be
condemned. How can it be just to place a being
where he is certain to sin, and then to damn him for
sinning? That is the problem to which no answer
can be given; and which already implies a confusion
of ideas. We apply the conception of justice in
a sphere where it is not applicable, and naturally
fail to get any intelligible answer.
It is impossible to combine the conceptions
of God as the creator and God as the judge; and the
logical straits into which the attempt leads are represented
by the endless free-will controversy. I will not
now enter that field of controversy: and I will
only indicate what seems to me to be the position
which we must accept in any scientific discussion
of our problem. Hume, as I think, laid down the
true principle when he said that there could be no
a priori proof of a matter of fact. An
a priori truth is a truth which cannot be denied
without self-contradiction, but there can never be
a logical consideration in supposing the non-existence
of any fact whatever. The ordinary appeal to
the truths of pure mathematics is, therefore, beside
the question. All such truths are statements
of the precise equivalence of two propositions.
To say that there are four things is also to say that
there are two pairs of things: to say that there
is a plane triangle is also to say that there is a
plane trilateral. One statement involves the
other, because the difference is not in the thing described,
but in our mode of contemplating it. We, therefore,
cannot make one assertion and deny the other without
implicit contradiction. From such results, again,
is evolved (in the logical sense of evolution) the
whole vast system of mathematical truths. The
complexity of that system gives the erroneous idea
that we can, somehow, attain a knowledge of facts,
independently of experience. We fail to observe
that even the most complex mathematical formula is
simply a statement of an exact equivalence of two
assertions; and that, till we know by experience the
truth of one statement, we can never infer the truth,
in fact, of the other. However elaborate may
be the evolutions of mathematical truth, they can
never get beyond the germs out of which they are evolved.
They are valid precisely because the most complex
statement is always the exact equivalent of the simpler,
out of which it is constructed. They remain to
the end truths of number or truths of geometry.
They cannot, by themselves, tell us that things exist
which can be counted or which can be measured.
The whole claim, however elaborate, still requires
its point of suspension. We may put their claims
to absolute or necessary truth as high as we please;
but they cannot give us by themselves a single fact.
I can show, for example, that a circle has an infinite
number of properties, all of which are virtually implied
in the very existence of a circle. But that the
circle or that space itself exists, is not a necessary
truth, but a datum of experience. It is quite
true that such truths are not, in one sense, empirical;
they can be discovered without any change of experience;
for, by their very nature, they refer to the constant
element of experience, and are true on the supposition
of the absolute changelessness of the objects contemplated.
But it is a fallacy to suppose that, because independent
of particular experiences, they are, therefore, independent
of experience in general.
Now, if we agree, as Huxley would
have agreed, that Hume’s doctrine is true, if
we cannot know a single fact except from experience,
we are limited in moral questions, as in all others,
to elaborating and analysing our experience, and can
never properly transcend it. A scientific treatment
of an ethical question, at any rate, must take for
granted all the facts of human nature. It can
show what morality actually is; what are, in fact,
the motives which make men moral, and what are the
consequences of moral conduct. But it cannot get
outside of the universe and lay down moral principles
independent of all influences. I am well aware
that in speaking of ethical questions upon this ground,
I am exposed to many expressions of metaphysical contempt.
I may hope to throw light upon the usual working of
morality; but my theory of the facts cannot make men
moral of itself. I cannot hope, for example,
to show that immorality involves a contradiction, for
I know that immorality exists. I cannot even
hope to show that it is necessarily productive of
misery to the individual, for I know that some people
take pleasure in vicious conduct. I cannot deduce
facts from morals, for I must consistently regard
morals as part of the observed consequences of human
nature under given conditions. Metaphysicians
may, if they can, show me a more excellent method.
I admit that their language sometimes enables them
to take what, in words at least, is a sublimer position
than mine. Kant’s famous phrase, “Thou
must, therefore thou canst,” is impressive.
And yet, it seems to me to involve an obvious piece
of logical juggling. It is quite true that whenever
it is my duty to act in a certain way, it must be a
possibility; but that is only because an impossibility
cannot be a duty. It is not my duty to fly, because
I have not wings; and conversely, no doubt, it would
follow that if it were my duty I must possess
the organs required. Thus understood, however,
the phrase loses its sublimity, and yet, it is only
because we have so to understand it, that it has any
plausibility. Admitting, however, that people
who differ from me can use grander language, and confessing
my readiness to admit error whenever they can point
to a single fact attainable by the pure reason, I
must keep to the humbler path. I speak of the
moral instincts as of others, simply from the point
of view of experience: I cannot myself discover
a single truth from the abstract principle of non-contradiction;
and am content to take for granted that the world
exists as we know it to exist, without seeking to deduce
its peculiarities by any high a priori road.
Upon this assumption, the question
really resolves itself into a different one.
We can neither explain nor justify the existence of
pain; but, of course, we can ask whether, as a matter
of fact, pain predominates over pleasure; and we can
ask whether, as a matter of fact, the “cosmic
processes” tend to promote or discourage virtuous
conduct. Does the theory of the “struggle
for existence” throw any new light upon the
general problem? I am quite unable to see, for
my own part, that it really makes any difference:
evil exists; and the question whether evil predominates
over good, can only, I should say, be decided by an
appeal to experience. One source of evil is the
conflict of interests. Every beast preys upon
others; and man, according to the old saying, is a
wolf to man. All that the Darwinian or any other
theory can do is, to enable us to trace the consequences
of this fact in certain directions; but it neither
creates the fact nor makes it more or less an essential
part of the process. It “explains”
certain phenomena, in the sense of showing their connection
with previous phenomena, but does not show why the
phenomena should present themselves at all. If
we indulge our minds in purely fanciful constructions,
we may regard the actual system as good or bad, just
as we choose to imagine for its alternative a better
or a worse system. If everybody had been put
into a world where there was no pain, or where each
man could get all he wanted without interfering with
his neighbours, we may fancy that things would have
been pleasanter. If the struggle, which we all
know to exist, had no effect in preventing the “survival
of the fittest,” things so, at least,
some of us may think would have been worse.
But such fancies have nothing to do with scientific
inquiries. We have to take things as they are
and make the best of them.
The common feeling, no doubt, is different.
The incessant struggle between different races suggests
a painful view of the universe, as Hobbes’ natural
state of war suggested painful theories as to human
nature. War is evidently immoral, we think; and
a doctrine which makes the whole process of evolution
a process of war must be radically immoral too.
The struggle, it is said, demands “ruthless
self-assertion” and the hunting down of all competitors;
and such phrases certainly have an unpleasant sound.
But in the first place, the use of the epithets implies
an anthropomorphism to which we have no right so long
as we are dealing with the inferior species. We
are then in a region to which such ideas have no direct
application, and where the moral sentiments exist
only in germ, if they can properly be said to exist
at all. Is it fair to call a wolf ruthless because
he eats a sheep and fails to consider the transaction
from the sheep’s point of view? We must
surely admit that if the wolf is without mercy he is
also without malice. We call an animal ferocious
because a man who acted in the same way would be ferocious.
But the man is really ferocious because he is really
aware of the pain which he inflicts. The wolf,
I suppose, has no more recognition of the sheep’s
feelings than a man has of feelings in the oyster
or the potato. For him, they are simply non-existent;
and it is just as inappropriate to think of the wolf
as cruel, as it would be to call the sheep cruel for
eating grass. Are we to say that “nature”
is cruel because the arrangement increases the sum
of undeserved suffering? That is a problem which
I do not feel able to examine; but it is, at least,
obvious that it cannot be answered off-hand in the
affirmative. To the individual sheep it matters
nothing whether he is eaten by the wolf or dies of
disease or starvation. He has to die any way,
and the particular way is unimportant. The wolf
is simply one of the limiting forces upon sheep, and
if he were removed others would come into play.
The sheep, left to himself, would still give a practical
illustration of the doctrine of Malthus. If, as
evolutionists tell us, the hostility of the wolf tends
to improve the breed of sheep, to encourage him to
think more and to sharpen his wits, the sheep may
be, on the whole, the better for the wolf, in this
sense at least: that the sheep of a wolfless
region might lead a more wretched existence, and be
less capable animals and more subject to disease and
starvation than the sheep in a wolf-haunted region.
The wolf may, so far, be a blessing in disguise.
This suggests another obvious remark.
When we speak of the struggle for existence, the popular
view seems to construe this into the theory that the
world is a mere cockpit, in which one race carries
on an interminable struggle with the other. If
the wolves are turned in with the sheep, the first
result will be that all the sheep will become mutton,
and the last that there will be one big wolf with all
the others inside him. But this is contrary to
the essence of the doctrine. Every race depends,
we all hold, upon its environment, and the environment
includes all the other races. If some, therefore,
are in conflict, others are mutually necessary.
If the wolf ate all the sheep, and the sheep ate all
the grass, the result would be the extirpation of
all the sheep and all the wolves, as well as all the
grass. The struggle necessarily implies reciprocal
dependence in a countless variety of ways. There
is not only a conflict, but a system of tacit alliances.
One species is necessary to the existence of others,
though the multiplication of some implies also the
dying out of particular rivals. The conflict
implies no cruelty, as I have said, and the alliance
no goodwill. The wolf neither loves the sheep
(except as mutton) nor hates him; but he depends upon
him as absolutely as if he were aware of the fact.
The sheep is one of the wolf’s necessaries of
life. When we speak of the struggle for existence
we mean, of course, that there is at any given period
a certain equilibrium between all the existing species;
it changes, though it changes so slowly that the process
is imperceptible and difficult to realise even to the
scientific imagination. The survival of any species
involves the disappearance of rivals no more than
the preservation of allies. The struggle, therefore,
is so far from internecine that it necessarily involves
co-operation. It cannot even be said that it necessarily
implies suffering. People, indeed, speak as though
the extinction of a race involved suffering in the
same way as the slaughter of an individual. It
is plain that this is not a necessary, though it may
sometimes be the actual result. A corporation
may be suppressed without injury to its members.
Every individual will die before long, struggle or
no struggle. If the rate of reproduction fails
to keep up with the rate of extinction, the species
must diminish. But this might happen without
any increase of suffering. If the boys in a district
discovered how to take birds’ eggs, they might
soon extirpate a species; but it does not follow that
the birds would individually suffer. Perhaps they
would feel themselves relieved from a disagreeable
responsibility. The process by which a species
is improved, the dying out of the least fit, implies
no more suffering than we know to exist independently
of any doctrine as to a struggle. When we use
anthropomorphic language, we may speak of “self-assertion”.
But “self-assertion,” minus the anthropomorphism,
means self-preservation; and that is merely a way of
describing the fact that an animal or plant which is
well adapted to its conditions of life is more likely
to live than an animal which is ill-adapted.
I have some difficulty in imagining how any other
arrangement can even be supposed possible. It
seems to be almost an identical proposition that the
healthiest and strongest will generally live longest;
and the conception of a “struggle for existence”
only enables us to understand how this results in
certain progressive modifications of the species.
If we could ever for a moment have fancied that there
was no pain and disease, and that some beings were
not more liable than others to those evils, I might
admit that the new doctrine has made the world darker.
As it is, it seems to me that it leaves the data just
what they were before, and only shows us that they
have certain previously unsuspected bearings upon the
history of the world.
One other point must be mentioned.
Not only are species interdependent as well as partly
in competition, but there is an absolute dependence
in all the higher species between its different members
which may be said to imply a de facto altruism,
as the dependence upon other species implies a de
facto co-operation. Every animal, to say
nothing else, is absolutely dependent for a considerable
part of its existence upon its parents. The young
bird or beast could not grow up unless its mother
took care of it for a certain period. There is,
therefore, no struggle as between mother and progeny;
but, on the contrary, the closest possible alliance.
Otherwise, life would be impossible. The young
being defenceless, their parents could exterminate
them if they pleased, and by so doing would exterminate
the race. The parental relation, of course, constantly
involves a partial sacrifice of the mother to her
young. She has to go through a whole series of
operations, which strain her own strength and endanger
her own existence, but which are absolutely essential
to the continuance of the race. It may be anthropomorphic
to attribute any maternal emotions of the human kind
to the animal. The bird, perhaps, sits upon her
eggs because they give her an agreeable sensation,
or, if you please, from a blind instinct which somehow
determines her to the practice. She does not
look forward, we may suppose, to bringing up a family,
or speculate upon the delights of domestic affection.
I only say that as a fact she behaves in a way which
is at once injurious to her own chances of individual
survival, and absolutely necessary to the survival
of the species. The abnormal bird who deserts
her nest escapes many dangers; but if all birds were
devoid of the instinct, the birds would not survive
a generation.
Now, I ask, what is the difference
which takes place when the monkey gradually loses
his tail and sets up a superior brain? Is it properly
to be described as a development or improvement of
the “cosmic process,” or as the beginning
of a prolonged contest against it?
In the first place, so far as man
becomes a reasonable being, capable of foresight and
of the adoption of means to ends, he recognises the
nature of these tacit alliances. He believes it
to be his interest not to exterminate everything,
but to exterminate those species alone whose existence
is incompatible with his own. The wolf eats every
sheep that he comes across as long as his appetite
lasts. If there are too many wolves, the process
is checked by the starvation of the supernumerary
eaters. Man can maintain just as many sheep as
he wants, and may also proportion the numbers of his
own species to the possibilities of future supply.
Many of the lower species thus become subordinate parts
of the social organism that is to say, of
the new equilibrium which has been established.
There is so far a reciprocal advantage. The sheep
that is preserved with a view to mutton gets the advantage,
though he is not kept with a view to his own advantage.
Of all arguments for vegetarianism, none is so weak
as the argument from humanity. The pig has a
stronger interest than any one in the demand for bacon.
If all the world were Jewish, there would be no pigs
at all. He has to pay for his privileges by an
early death; but he makes a good bargain of it.
He dies young, and, though we can hardly infer the
“love of the gods,” we must admit that
he gets a superior race of beings to attend to his
comforts, moved by the strongest possible interest
in his health and vigour, and induced by its own needs,
perhaps, to make him a little too fat for comfort,
but certainly also to see that he has a good sty, and
plenty to eat every day of his life. Other races,
again, are extirpated as “ruthlessly”
as in the merely instinctive struggle for existence.
We get rid of wolves and snakes as well as we can,
and more systematically than can be done by their
animal competitors. The process does not necessarily
involve cruelty, and certainly does not involve a
diminution of the total of happiness. The struggle
for existence means the substitution of a new system
of equilibrium, in which one of the old discords has
been removed, and the survivors live in greater harmony.
If the wolf is extirpated as an internecine enemy,
it is that there may be more sheep when sheep have
become our allies and the objects of our earthly providence.
The result may be, perhaps I might say must be, a
state in which, on the whole, there is a greater amount
of life supported on the planet; and therefore, as
those will think who are not pessimists, a decided
gain on the balance. At any rate, the difference
so far is that the condition which was in all cases
necessary, is now consciously recognised as necessary;
and that we deliberately aim at a result which always
had to be achieved on penalty of destruction.
So far, again, as morality can be established on purely
prudential grounds, the same holds good of relations
between human beings themselves. Men begin to
perceive that, even from a purely personal point of
view, peace is preferable to war. If war is unhappily
still prevalent, it is at least not war in which every
clan is fighting with its neighbours, and where conquest
means slavery or extirpation. Millions of men
are at peace within the limits of a modern State, and
can go about their business without cutting each other’s
throats. When they fight with other nations they
do not enslave nor massacre their prisoners.
Starting from the purely selfish ground Hobbes could
prove conclusively that everybody benefited by the
social compact which substituted peace and order for
the original state of war. Is this, then, a reversal
of the old state of things a combating of
a “cosmic process”? I should rather
say that it is a development of the tacit alliances,
and a modification so far of the direct or internecine
conflict. Both were equally implied in the older
conditions, and both still exist. Some races
form alliances, while others are crowded out of existence.
Of course, I cease to do some things which I should
have done before. I don’t attack the first
man I meet in the street and take his scalp.
One reason is that I don’t expect he will take
mine; for, if I did, I fear that, even as a civilised
being, I should try to anticipate his intentions.
This merely means that we have both come to see that
we have a common interest in keeping the peace.
And this, again, merely means that the tacit alliance
which was always an absolutely necessary condition
of the survival of the species has now been extended
through a wider area. The species could not have
got on at all if there had not been so much alliance
as is necessary for its reproduction and for the preservation
of its young for some years of helplessness.
The change is simply that the small circle which included
only the primitive family or class has extended, so
that we can meet members of the same nation, or, it
may be, of the same race, on terms which were previously
confined to the minor group. We have still to
exterminate and still to preserve. The mode of
employing our energies has changed, but not the essential
nature. Morality proper, however, has so far
not emerged. It begins when sympathy begins; when
we really desire the happiness of others; or, as Kant
says, when we treat other men as an end and not simply
as a means. Undoubtedly this involves a new principle,
no less than the essential principle of all true morality.
Still, I have to ask whether it implies a combating
or a continuation of a cosmic process. Now, as
I have observed, even the animal mother shows what
I have called a de facto altruism. She
has instincts which, though dangerous to the individual,
are essential for the race. The human mother
sacrifices herself with a consciousness of the results
to herself, and her personal fears are overcome by
the strength of her affections. She intentionally
endures a painful death to save them from suffering.
The animal sacrifices herself, but without foresight
of the result, and therefore without moral worth.
This is merely the most striking exemplification of
the general process of the development of morality.
Conduct is first regarded purely with a view to the
effects upon the agent, and is therefore enforced by
extrinsic penalties, by consequences, that is, supposed
to be attached to us by the will of some ruler, natural
or supernatural. The instinct which comes to
regard such conduct as bad in itself, which implies
a dislike of giving pain to others, and not merely
a dislike to the gallows, grows up under such probation
until the really moralised being acquires feelings
which make the external penalty superfluous. This,
indubitably, is the greatest of all changes, the critical
fact which decides whether we are to regard conduct
simply as useful, or also to regard it as moral in
the strictest sense. But I should still call it
a development and not a reversal of the previous process.
The conduct which we call virtuous is the same conduct
externally which we before regarded as useful.
The difference is that the simple fact of its utility,
that is, of its utility to others and to the race in
general, has now become also the sufficient motive
for the action as well as the implicit cause of the
action. In the earlier stages, when no true sympathy
existed, men and animals were still forced to act in
a certain way because it was beneficial to others.
They now act in that way because they are conscious
that it is beneficial to others. The whole history
of moral evolution seems to imply this. We may
go back to a period at which the moral law is identified
with the general customs of the race; at which there
is no perception of any clear distinction between
that which is moral and that which is simply customary;
between that which is imposed by a law in the strict
sense and that which is dictated by general moral
principles. In such a state of things, the motives
for obedience partake of the nature of “blind
instincts”. No definite reason for them
is present to the mind of the agent, and it does not
occur to him even to demand a reason. “Our
fathers did so and we do so” is the sole and
sufficient explanation of their conduct. Thus
instinct again may be traced back by evolutionists
to the earliest period at which the instincts implied
in the relations between the sexes or between parents
and offspring, existed. They were the germ from
which has sprung all morality such as we now recognise.
Morality, then, implies the development
of certain instincts which are essential to the race,
but which may, in an indefinite number of cases, be
injurious to the individual. The particular mother
is killed because she obeys her natural instincts;
but, if it were not for mothers and their instincts,
the race would come to an end. Professor Huxley
speaks of the “fanatical individualism”
of our time as failing to construct morality from
the analogy of the cosmic process. An individualism
which regards the cosmic process as equivalent simply
to an internecine struggle of each against all, must
certainly fail to construct a satisfactory morality
upon such terms, and I will add that any individualism
which fails to recognise fully the social character,
which regards society as an aggregate instead of an
organism, will, in my opinion, find itself in difficulties.
But I also submit that the development of the instincts
which directly correspond to the needs of the race,
is merely another case in which we aim consciously
at an end which was before an unintentional result
of our actions. Every race, above the lowest,
has instincts which are only intelligible by the requirements
of the race; and has both to compete with some and
to form alliances with others of its fellow occupants
of the planet. Both in the unmoralised condition
and in that in which morality has become most developed,
these instincts have common characteristics, and may
be regarded as conditions of the power of the race
to which they belong to maintain its position in the
world, and, speaking roughly, to preserve or increase
its own vitality.
I will not pause to insist upon this
so far as regards many qualities which are certainly
moral, though they may be said to refer primarily
to the individual. That chastity and temperance,
truthfulness and energy, are, on the whole, advantages
both to the individual and to the race, does not,
I fancy, require elaborate proof; nor need I argue
at length that the races in which they are common
will therefore have inevitable advantages in the struggle
for existence. Of all qualities which enable
a race to hold its own, none is more important than
the power of organising individually, politically,
and socially, and that power implies the existence
of justice and the instinct of mutual confidence-in
short, all the social virtues. The difficulty
seems to be felt in regard to those purely altruistic
impulses, which, at first glance at any rate, make
it apparently our duty to preserve those who would
otherwise be unfit to live. Virtue, says Professor
Huxley, is directed “not so much to the survival
of the fittest,” as to the “fitting of
as many as possible to survive”. I do not
dispute the statement, I think it true in a sense;
but I have a difficulty as to its application.
Morality, it is obvious, must be limited
by the conditions in which we are placed. What
is impossible is not a duty. One condition plainly
is that the planet is limited. There is only
room for a certain number of living beings; and though
we may determine what shall be the number, we cannot
arbitrarily say that it shall be indefinitely great.
It is one consequence that we do, in fact, go on suppressing
the unfit, and cannot help going on suppressing them.
Is it desirable that it should be otherwise?
Should we wish, for example, that America could still
be a hunting-ground for savages? Is it better
that it should contain a million red men or sixty
millions of civilised whites? Undoubtedly the
moralist will say with absolute truth that the methods
of extirpation adopted by Spaniards and Englishmen
were detestable. I need not say that I agree
with him, and hope that such methods may be abolished
wherever any remnant of them exists. But I say
so partly because I believe in the struggle for existence.
This process underlies morality, and operates whether
we are moral or not. The most civilised race,
that which has the greatest knowledge, skill, power
of organisation, will, I hold, have an inevitable
advantage in the struggle, even if it does not use
the brutal means which are superfluous as well as cruel.
All the natives who lived in America a hundred years
ago would be dead now in any case, even if they had
invariably been treated with the greatest humanity,
fairness, and consideration. Had they been unable
to suit themselves to new conditions of life, they
would have suffered an euthanasia instead of a partial
extirpation; and had they suited themselves they would
either have been absorbed or become a useful part
of the population. To abolish the old brutal method
is not to abolish the struggle for existence, but
to make the result depend upon a higher order of qualities
than those of the mere piratical viking.
Mr. Pearson has been telling us in
his most interesting book, that the negro may not
improbably hold his own in Africa. I cannot say
I regard this as an unmixed evil. Why should
there not be parts of the world in which races of
inferior intelligence or energy should hold their own?
I am not so anxious to see the whole earth covered
by an indefinite multiplication of the cockney type.
But I only quote the suggestion for another reason.
Till recent years the struggle for existence was carried
on as between Europeans and negroes by simple violence
and brutality. The slave trade and its consequences
have condemned the whole continent to barbarism.
That, undoubtedly, was part of the struggle for existence.
But, if Mr. Pearson’s guess should be verified,
the results have been so far futile as well as disastrous.
The negro has been degraded, and yet, after all our
brutality, we cannot take his place. Therefore,
besides the enormous evils to slave-trading countries
themselves, the lowering of their moral tone, the substitution
of piracy for legitimate commerce, and the degradation
of the countries which bought the slaves, the superior
race has not even been able to suppress the inferior.
But the abolition of this monstrous evil does not
involve the abolition but the humanisation of the struggle.
The white man, however merciful he becomes, may gradually
extend over such parts of the country as are suitable
to him; and the black man will hold the rest and acquire
such arts and civilisation as he is capable of appropriating.
The absence of cruelty would not alter the fact that
the fittest race would extend; but it may ensure that
whatever is good in the negro may have a chance of
development in his own sphere, and that success in
the struggle will be decided by more valuable qualities.
Without venturing further into a rather
speculative region, I need only indicate the bearing
of such considerations upon problems nearer home.
It is often complained that the tendency of modern
civilisation is to preserve the weakly, and therefore
to lower the vitality of the race. This seems
to involve inadmissible assumptions. In the first
place, the process by which the weaker are preserved
consists in suppressing various conditions unfavourable
to human life in general. Sanitary legislation,
for example, aims at destroying the causes of many
of the diseases from which our forefathers suffered.
If we can suppress the smallpox, we of course save
many weakly children, who would have died had they
been attacked. But we also remove one of the causes
which weakened the constitutions of many of the survivors.
I do not know by what right we can say that such legislation,
or again, the legislation which prevents the excessive
labour of children, does more harm by preserving the
weak than it does good by preventing the weakening
of the strong. One thing is at any rate clear:
to preserve life is to increase the population, and
therefore to increase the competition; or, in other
words, to intensify the struggle for existence.
The process is as broad as it is long. If we
could be sure that every child born should grow up
to maturity, the result would be to double the severity
of the competition for support, What we should have
to show, therefore, in order to justify the inference
of a deterioration due to this process, would be,
not that it simply increased the number of the candidates
for living, but that it gave to the feebler candidates
a differential advantage; that they are now more fitted
than they were before for ousting their superior neighbours
from the chances of support. But I can see no
reason for supposing such a consequence to be probable
or even possible. The struggle for existence,
as I have suggested, rests upon the unalterable facts
that the world is limited and population elastic.
Under all conceivable circumstances we shall still
have in some way or other to proportion our numbers
to our supplies; and under all circumstances those
who are fittest by reason of intellectual or moral
or physical qualities will have the best chance of
occupying good places, and leaving descendants to supply
the next generation. It is surely not less true
that in the civilised as much as in the most barbarous
race, the healthiest are the most likely to live,
and the most likely to be ancestors. If so, the
struggle will still be carried on upon the same principles,
though certainly in a different shape.
It is true that this suggests one
of the most difficult questions of the time.
It is suggested, for example, that in some respects
the “highest” specimens of the race are
not the healthiest or the fittest. Genius, according
to some people, is a variety of disease, and intellectual
power is won by a diminution of reproductive power.
A lower race, again, if we measure “high”
and “low” by intellectual capacity, may
oust a higher race, because it can support itself more
cheaply, or, in other words, because it is more efficient
for industrial purposes. Without presuming to
pronounce upon such questions, I will simply ask whether
this does not interpret Professor Huxley’s remark
about that “cosmic nature” which is still
so strong, and which is likely to be strong so long
as men require stomachs. We have not, I think,
to suppress it, but to adapt it to new circumstances.
We are engaged in working out a gigantic problem:
What is the best, in the sense of the most efficient,
type of human being? What is the best combination
of brains and stomach? We turn out saints, who
are “too good to live,” and philosophers,
who have run too rapidly to brains. They do not
answer in practice, because they are instruments too
delicate for the rough work of daily life. They
may give us a foretaste of qualities which will be
some day possible for the average man; of intellectual
and moral qualities, which, though now exceptional,
may become commonplace. But the best stock for
the race are those in whom we have been lucky enough
to strike out the happy combination, in which greater
intellectual power is produced without the loss of
physical vigour. Such men, it is probable, will
not deviate so widely from the average type.
The reconciliation of the two conditions can only
be effected by a very gradual process of slowly edging
onwards in the right direction. Meanwhile the
theory of a struggle for existence justifies us, instead
of condemning us, for preserving the delicate child,
who may turn out to be a Newton or a Keats, because
he will leave to us the advantage of his discoveries
or his poems, while his physical feebleness assures
us that he will not propagate his race.
This may lead to a final question.
Does the morality of a race strengthen or weaken it;
fit it to hold its own in the general equilibrium,
or make its extirpation by low moral races more probable?
I do not suppose that anybody would deny what I have
already suggested, that the more moral the race, the
more harmonious and the better organised, the better
it is fitted for holding its own. But if this
be admitted, we must also admit that the change is
not that it has ceased to struggle, but that it struggles
by different means. It holds its own, not merely
by brute force, but by justice, humanity, and intelligence,
while, it may be added, the possession of such qualities
does not weaken the brute force, where such a quality
is still required. The most civilised races are,
of course, also the most formidable in war. But,
if we take the opposite alternative, I must ask how
any quality which really weakens the vitality of the
race can properly be called moral. I should entirely
repudiate any rule of conduct which could be shown
to have such a tendency. This, indeed, indicates
what seems to me to be the moral difficulty with most
people. Charity, you say, is a virtue; charity
increases beggary, and so far tends to produce a feebler
population; therefore, a moral quality tends doubly
to diminish the vigour of a nation. The answer
is, of course, obvious, and I am confident that Professor
Huxley would have so far agreed with me. It is
that all charity which fosters a degraded class is
therefore immoral. The “fanatical individualism”
of to-day has its weaknesses; but in this matter it
seems to me that we see the weakness of the not less
fanatical “collectivism”.
The question, in fact, how far any
of the socialistic or ethical schemes of to-day are
right or wrong, depends upon our answer to the question
how far they tend to produce a vigorous or an enervated
population. If I am asked to subscribe to General
Booth’s scheme, I inquire first whether the
scheme is likely to increase or diminish the number
of helpless hangers-on upon the efficient part of society.
Will the whole nation consist in larger proportions
of active and responsible workers, or of people who
are simply burdens upon the real workers? The
answer decides not only the question whether it is
expedient, but also the question whether it is right
or wrong, to support the proposed scheme. Every
charitable action is so far a good action that it
implies sympathy for suffering; but if it is so much
in want of prudence that it increases the evil which
it means to remedy, it becomes for that reason a bad
action. To develop sympathy without developing
foresight is just one of the one-sided developments
which fail to constitute a real advance in morality,
though I will not deny that it may incidentally lead
to an advance.
I hold, then, that the “struggle
for existence” belongs to an underlying order
of facts to which moral epithets cannot be properly
applied. It denotes a condition of which the moralist
has to take account, and to which morality has to
be adapted; but which, just because it is a “cosmic
process,” cannot be altered, however much we
may alter the conduct which it dictates. Under
all conceivable circumstances, the race has to adapt
itself to the environment, and that necessarily implies
a conflict as well as an alliance. The preservation
of the fittest, which is surely a good thing, is merely
another aspect of the dying out of the unfit, which
is hardly a bad thing. The feast which Nature
spreads before us, according to Malthus’s metaphor,
is only sufficient for a limited number of guests,
and the one question is how to select them. The
tendency of morality is to humanise the struggle,
to minimise the suffering of those who lose the game;
and to offer the prizes to the qualities which are
advantageous to all, rather than to those which increase
and intensify the bitterness of the conflict.
This implies the growth of foresight, which is an
extension of the earlier instinct, and enables men
to adapt themselves to the future and to learn from
the past, as well as to act up to immediate impulse
of present events. It implies still more the
development of the sympathy which makes every man feel
for the hurts of all, and which, as social organisation
is closer, and the dependence of each constituent
atom upon the whole organisation is more vividly realised,
extends the range of a man’s interests beyond
his own private needs. In that sense, again,
it must stimulate “collectivism” at the
expense of a crude individualism, and condemns the
doctrine which, as Professor Huxley puts it, would
forbid us to restrain the member of a community from
doing his best to destroy it. To restrain such
conduct is surely to carry on the conflict against
all anti-social agents or tendencies. For I should
certainly hold any form of collectivism to be immoral
which denied the essential doctrine of the abused
individualist, the necessity, that is, for individual
responsibility. We have surely to suppress the
murderer, as our ancestors suppressed the wolf.
We have to suppress both the external enemies, the
noxious animals whose existence is incompatible with
our own, and the internal enemies which are injurious
elements in the society itself. That is, we have
to work for the same end of eliminating the least fit.
Our methods are changed; we desire to suppress poverty,
not to extirpate the poor man. We give inferior
races a chance of taking whatever place they are fit
for, and try to supplant them with the least possible
severity if they are unfit for any place. But
the suppression of poverty supposes not the confiscation
of wealth, which would hardly suppress poverty in
the long run, nor even the adoption of a system of
living which would enable the idle and the good-for-nothing
to survive. The progress of civilisation depends,
I should say, on the extension of the sense of duty
which each man owes to society at large. That
involves such a constitution of society that, although
we abandon the old methods of hanging and flogging
and shooting down methods which corrupted
the inflicters of punishment by diminishing their
own sense of responsibility may give an
advantage to the prudent and industrious, and make
it more probable that they will be the ancestors of
the next generation. A system which should equalise
the advantages of the energetic and the helpless would
begin by demoralising, and would very soon lead to
an unprecedented intensification of the struggle for
existence. The probable result of a ruthless socialism
would be the adoption of very severe means for suppressing
those who did not contribute their share of work.
But, in any case, as it seems, we never get away or
break away from the inevitable fact. If individual
ends could be suppressed, if every man worked for
the good of society as energetically as for his own,
we should still feel the absolute necessity of proportioning
the whole body to the whole supplies obtainable from
the planet, and to preserve the equilibrium of mankind
relatively to the rest of nature. That day is
probably distant; but even upon that hypothesis the
struggle for existence would still be with us, and
there would be the same necessity for preserving the
fittest and killing out, as gently as might be, those
who were unfit.