‘The Rebuilding of London’
proceeds ruthlessly apace. The humble old houses
that dare not scrape the sky are being duly punished
for their timidity. Down they come; and in their
place are shot up new tenements, quick and high as
rockets. And the little old streets, so narrow
and exclusive, so shy and crooked — we are
making an example of them, too. We lose our way
in them, do we? — we whose time is money.
Our omnibuses can’t trundle through them, can’t
they? Very well, then. Down with them!
We have no use for them. This is the age of ‘noble
arteries.’
‘The Rebuilding of London’
is a source of much pride and pleasure to most of
London’s citizens, especially to them who are
county councillors, builders, contractors, navvies,
glaziers, decorators, and so forth. There is
but a tiny residue of persons who do not swell and
sparkle. And of these glum bystanders at the carnival
I am one. Our aloofness is mainly irrational,
I suppose. It is due mainly to temperamental
Toryism. We say ‘The old is better.’
This we say to ourselves, every one of us feeling
himself thereby justified in his attitude. But
we are quite aware that such a postulate would not
be accepted by time majority. For the majority,
then, let us make some show of ratiocination.
Let us argue that, forasmuch as London is an historic
city, with many phases and periods behind her, and
forasmuch as many of these phases and periods are
enshrined in the aspect of her buildings, the constant
rasure of these buildings is a disservice to the historian
not less than to the mere sentimentalist, and that
it will moreover (this is a more telling argument)
filch from Englishmen the pleasant power of crowing
over Americans, and from Americans the unpleasant
necessity of balancing their pity for our present with
envy of our past. After all, our past is our
point d’appui. Our present is merely a
bad imitation of what the Americans can do much better.
Ignoring as mere scurrility this criticism
of London’s present, but touched by my appeal
to his pride in its history, the average citizen will
reply, reasonably enough, to this effect: ’By
all means let us have architectural evidence of our
epochs — Caroline, Georgian, Victorian, what
you will. But why should the Edvardian be ruled
out? London is packed full of architecture already.
Only by rasing much of its present architecture can
we find room for commemorating duly the glorious epoch
which we have just entered. To this reply there
are two rejoinders: (1) let special suburbs be
founded for Edvardian buildings; (2) there are no
really Edvardian buildings, and there won’t be
any. Long before the close of the Victorian Era
our architects had ceased to be creative. They
could not express in their work the spirit of their
time. They could but evolve a medley of old styles,
some foreign, some native, all inappropriate.
Take the case of Mayfair. Mayfair has for some
years been in a state of transition. The old Mayfair,
grim and sombre, with its air of selfish privacy and
hauteur and leisure, its plain bricked façades, so
disdainful of show — was it not redolent of
the century in which it came to being? Its wide
pavements and narrow roads between — could
not one see in them the time when by day gentlemen
and ladies went out afoot, needing no vehicle to whisk
them to a destination, and walked to and fro amply,
needing elbow-room for their dignity and their finery,
and by night were borne in chairs, singly? And
those queer little places of worship, those stucco
chapels, with their very secular little columns, their
ample pews, and their negligible altars over which
one saw the Lion and the Unicorn fighting, as who
should say, for the Cross — did they not breathe
all the inimitable Erastianism of their period?
In qua te qaero proseucha, my Lady
Powderbox? Alas! every one of your tabernacles
is dust now — dust turned to mud by the tears
of the ghost of the Rev. Charles Honeyman, and by
my own tears.... I have strayed again into sentiment.
Back to the point — which is that the new
houses and streets in Mayfair mean nothing. Let
me show you Mount Street. Let me show you that
airy stretch of sham antiquity, and defy you to say
that it symbolises, how remotely soever, the spirit
of its time. Mount Street is typical of the new
Mayfair. And the new Mayfair is typical of the
new London. In the height of these new houses,
in the width of these new roads, future students will
find, doubtless, something characteristic of this
pressing and bustling age. But from the style
of the houses he will learn nothing at all. The
style might mean anything; and means, therefore, nothing.
Original architecture is a lost art in England; and
an art that is once lost is never found again.
The Edvardian Era cannot be commemorated in its architecture.
Erection of new buildings robs us
of the past and gives us in exchange nothing of the
present. Consequently, the excuse put by me into
the gaping mouth of the average Londoner cannot be
accepted. I had no idea that my case was such
a good one. Having now vindicated on grounds of
patriotic utility that which I took to be a mere sentimental
prejudice, I may be pardoned for dragging ‘beauty’
into the question. The new buildings are not
only uninteresting through lack of temporal and local
significance: they are also hideous. With
all his learned eclecticism, the new architect seems
unable to evolve a fake that shall be pleasing to
the eye. Not at all pleasing is a mad hotch-potch
of early Victorian hospital, Jacobean manor-house,
Venetian palace, and bride-cake in Gunter’s
best manner. Yet that, apparently, is the modern
English architect’s pet ideal. Even when
he confines himself to one manner, the result (even
if it be in itself decent) is made horrible by vicinity
to the work of a rival who has been dabbling in some
other manner. Every street in London is being
converted into a battlefield of styles, all shrieking
at one another, all murdering one another. The
tumult may be exciting, especially to the architects,
but it is not beautiful. It is not good to live
in.
However, I am no propagandist.
I am not sanguine enough to suppose that I could do
anything to stop either the adulteration or the demolition
of old streets. I do not wish to infect the public
with my own misgivings. On the contrary, my motive
for this essay is to inoculate the public with my
own placid indifference in a certain matter which
seems always to cause them painful anxiety. Whenever
a new highway is about to be opened, the newspapers
are filled with letters suggesting that it ought to
be called by this or that beautiful name, or by the
name of this or that national hero. Well, in point
of fact, a name cannot (in the long-run) make any
shadow of difference in our sentiment for the street
that bears it, for our sentiment is solely according
to the character of the street itself; and, further,
a street does nothing at all to keep green the memory
of one whose name is given to it.
For a street one name is as good as
another. To prove this proposition, let us proceed
by analogy of the names borne by human beings.
Surnames and Christian names may alike be divided
into two classes: (1) those which, being identical
with words in the dictionary, connote some definite
thing; (2) those which, connoting nothing, may or may
not suggest something by their sound. Instances
of Christian names in the first class are Rose, Faith;
of surnames, Lavender, Badger; of Christian names
in the second class, Celia, Mary; of surnames, Jones,
Vavasour. Let us consider the surnames in the
first class. You will say, off-hand, that Lavender
sounds pretty, and that Badger sounds ugly. Very
well. Now, suppose that Christian names connoting
unpleasant things were sometimes conferred at baptisms.
Imagine two sisters named Nettle and Envy. Off-hand,
you will say that these names sound ugly, whilst Rose
and Faith sound pretty. Yet, believe me, there
is not, in point of actual sound, one pin to choose
either between Badger and Lavender, or between Rose
and Nettle, or between Faith and Envy. There
is no such thing as a singly euphonious or a singly
cacophonous name. There is no word which, by
itself, sounds ill or well. In combination, names
or words may be made to sound ill or well. A sentence
can be musical or unmusical. But in detachment
words are no more preferable one to another in their
sound than are single notes of music. What you
take to be beauty or ugliness of sound is indeed nothing
but beauty or ugliness of meaning. You are pleased
by the sound of such words as gondola, vestments,
chancel, ermine, manor-house. They seem to be
fraught with a subtle onomatopoeia, severally suggesting
by their sounds the grace or sanctity or solid comfort
of the things which they connote. You murmur
them luxuriously, dreamily. Prepare for a slight
shock. Scrofula, investments, cancer, vermin,
warehouse. Horrible words, are they not?
But say gondola — scrofula, vestments — investments,
and so on; and then lay your hand on your heart, and
declare that the words in the first list are in mere
sound nicer than the words in the second. Of
course they are not. If gondola were a disease,
and if a scrofula were a beautiful boat peculiar to
a beautiful city, the effect of each word would be
exactly the reverse of what it is. This rule may
be applied to all the other words in the two lists.
And these lists might, of course, be extended to infinity.
The appropriately beautiful or ugly sound of any word
is an illusion wrought on us by what the word connotes.
Beauty sounds as ugly as ugliness sounds beautiful.
Neither of them has by itself any quality in sound.
It follows, then, that the Christian
names and surnames in my first class sound beautiful
or ugly according to what they connote. The sound
of those in the second class depends on the extent
to which it suggests any known word more than another.
Of course, there might be a name hideous in itself.
There might, for example, be a Mr. Griggsbiggmiggs.
But there is not. And the fact that I, after prolonged
study of a Postal Directory, have been obliged to
use my imagination as factory for a name that connotes
nothing and is ugly in itself may be taken as proof
that such names do not exist actually. You cannot
stump me by citing Mr. Matthew Arnold’s citation
of the words ‘Ragg is in custody,’ and
his comment that ‘there was no Ragg by the Ilyssus.’
‘Ragg’ has not an ugly sound in itself.
Mr. Arnold was jarred merely by its suggestion of
something ugly, a rag, and by the cold brutality of
the police-court reporter in withholding the prefix
‘Miss’ from a poor girl who had got into
trouble. If ‘Ragg’ had been brought
to his notice as the name of some illustrious old
family, Mr. Arnold would never have dragged in the
Ilyssus. The name would have had for him a savour
of quaint distinction. The suggestion of a rag
would never have struck him. For it is a fact
that whatever thing may be connoted or suggested by
a name is utterly overshadowed by the name’s
bearer (unless, as in the case of poor ‘Ragg,’
there is seen to be some connexion between the bearer
and the thing implied by the name). Roughly,
it may be said that all names connote their bearers,
and them only.
To have a ‘beautiful’
name is no advantage. To have an ‘ugly’
name is no drawback. I am aware that this is
a heresy. In a famous passage, Bulwer Lytton
propounded through one of his characters a theory that
’it is not only the effect that the sound of
a name has on others which is to be thoughtfully considered;
the effect that his name produces on the man himself
is perhaps still more important. Some names stimulate
and encourage the owner, others deject and paralyse
him.’
Bulwer himself, I doubt not, believed
that there was something in this theory. It is
natural that a novelist should. He is always at
great pains to select for his every puppet a name
that suggests to himself the character which he has
ordained for that puppet. In real life a baby
gets its surname by blind heredity, its other names
by the blind whim of its parents, who know not at
all what sort of a person it will eventually become.
And yet, when these babies grow up, their names seem
every whit as appropriate as do the names of the romantic
puppets. ‘Obviously,’ thinks the
novelist, ’these human beings must “grow
to” their names; or else, we must be viewing
them in the light of their names.’ And
the quiet ordinary people, who do not write novels,
incline to his conjectures. How else can they
explain the fact that every name seems to fit its
bearer so exactly, to sum him or her up in a flash?
The true explanation, missed by them, is that a name
derives its whole quality from its bearer, even as
does a word from its meaning. The late Sir Redvers
Buller, tauredon hupoblepsas [spelled in Greek, from
Plato’s Phaedo 117b], was thought to be
peculiarly well fitted with his name. Yet had
it belonged not to him, but to (say) some gentle and
thoughtful ecclesiastic, it would have seemed quite
as inevitable. ‘Gore’ is quite as
taurine as ‘Buller,’ and yet does it not
seem to us the right name for the author of Lux
Mundi? In connection with him, who is struck
by its taurinity? What hint of ovinity would there
have been for us if Sir Redvers’ surname had
happened to be that of him who wrote the Essays of
Elia? Conversely, ‘Charles Buller’
seems to us now an impossible nom de
vie for Elia; yet it would have done just as well,
really. Even ‘Redvers Buller’ would
have done just as well. ’Walter Pater’
means for us — how perfectly! — the
author of Marius the Epicurean, whilst the author
of All Sorts and Conditions of Men was summed up for
us, not less absolutely, in ‘Walter Besant.’
And yet, if the surnames of these two opposite Walters
had been changed at birth, what difference would have
been made? ‘Walter Besant’ would have
signified a prose style sensuous in its severity, an
exquisitely patient scholarship, an exquisitely sympathetic
way of criticism. ‘Walter Pater’
would have signified no style, but an unslakable thirst
for information, and a bustling human sympathy, and
power of carrying things through. Or take two
names often found in conjunction — Johnson
and Boswell. Had the dear great oracle been named
Boswell, and had the sitter-at-his-feet been named
Johnson, would the two names seem to us less appropriate
than they do? Should we suffer any greater loss
than if Salmon were Gluckstein, and Gluckstein Salmon?
Finally, take a case in which the same name was borne
by two very different characters. What name could
seem more descriptive of a certain illustrious Archbishop
of Westminster than ‘Manning’? It
seems the very epitome of saintly astuteness.
But for ‘Cardinal’ substitute ‘Mrs.’
as its prefix, and, presto! it is equally descriptive
of that dreadful medio-Victorian murderess who
in the dock of the Old Bailey wore a black satin gown,
and thereby created against black satin a prejudice
which has but lately died. In itself black satin
is a beautiful thing. Yet for many years, by
force of association, it was accounted loathsome.
Conversely, one knows that many quite hideous fashions
in costume have been set by beautiful women.
Such instances of the subtle power of association will
make clear to you how very easily a name (being neither
beautiful nor hideous in itself) can be made hideous
or beautiful by its bearer — how inevitably
it becomes for us a symbol of its bearer’s most
salient qualities or defects, be they physical, moral,
or intellectual.
Streets are not less characteristic
than human beings. ‘Look!’ cried a
friend of mine, whom lately I found studying a map
of London, ’isn’t it appalling? All
these streets — thousands of them — in
this tiny compass! Think of the miles and miles
of drab monotony this map contains! I pointed
out to him (it is a thinker’s penalty to be always
pointing things out to people) that his words were
nonsense. I told him that the streets on this
map were no more monotonous than the rivers on the
map of England. Just as there were no two rivers
alike, every one of them having its own speed, its
own windings, depths, and shallows, its own way with
the reeds and grasses, so had every street its own
claim to an especial nymph, forasmuch as no two streets
had exactly the same proportions, the same habitual
traffic, the same type of shops or houses, the same
inhabitants. In some cases, of course, the difference
between the ‘atmosphere’ of two streets
is a subtle difference. But it is always there,
not less definite to any one who searches for it than
the difference between (say) Hill Street and Pont Street,
High Street Kensington and High Street Notting Hill,
Fleet Street and the Strand. I have here purposely
opposed to each other streets that have obvious points
of likeness. But what a yawning gulf of difference
is between each couple! Hill Street, with its
staid distinction, and Pont Street, with its eager,
pushful ‘smartness,’ its air de petit parvenu,
its obvious delight in having been ‘taken up’;
High Street Notting Hill, down-at-heels and unashamed,
with a placid smile on its broad ugly face, and High
Street Kensington, with its traces of former beauty,
and its air of neatness and self-respect, as befits
one who in her day has been caressed by royalty; Fleet
Street, that seething channel of business, and the
Strand, that swollen river of business, on whose surface
float so many aimless and unsightly objects. In
every one of these thoroughfares my mood and my manner
are differently affected. In Hill Street, instinctively,
I walk very slowly — sometimes, even with
a slight limp, as one recovering from an accident
in the hunting-field. I feel very well-bred there,
and, though not clever, very proud, and quick to resent
any familiarity from those whom elsewhere I should
regard as my equals. In Pont Street my demeanour
is not so calm and measured. I feel less sure
of myself, and adopt a slight swagger. In High
Street, Kensington, I find myself dapper and respectable,
with a timid leaning to the fine arts. In High
Street, Notting Hill, I become frankly common.
Fleet Street fills me with a conviction that if I don’t
make haste I shall be jeopardising the national welfare.
The Strand utterly unmans me, leaving me with only
two sensations: (1) a regret that I have made
such a mess of my life; (2) a craving for alcohol.
These are but a few instances. If I had time,
I could show you that every street known to me in
London has a definite effect on me, and that no two
streets have exactly the same effect. For the
most part, these effects differ in kind according
only to the different districts and their different
modes of life; but they differ in detail according
to such specific little differences as exist between
such cognate streets as Bruton Street and Curzon Street,
Doughty Street and Great Russell Street. Every
one of my readers, doubtless, realises that he, too,
is thus affected by the character of streets.
And I doubt not that for him, as for me, the mere
sound or sight of a street’s name conjures up
the sensation he feels when he passes through that
street. For him, probably, the name of every
street has hitherto seemed to be also its exact, inevitable
symbol, a perfect suggestion of its character.
He has believed that the grand or beautiful streets
have grand or beautiful names, the mean or ugly streets
mean or ugly names. Let me assure him that this
is a delusion. The name of a street, as of a human
being, derives its whole quality from its bearer.
‘Oxford Street’ sounds
harsh and ugly. ‘Manchester Street’
sounds rather charming. Yet ‘Oxford’
sounds beautiful, and ‘Manchester’ sounds
odious. ‘Oxford’ turns our thoughts
to that ’adorable dreamer, whispering from her
spires the last enchantments of the Middle Age.’
An uproarious monster, belching from its factory-chimneys
the latest exhalations of Hell — that is
the image evoked by ‘Manchester.’
But neither in ‘Manchester Street’ is
there for us any hint of that monster, nor in ‘Oxford
Street’ of that dreamer. The names have
become part and parcel of the streets. You see,
then, that it matters not whether the name given to
a new street be one which in itself suggests beauty,
or one which suggests ugliness. In point of fact,
it is generally the most pitiable little holes and
corners that bear the most ambitiously beautiful names.
To any one who has studied London, such a title as
‘Paradise Court’ conjures up a dark fetid
alley, with untidy fat women gossiping in it, untidy
thin women quarrelling across it, a host of haggard
and shapeless children sprawling in its mud, and one
or two drunken men propped against its walls.
Thus, were there an official nomenclator of streets,
he might be tempted to reject such names as in themselves
signify anything beautiful. But his main principle
would be to bestow whatever name first occurred to
him, in order that he might save time for thinking
about something that really mattered.
I have yet to fulfil the second part
of my promise: show the futility of trying to
commemorate a hero by making a street his namesake.
By implication I have done this already. But,
for the benefit of the less nimble among my readers,
let me be explicit. Who, passing through the
Cromwell Road, ever thinks of Cromwell, except by accident?
What journalist ever thinks of Wellington in Wellington
Street? In Marlborough Street, what policeman
remembers Marlborough? In St. James’s Street,
has any one ever fancied he saw the ghost of a pilgrim
wrapped in a cloak, leaning on a staff? Other
ghosts are there in plenty. The phantom chariot
of Lord Petersham dashes down the slope nightly.
Nightly Mr. Ball Hughes appears in the bow-window of
White’s. At cock-crow Charles James Fox
still emerges from Brooks’s. Such men as
these were indigenous to the street. Nothing will
ever lay their ghosts there. But the ghost of
St. James — what should it do in that galley?...
Of all the streets that have been named after famous
men, I know but one whose namesake is suggested by
it. In Regent Street you do sometimes think of
the Regent; and that is not because the street is
named after him, but because it was conceived by him,
and was designed and built under his auspices, and
is redolent of his character and his time. When
a national hero is to be commemorated by a street,
he must be allowed to design the street himself.
The mere plastering-up of his name is no mnemonic.