RIGHTS AND FUNCTIONS
A function may be defined as an activity
which embodies and expresses the idea of social purpose.
The essence of it is that the agent does not perform
it merely for personal gain or to gratify himself,
but recognizes that he is responsible for its discharge
to some higher authority. The purpose of industry
is obvious. It is to supply man with things
which are necessary, useful or beautiful, and thus
to bring life to body or spirit. In so far as
it is governed by this end, it is among the most important
of human activities. In so far as it is diverted
from it, it may be harmless, amusing, or even exhilarating
to those who carry it on, but it possesses no more
social significance than the orderly business of ants
and bees, the strutting of peacocks, or the struggles
of carnivorous animals over carrion.
Men have normally appreciated this
fact, however unwilling or unable they may have been
to act upon it; and therefore from time to time, in
so far as they have been able to control the forces
of violence and greed, they have adopted various expedients
for emphasizing the social quality of economic activity.
It is not easy, however, to emphasize it effectively,
because to do so requires a constant effort of will,
against which egotistical instincts are in rebellion,
and because, if that will is to prevail, it must be
embodied in some social and political organization,
which may itself become so arbitrary, tyrannical and
corrupt as to thwart the performance of function instead
of promoting it. When this process of degeneration
has gone far, as in most European countries it had
by the middle of the eighteenth century, the indispensable
thing is to break the dead organization up and to
clear the ground. In the course of doing so,
the individual is emancipated and his rights are enlarged;
but the idea of social purpose is discredited by the
discredit justly attaching to the obsolete order in
which it is embodied.
It is not surprising, therefore, that
in the new industrial societies which arose on the
ruins of the old regime the dominant note should have
been the insistence upon individual rights, irrespective
of any social purpose to which their exercise contributed.
The economic expansion which concentrated population
on the coal-measures was, in essence, an immense movement
of colonization drifting from the south and east to
the north and west; and it was natural that in those
regions of England, as in the American settlements,
the characteristic philosophy should be that of the
pioneer and the mining camp. The change of social
quality was profound. But in England, at least,
it was gradual, and the “industrial revolution,”
though catastrophic in its effects, was only the visible
climax of generations of subtle moral change.
The rise of modern economic relations, which may be
dated in England from the latter half of the seventeenth
century, was coincident with the growth of a political
theory which replaced the conception of purpose by
that of mechanism. During a great part of history
men had found the significance of their social
order in its relation to the universal purposes of
religion. It stood as one rung in a ladder which
stretched from hell to Paradise, and the classes who
composed it were the hands, the feet, the head of
a corporate body which was itself a microcosm imperfectly
reflecting a larger universe. When the Reformation
made the Church a department of the secular government,
it undermined the already enfeebled spiritual forces
which had erected that sublime, but too much elaborated,
synthesis. But its influence remained for nearly
a century after the roots which fed it had been severed.
It was the atmosphere into which men were born, and
from which, however practical, or even Machiavellian,
they could not easily disengage their spirits.
Nor was it inconvenient for the new statecraft to
see the weight of a traditional religious sanction
added to its own concern in the subordination of all
classes and interests to the common end, of which
it conceived itself, and during the greater part of
the sixteenth century was commonly conceived, to be
the guardian. The lines of the social structure
were no longer supposed to reproduce in miniature
the plan of a universal order. But common habits,
common traditions and beliefs, common pressure from
above gave them a unity of direction, which restrained
the forces of individual variation and lateral expansion;
and the center towards which they converged, formerly
a Church possessing some of the characteristics of
a State, was now a State that had clothed itself with
many of the attributes of a Church.
The difference between the England
of Shakespeare, still visited by the ghosts of
the Middle Ages, and the England which merged in 1700
from the fierce polemics of the last two generations,
was a difference of social and political theory even
more than of constitutional and political arrangements.
Not only the facts, but the minds which appraised
them, were profoundly modified. The essence of
the change was the disappearance of the idea that
social institutions and economic activities were related
to common ends, which gave them their significance
and which served as their criterion. In the eighteenth
century both the State and the Church had abdicated
that part of the sphere which had consisted in the
maintenance of a common body of social ethics; what
was left of it was repression of a class, not the
discipline of a nation. Opinion ceased to regard
social institutions and economic activity as amenable,
like personal conduct, to moral criteria, because
it was no longer influenced by the spectacle of institutions
which, arbitrary, capricious, and often corrupt in
their practical operation, had been the outward symbol
and expression of the subordination of life to purposes
transcending private interests. That part of
government which had been concerned with social administration,
if it did not end, became at least obsolescent.
For such democracy as had existed in the Middle Ages
was dead, and the democracy of the Revolution was
not yet born, so that government passed into the lethargic
hand of classes who wielded the power of the State
in the interests of an irresponsible aristocracy.
And the Church was even more remote from the daily
life of mankind than the State. Philanthropy
abounded; but religion, once the greatest social
force, had become a thing as private and individual
as the estate of the squire or the working clothes
of the laborer. There were special dispensations
and occasional interventions, like the acts of a monarch
who reprieved a criminal or signed an order for his
execution. But what was familiar, and human
and lovable what was Christian in Christianity
had largely disappeared. God had been thrust
into the frigid altitudes of infinite space.
There was a limited monarchy in Heaven, as well as
upon earth. Providence was the spectator of the
curious machine which it had constructed and set in
motion, but the operation of which it was neither
able nor willing to control. Like the occasional
intervention of the Crown in the proceedings of Parliament,
its wisdom was revealed in the infrequency of its
interference.
The natural consequence of the abdication
of authorities which had stood, however imperfectly,
for a common purpose in social organization, was the
gradual disappearance from social thought of the idea
of purpose itself. Its place in the eighteenth
century was taken by the idea of mechanism.
The conception of men as united to each other, and
of all mankind as united to God, by mutual obligations
arising from their relation to a common end, which
vaguely conceived and imperfectly realized, had been
the keystone holding together the social fabric, ceased
to be impressed upon men’s minds, when Church
and State withdrew from the center of social life
to its circumference. What remained when the
keystone of the arch was removed, was private rights
and private interests, the materials of a society rather
than a society itself. These rights and
interests were the natural order which had been distorted
by the ambitions of kings and priests, and which emerged
when the artificial super-structure disappeared, because
they were the creation, not of man, but of Nature herself.
They had been regarded in the past as relative to some
public end, whether religion or national welfare.
Henceforward they were thought to be absolute and
indefeasible, and to stand by their own virtue.
They were the ultimate political and social reality;
and since they were the ultimate reality, they were
not subordinate to other aspects of society, but other
aspects of society were subordinate to them.
The State could not encroach upon
these rights, for the State existed for their maintenance.
They determined the relation of classes, for the
most obvious and fundamental of all rights was property property
absolute and unconditioned and those who
possessed it were regarded as the natural governors
of those who did not. Society arose from their
exercise, through the contracts of individual with
individual. It fulfilled its object in so far
as, by maintaining contractual freedom, it secured
full scope for their unfettered exercise. It
failed in so far as, like the French monarchy, it
overrode them by the use of an arbitrary authority.
Thus conceived, society assumed something of the
appearance of a great joint-stock company, in which
political power and the receipt of dividends were
justly assigned to those who held the most numerous
shares. The currents of social activity did not
converge upon common ends, but were dispersed through
a multitude of channels, created by the private
interests of the individuals who composed society.
But in their very variety and spontaneity, in the
very absence of any attempt to relate them to a larger
purpose than that of the individual, lay the best
security of its attainment. There is a mysticism
of reason as well as of emotion, and the eighteenth
century found, in the beneficence of natural instincts,
a substitute for the God whom it had expelled from
contact with society, and did not hesitate to identify
them.
“Thus God and nature planned the
general frame
And bade self-love and social be the same.”
The result of such ideas in the world
of practice was a society which was ruled by law,
not by the caprice of Governments, but which recognized
no moral limitation on the pursuit by individuals of
their economic self-interest. In the world of
thought, it was a political philosophy which made
rights the foundation of the social order, and which
considered the discharge of obligations, when it considered
it at all, as emerging by an inevitable process from
their free exercise. The first famous exponent
of this philosophy was Locke, in whom the dominant
conception is the indefeasibility of private rights,
not the pre-ordained harmony between private rights
and public welfare. In the great French writers
who prepared the way for the Revolution, while believing
that they were the servants of an enlightened absolutism,
there is an almost equal emphasis upon the sanctity
of rights and upon the infallibility of the alchemy
by which the pursuit of private ends is transmuted
into the attainment of public good. Though their
writings reveal the influence of the conception of
society as a self-adjusting mechanism, which afterwards
became the most characteristic note of the English
individualism, what the French Revolution burned into
the mind of Europe was the former not the latter.
In England the idea of right had been negative and
defensive, a barrier to the encroachment of Governments.
The French leapt to the attack from trenches which
the English had been content to defend, and in France
the idea became affirmative and militant, not a weapon
of defense, but a principle of social organization.
The attempt to refound society upon rights, and rights
springing not from musty charters, but from the very
nature of man himself, was at once the triumph and
the limitation of the Revolution. It gave it
the enthusiasm and infectious power of religion.
What happened in England might seem
at first sight to have been precisely the reverse.
English practical men, whose thoughts were pitched
in a lower key, were a little shocked by the pomp and
brilliance of that tremendous creed. They had
scanty sympathy with the absolute affirmations of
France. What captured their imagination was
not the right to liberty, which made no appeal to their
commercial instincts, but the expediency of liberty,
which did; and when the Revolution had revealed the
explosive power of the idea of natural right, they
sought some less menacing formula. It had been
offered them first by Adam Smith and his precursors,
who showed how the mechanism of economic life
converted “as with an invisible hand,”
the exercise of individual rights into the instrument
of public good. Bentham, who despised metaphysical
subtleties, and thought the Declaration of the Rights
of Man as absurd as any other dogmatic religion, completed
the new orientation by supplying the final criterion
of political institutions in the principle of Utility.
Henceforward emphasis was transferred from the right
of the individual to exercise his freedom as he pleased
to the expediency of an undisturbed exercise of freedom
to society.
The change is significant. It
is the difference between the universal and equal
citizenship of France, with its five million peasant
proprietors, and the organized inequality of England
established solidly upon class traditions and class
institutions; the descent from hope to resignation,
from the fire and passion of an age of illimitable
vistas to the monotonous beat of the factory engine,
from Turgot and Condorcet to the melancholy mathematical
creed of Bentham and Ricardo and James Mill.
Mankind has, at least, this superiority over its
philosophers, that great movements spring from the
heart and embody a faith; not the nice adjustments
of the hedonistic calculus. So in the name of
the rights of property France abolished in three years
a great mass of property rights which, under the old
regime had robbed the peasant of part of the produce
of his labor, and the social transformation survived
a whole world of political changes. In England
the glad tidings of democracy were broken too discreetly
to reach the ears of the hind in the furrow or the
shepherd on the hill; there were political changes
without a social transformation. The doctrine
of Utility, though trenchant in the sphere of politics,
involved no considerable interference with the fundamentals
of the social fabric. Its exponents were principally
concerned with the removal of political abuses and
legal anomalies. They attacked sinécures
and pensions and the criminal code and the procedure
of the law courts. But they touched only the
surface of social institutions. They thought
it a monstrous injustice that the citizen should pay
one-tenth of his income in taxation to an idle Government,
but quite reasonable that he should pay one-fifth
of it in rent to an idle landlord.
The difference, neverthelesss, was
one of emphasis and expression, not of principle.
It mattered very little in practice whether private
property and unfettered economic freedom were stated,
as in France, to be natural rights, or whether, as
in England, they were merely assumed once for all
to be expedient. In either case they were taken
for granted as the fundamentals upon which social
organization was to be based, and about which no further
argument was admissible. Though Bentham argued
that rights were derived from utility, not from nature,
he did not push his analysis so far as to argue that
any particular right was relative to any particular
function, and thus endorsed indiscriminately rights
which were not accompanied by service as well as rights
which were. While eschewing, in short, the phraseology
of natural rights, the English Utilitarians retained
something not unlike the substance of them.
For they assumed that private property in land,
and the private ownership of capital, were natural
institutions, and gave them, indeed, a new lease of
life, by proving to their own satisfaction that social
well-being must result from their continued exercise.
Their negative was as important as their positive
teaching. It was a conductor which diverted the
lightning. Behind their political theory, behind
the practical conduct, which as always, continues
to express theory long after it has been discredited
in the world of thought, lay the acceptance of absolute
rights to property and to economic freedom as the
unquestioned center of social organization.
The result of that attitude was momentous.
The motive and inspiration of the Liberal Movement
of the eighteenth century had been the attack on Privilege.
But the creed which had exorcised the specter of
agrarian feudalism haunting village and chateau
in France, was impotent to disarm the new ogre of
industrialism which was stretching its limbs in the
north of England. When, shorn of its splendors
and illusions, liberalism triumphed in England in
1832, it carried without criticism into the new world
of capitalist industry categories of private property
and freedom of contract which had been forged in the
simpler economic environment of the pre-industrial
era. In England these categories are being bent
and twisted till they are no longer recognizable,
and will, in time, be made harmless. In America,
where necessity compelled the crystallization of principles
in a constitution, they have the rigidity of an iron
jacket. The magnificent formulae in which a
society of farmers and master craftsmen enshrined
its philosophy of freedom are in danger of becoming
fetters used by an Anglo-Saxon business aristocracy
to bind insurgent movements on the part of an immigrant
and semi-servile proletariat.