THE METHOD OF PROGRESS
Progress as an ideal is quite modern
in its origin. For although the ancients were
progressing, they did it unconsciously, blindly, stumbling
on it by chance, forced to it, as we have seen, by
the struggle for existence. True of the ancient
civilizations of Europe and Western Asia and Africa,
this is emphatically true of the Orient. Here,
so far from seeking to progress, the avowed aim has
been not to progress; the set purpose has been to
do as the fathers did; to follow their example even
in customs and rites whose meaning has been lost in
the obscurity of the past. This blind adherence
was the boast of those who called themselves religious.
They strove to fulfill their duties to their ancestors.
Under such conditions how was progress
possible? And how has it come to pass that, ruled
by this ideal until less than fifty years ago, Japan
is now facing quite the other way? The passion
of the nation to-day is to make the greatest possible
progress in every direction. Here is an anomaly,
a paradox; progress made in spite of its rejection;
and, recently, a total volte-face. How
shall we explain this paradox?
In our chapter on the Principles of
National Evolution, we see that the first step
in progress was made through the development of enlarging
communities by means of extending boundaries and hardening
customs. We see that, on reaching this stage,
the great problem was so to break the “cake
of custom” as to give liberty to individuals
whereby to secure the needful variations. We do
not consider how this was to be accomplished.
We merely show that, if further progress was to be
made, it could only be through the development of the
individualistic principle to which we give the more
exact name communo-individualism. This problem
as to how the “cake of custom” is successfully
broken must now engage our attention.
Mr. Bagehot contends that this process
consisted, as a matter of history, in the establishment
of government by discussion. Matters of principle
came to be talked over; the desirability of this or
that measure was submitted to the people for their
approval or disapproval. This method served to
stimulate definite and practical thought on a wide
scale; it substituted the thinking of the many for
the thinking of the few; it stimulated independent
thinking and consequently independent action.
This is, however, but another way of saying that it
stimulated variation. A government whose action
was determined after wide discussion would be peculiarly
fitted to take advantage of all useful variations
of ideas and practice. Experience shows, he continues,
that the difficulty of developing a “cake of
custom” is far more easily surmounted than that
of developing government by discussion; i.e.,
that it is far less difficult to develop communalism
than communo-individualism. The family of arrested
civilizations, of which China and India and Japan,
until recent times, are examples, were caught in the
net of what had once been the source of their progress.
The tyranny of their laws and customs was such that
all individual variations were nipped in the bud.
They failed to progress because they failed to develop
variations. And they failed in this because they
did not have government by discussion.
No one will dispute the importance
of Mr. Bagehot’s, contribution to this subject.
But it may be doubted whether he has pointed out the
full reason for the difficulty of breaking the “cake
of custom” or manifested the real root of progress.
To attain progress in the full sense, not merely of
an oligarchy or a caste, but of the whole people,
there must not only be government by discussion, but
the responsibilities of the government must be snared
more or less fully by all the governed.
History, however, shows that this
cannot take place until a conception of intrinsic
manhood and womanhood has arisen, a conception which
emphasizes their infinite and inherent worth.
This conception is not produced by government by discussion,
while government by discussion is the necessary consequence
of the wide acceptance of this conception. It
is therefore the real root of progress.
As I look over the history of the
Orient, I find no tendency to discover the inherent
worth of man or to introduce the principle of government
by discussion. Left to themselves, I see no probability
that any of these nations would ever have been able
to break the thrall of their customs, and to reach
that stage of development in which common individuals
could be trusted with a large measure of individual
liberty. Though I can conceive that Japan might
have secured a thorough-going political centralization
under the old regime, I cannot see that that
centralization would have been accompanied by growing
liberty for the individual or by such constitutional
rights for the common man as he enjoys to-day.
Whatever progress she might have made in the direction
of nationality it would still have been a despotism.
The common man would have remained a helpless and
hopeless slave. Art might have prospered; the
people might have remained simple-minded and relatively
contented. But they could not have attained that
freedom and richness of life, that personality, which
we saw in our last chapter to be the criterion and
goal of true progress.
If the reader judges the above contention
correct and agrees with the writer that the conception
of the inherent value of a human being could not arise
spontaneously in Japan, he will conclude that the
progress of Japan depended on securing this important
conception from without. Exactly this has taken
place. By her thorough-going abandonment of the
feudal social order and adoption of the constitutional
and representative government of Christendom, whether
she recognizes it or not, she has accepted the principles
of the inherent worth of manhood and womanhood, as
well as government by discussion. Japan has thus,
by imitation rather than by origination, entered on
the path of endless progress.
So important, however, is the step
recently taken that further analysis of this method
of progress is desirable for its full comprehension.
We have already noted quite briefly how Japan was
supplied by the West with the ideal of national unity
and the material instruments essential to its attainment.
In connection with the high development of the nation
as a whole, these two elements of progress, the ideal
and the material, need further consideration.
We note in the first place that both
begin with imitation, but if progress is to be real
and lasting, both must grow to independence.
The first and by far the most important
is the psychical, the introduction of new ideas.
So long as the old, familiar ideas hold sway over
the mind of a nation, there is little or no stimulus
to comparison and discussion. Stagnation is well-nigh
complete. But let new ideas be so introduced
as to compel attention and comprehension, and the
mind spontaneously awakes to wonderful activity.
The old stagnation is no longer possible. Discussion
is started; and in the end something must take place,
even if the new ideas are not accepted wholly or even
in part. But they will not gain attention if presented
simply in the abstract, unconnected with real life.
They must bring evidence that, if accepted and lived,
they will be of practical use, that they will give
added power to the nation.
Exactly this took place in 1854 when
Admiral Perry demanded entrance to Japan. The
people suddenly awoke from their sleep of two and a
half centuries to find that new nations had arisen
since they closed their eyes, nations among which
new sets of ideas had been at work, giving them a
power wholly unknown to the Orient and even mysterious
to it. Those ideas were concerned, not alone
with the making of guns, the building of ships, the
invention of machinery, the taming and using of the
forces of nature, but also with methods of government
and law, with strange notions, too, about religion
and duty, about the family and the individual, which
the foreigners said were of inestimable value and
importance. It needed but a few years of intercourse
with Western peoples to convince the most conservative
that unless the Japanese themselves could gain the
secret of their power, either by adopting their weapons
or their civilization, they themselves must fade away
before the stronger nations. The need of self-preservation
was the first great stimulus that drove new thoughts
into unwilling brains.
There can be no doubt that the Japanese
were right in this analysis of the situation.
Had they insisted on maintaining their old methods
of national life and social order and ancient customs,
there can be no doubt as to the result. Africa
and India in recent decades and China and Korea in
the most recent years tell the story all too clearly.
Those who know the course of treaty conferences and
armed collisions, as at Shimonoseki and Kagoshima
between Japan and the foreign nations, have no doubt
that Japan, divided into clans and persisting in her
love of feudalism, would long since have become the
territory of some European Power. She was saved
by the possession of a remarkable combination of national
characteristics, the powers of observation,
of appreciation, and of imitation. In a word,
her sensitiveness to her environment and her readiness
to respond to it proved to be her salvation.
But the point on which I wish to lay
special emphasis is that the prime element of the
form in which the deliverance came was through the
acquisition of numerous new ideas. These were
presented by persons who thoroughly believed in them
and who admittedly had a power not possessed by the
Japanese themselves. Though unable to originate
these ideas, the Japanese yet proved themselves capable
of understanding and appreciating them in
a measure at least. They were at first attracted
to that which related chiefly to the externals of civilization,
to that which would contribute immediately to the
complete political centralization of the nation.
With great rapidity they adopted Western ideas about
warfare and weapons. They sent their young men
abroad to study the civilization of the foreign nations.
At great expense they also employed many foreigners
to teach them in their own land the things they wished
to learn. Thus have the Japanese mastered so
rapidly the details of those ideas which, less than
fifty years ago, were not only strange but odious
to them.
Under their influence, the conditions
which history shows to be the most conducive to the
continuous growth of civilization have been definitely
accepted and adopted by the people, namely, popular
rights, the liberty of individuals to differ from
the past so far as this does not interfere with national
unity, and the direct responsibility and relation
of each individual to the nation without any mediating
group. These rights and liberties are secured
to the individual by a constitution and by laws enacted
by representative legislatures. Government by
discussion has been fairly inaugurated.
During these years of change the effort
has been to leave the old social order as undisturbed
as possible. For example, it was hoped that the
reorganization of the military and naval forces of
the Empire would be sufficient without disturbing
the feudal order and without abolishing the feudal
states. But this was soon found ineffectual.
For a time it was likewise thought that the adoption
of Western methods of government might be made without
disturbing the old religious ideas and without removing
the edicts against Christianity. But experience
soon showed that the old civilization was a unit.
No part could be vitally modified without affecting
the whole structure. Having knocked over one
block in the long row that made up their feudal social
order, it was found that each successive block was
touched and fell, until nothing was left standing
as before. It was found also that the old ideas
of education, of travel, of jurisprudence, of torture
and punishment, of social ranks, of the relation of
the individual to the state, of the state to the family,
and of religion to the family, were more or less defective
and unsuited to the new civilization. Before
this new movement all obstructive ideas, however, sanctioned
by antiquity, have had to give way. The Japanese
of to-day look, as it were, upon a new earth and a
new heaven. Those of forty years ago would be
amazed, not only at the enormous changes in the externals,
life and government, but also at the transformation
which has overtaken every element of the older civilization.
Putting it rather strongly, it is now not the son
who obeys the father, but the father the son.
The rulers no longer command the people, but the people
command the rulers. The people do not now toil
to support the state; but the state toils to protect
the people.
Whether the incoming of these new
ideas and practices be thought to constitute progress
or not will depend on one’s view of the aim of
life. If this be as maintained in the previous
chapter, then surely the transformation of Japan must
be counted progress. That, however, to which
I call attention is the fact that the essential requisite
of progress is the attainment of new ideas, whatever
be their source. Japan has not only taken up
a great host of these, but in doing so she has adopted
a social structure to stimulate the continuous production
of new ideas, through the development of individuality.
She is thus in the true line of continuously progressive
evolution. Imitating the stronger nations, she
has introduced into her system the life-giving blood
of free discussion, popular education, and universal
individual rights and liberty. In a word, she
has begun to be an individualistic nation. She
has introduced a social order fitted to a wide development
of personality.
The importance of the second line
of progress, the physical, would seem to be too obvious
to call for any detailed consideration. But so
much has been said by both graceful and able writers
on Japan as to the advantages she enjoys from her
simple non-mechanical civilization, and the mistake
she is making in adopting the mechanical civilization
of the West, that it may not be amiss to dwell for
a few moments upon it. I wish to show that the
second element of progress consists in the increasing
use of mechanisms.
The enthusiastic admirer of Japan
hardly finds words wherewith sufficiently to praise
the simplicity of her pre-Meiji civilization.
No furniture brings confusion to the room; no machinery
distresses the ear with its groanings or the eye with
its unsightliness. No factories blacken the sky
with smoke. No trains screeching through the towns
and cities disturb sleepers and frighten babies.
The simple bed on the floor, the straw sandal on the
foot, wooden chopsticks in place of knives and forks,
the small variety of foods and of cooking utensils,
the simple, homespun cotton clothing, the fascinating
homes, so small and neat and clean in truth
all that pertains to Old Japan finds favor in the
eyes of the enthusiastic admirer from the Occident.
One such writer, in an elaborate paper intended to
set forth the superiority of the original Japanese
to the Occidental civilization, uses the following
language: “Ability to live without furniture,
without impedimenta, with the least possible amount
of neat clothing, shows more than the advantage held
by the Japanese race in the struggle of life; it shows
also the real character of some of the weaknesses
in our own civilization. It forces reflection
upon the useless multiplicity of our daily wants.
We must have meat and bread and butter; glass windows
and fire; hats, white shirts, and woolen underwear;
boots and shoes; trunks, bags, and boxes; bedsteads,
mattresses, sheets, and blankets; all of which a Japanese
can do without, and is really better off without."
Surely one finds much of truth in this, and there
is no denying the charm of the simpler civilization,
but the closing phrase of the quotation is the assumption
without discussion of the disputed point. Are
the Japanese really better off without these implements
of Western civilization? Evidently they themselves
do not think so. For, in glancing through the
list as given by the writer quoted, one realizes the
extent of Japanese adoption of these Western devices.
Hardly an article but is used in Japan, and certainly
with the supposition of the purchaser that it adds
either to his health or his comfort. In witness
are the hundreds of thousands of straw hats, the glass
windows everywhere, and the meat-shops in each town
and city of the Empire. The charm of a foreign
fashion is not sufficient explanation for the rapidly
spreading use of foreign inventions.
That there are no useless or even
evil features in our Western civilization is not for
a moment contended. The stiff starched shirt
may certainly be asked to give an account of itself
and justify its continued existence, if it can.
But I think the proposition is capable of defense
that the vast majority of the implements of our Occidental
civilization have their definite place and value, either
in contributing directly to the comfort and happiness
of their possessor, or in increasing his health and
strength and general mental and physical power.
What is it that makes the Occidental longer-lived than
the Japanese? Why is he healthier? Why is
he more intelligent? Why is he a more developed
personality? Why are his children more energetic?
Or, reversing the questions, why has the population
of Japan been increasing with leaps and bounds since
the introduction of Western civilization and medical
science? Why is the rising generation so free
from pockmarks? Why is the number of the blind
steadily diminishing? Why are mechanisms multiplying
so rapidly the jinrikisha, the railroads,
the roads, the waterworks and sewers, the chairs, the
tables, the hats and umbrellas, lamps, clocks, glass
windows and shoes? A hundred similar questions
might be asked, to which no definite answers are needful.
Further discussion of details seems
unnecessary. Yet the full significance of this
point can hardly be appreciated without a perception
of the great principle that underlies it. The
only way in which man has become and continues to
be increasingly superior to animals is in his use
of mechanisms. The animal does by brute force
what man accomplishes by various devices. The
inventiveness of different races differs vastly.
But everywhere, the most advanced are the most powerful.
Take the individual man of the more developed race
and separate him from his tools and machines, and it
is doubtless true that he cannot in some selected
points compete with an individual of a less developed
race. But let ten thousand men of the higher
development compete with ten thousand of the lower,
each using the mechanisms under his control, and can
there be any doubt as to which is the superior?
In other words, the method of human
progress consists, in no small degree, in the progressive
mastery of nature, first through understanding her
and then through the use of her immense forces by
means of suitable mechanisms. All the machines
and furniture, and tools and clothing, and houses
and canned foods, and shoes and boots, and railroads
and telegraph lines, and typewriters and watches, and
the ten thousand other so-called “impedimenta”
of the Occidental civilization are but devices whereby
Western man has sought to increase his health, his
wealth, his knowledge, his comfort, his independence,
his capacity of travel in a word, his well-being.
Through these mechanisms he masters nature. He
extracts a rich living from nature; he annihilates
time and space; he defies the storms; he tunnels the
mountains; he extracts precious ores and metals from
the rock-ribbed hills; with a magic touch he loosens
the grip of the elements and makes them surrender
their gold, their silver, and, more precious still,
their iron; with these he builds his spacious cities
and parks, his railroads and ocean steamers; he travels
the whole world around, fearing neither beast nor
alien man; all are subject to his command and will.
He investigates and knows the constitution of stellar
worlds no less than that of the world in which he lives.
By his instruments he explores the infinite depths
of heaven and the no less infinite depths of the microscopic
world. All these reviled “impedimenta”
thus bring to the race that has them a wealth of life
both physical and psychical, practical and ideal, that
is otherwise unattainable. By them he gains and
gives external expression to the reality of his inner
nature, his freedom, his personality. True, instead
of bringing health and long life, knowledge and deep
enjoyment, they may become the means of bitterest curses.
But the lesson to learn from this fact is how to use
these powers aright, not how to forbid their use altogether.
They are not to be branded as hindrances to progress.
The defect of Occidental civilization
to-day is hot its multiplicity of machinery, but the
defective view that still blinds the eyes of the multitude
as to the true nature and the legitimate goal of progress.
Individual, selfish happiness is still the ideal of
too many men and women to permit of the ideal which
carries the Golden Rule into the markets and factories,
into the politics of parties and nations, which is
essential to the attainment of the highest progress.
But no one who casts his eyes over the centuries of
struggle and effort through which man has been slowly
working his way upward from the rank of a beast to
that of a man, can doubt that progress has been made.
The worth of character has been increasingly seen
and its possession desired. The true end of effort
and development was never more clear than it is at
the close of the nineteenth century. Never before
were the conditions of progress so bright, not only
for the favored few in one or two lands, but for the
multitudes the world over. Isolation and separation
have passed from this world forever. Free social
intercourse between the nations permits wide dissemination
of ideas and their application to practical life in
the form of social organization and mechanical invention.
This makes it possible for nations more or less backward
in social and civilizational development to gain in
a relatively short time the advantages won by advanced
nations through ages of toil and under favoring circumstances.
Nation thus stimulates nation, each furnishing the
other with important variations in ideas, customs,
institutions, and mechanisms resulting from long-continued
divergent evolution. The advantages slowly gained
by advanced peoples speedily accrues through social
heredity to any backward race really desiring to enter
the social heritage.
Thus does the paradox of Japan’s
recent progress become thoroughly intelligible.