PRACTICAL APPLICATIONS OF THE MORAL TEST.
In this chapter I propose, without
any attempt to be exhaustive or systematic, to give
some examples of the manner in which the test of conduct
may be applied to practical questions, either by extending
existing rules to cases which do not obviously fall
under them, or by suggesting more refined maxims of
conduct than those which are commonly prevalent.
In either case, I am accepting the somewhat invidious
task of pointing out defects in the commonly received
theory, or the commonly approved practice, of morality.
But, if morality is progressive, as I contend that
it is, and progresses by the application to conduct
of a test which itself involves a growing conception,
the best mode of exhibiting the application of that
test will be in the more recent acquisitions or the
more subtle deductions of morality, rather than in
its fundamental rules or most acknowledged maxims.
I shall begin with a topic, the examples
of which are ready to hand, and may easily be multiplied,
to almost any extent, by the reader for himself the
better realisation of our duties to society at large
as distinct from particular individuals. When
the primary mischief resulting from a wrong act falls
upon individuals, and especially upon our neighbours
or those with whom we are constantly associating, it
can hardly escape our observation. And, even
if it does, the probability is that our attention
will be quickly called to it by the reprobation of
others. But, when the consequences of the act
are diffused over the whole community, or a large
aggregate of persons, so that the effect on each individual
is almost imperceptible, we are very apt to overlook
the mischief resulting from it, and so not to recognise
its wrongful character, while, at the same time, from
lack of personal interest, others fail to call us
to account. Hence it is that men, almost without
any thought, and certainly often without any scruple,
commit offences against the public or against corporations
or societies or companies, which they would themselves
deem it impossible for them to commit against individuals.
And yet the character of the acts is exactly the same.
Take smuggling. A man smuggles cigars or tobacco
to an amount by which he saves himself twenty shillings,
and defrauds the state to the same extent. This
is simply an act of theft, only that the object of
the theft is the community at large and not an individual.
So far as the mischief or wrongfulness of the act
goes, apart from the intention of the agent, he might
as well put his hands into the pocket of one of his
fellow-passengers and extract the same amount of money.
The twenty shillings which, by evading payment of
the duty, he has appropriated to his own uses, has
been taken from the rest of the tax-payers, and he
has simply shifted on to them the obligation which
properly attached to himself. Sooner or later
they must make up the deficit. If many men were
to act in the same way, the burden of the honest tax-payer
would be largely increased, and, if the practice became
general, the state would have to resort to some other
mode of taxation or collect its customs-revenue at
a most disproportionate cost. Thus, a little
reflexion shows that smuggling is really theft, and
I cannot but think that it would be to the moral as
well as the material advantage of the community if
it were called by that name, and were visited with
the same punishment as petty larceny. Exactly
the same remarks, of course, apply to the evasion
of income-tax, or of rates or taxes of any kind, which
are imposed by a legitimate authority. Travelling
on a railway without a ticket or in a higher class
or for a greater distance than that for which the
ticket was taken is, similarly, only a thinly disguised
case of theft, and should be treated accordingly.
The sale or purchase of pirated editions of books
is another case of the same kind, the persons from
whom the money is stolen being the authors or publishers.
Many paltry acts of pilfering, such as the unauthorised
use of government-paper or franks, or purloining novels
or letter-paper from a club, or plucking flowers in
a public garden, fall under the same head of real,
though not always obvious, thefts. There is, of
course, a certain degree of pettiness which makes
them insignificant, but there is always a danger lest
men should think too lightly of acts of this kind,
whether done by themselves or others. The best
safeguard, perhaps, against thoughtless wrong-doing
to the community or large social aggregates is to
ask ourselves these two questions: Should we commit
this act, or what should we think of a man who did
commit it, in the case of a private individual?
What would be the result, if every one who had the
opportunity were to do the same? Many of these
acts would, then, stand out in their true light, and
we should recognise that they are not only mean but
criminal.
Other, but analogous, instances of
the failure of men to realise their obligations to
society or to large social aggregates are to be found
in the careless and perfunctory manner in which persons
employed by government, or by corporations, or large
companies, often perform their duties. If they
were in the service of a private employer, they would
at all events realise, even if they did not act on
their conviction, that they were defrauding him by
idling away their time or attending to their own affairs,
or those of charities or institutions in which they
were interested, when they ought to be attending to
the concerns of their employer. But in a government
or municipal office, or the establishment of a large
company, no one in particular seems to be injured by
the ineffective discharge of their functions; and
hence it does not occur to them that they are receiving
their wages without rendering the equivalent of them.
The inadequate supervision which overlooks or condones
this listlessness is, of course, itself also the result
of a similar failure to realise responsibility.
The spirit in which patronage is often
administered affords an instance of a similar kind.
If a man were engaging a person to perform some service
for himself or his family, or one of his intimate friends,
he would simply look to competency, including, perhaps,
moral character, for the special work to be done.
But, when he has to appoint to a public post, and
especially if he is only one of a board of electors,
he is very apt to think that there is no great harm
in appointing or voting for a relative or friend,
or a person who has some special bond of connexion
with him, such as that of political party, though he
may not be the candidate best qualified for the position.
And, if it does occur to him that he is acting wrongly,
he is more likely to think of the wrong which he is
doing to the individual who possesses the highest
qualifications (and to him it is an undoubted wrong,
for it frustrates just expectations) than of the wrong
which he is doing to the community or the institution
which he is depriving of the services of the fittest
man. And yet, if he takes the trouble to reflect,
he must see that he is guilty of a breach of trust;
that, having undertaken a public duty, he has abused
the confidence reposed in him.
A vote given in return for a bribe,
a case which now seldom occurs except in parliamentary
elections, is open to the same ethical objections
as a vote given on grounds of partiality; and, as the
motive which dictates the breach of trust is purely
selfish, it incurs the additional reproach of meanness.
But why, it may be asked, should not a man accept
a bribe, if, on other grounds, he would vote for the
candidate who offers it? Simply, because he is
encouraging a practice which would, in time, deprive
Parliament of most of its more competent members,
and reduce it to an oligarchy of millionaires, as well
as degrading himself by a sordid act. To receive
a present for a vote, even if the vote be given conscientiously,
is to lend countenance to a practice which must inevitably
corrupt the consciences, and pervert the judgment,
of others. It hardly needs to be pointed out that
the man who offers the bribe is acting still more
immorally than the man who accepts it. He is
not only causing others to act immorally, but, as no
man can be a proper judge of his own competency, he
is attempting to thrust himself into an office of
trust without any regard to his fitness to fill it.
Intimidation, on the part of the man who practises
it, is on the same ethical level as bribery, with
respect to the two points just mentioned; but, as
it appeals to the fears of men instead of their love
of gain, and costs nothing to him who employs it, it
is more odious, and deserves, at the hands of the
law, a still more severe punishment. To yield
to intimidation is, under most circumstances, more
excusable than to yield to bribery; for the fear of
losing what one has is to most men a more powerful
inducement than the hope of gaining what one has not,
and, generally speaking, the penalty threatened by
the intimidator is far in excess of the advantage
offered by the briber.
As it betrays a vain and grasping
disposition, when a man attempts to thrust himself
into an office to which he is not called by the spontaneous
voice of his fellow-citizens, so to refuse office,
when there is an evident opportunity of doing good
service to the community, betrays pride or indolence,
coupled with an indifference to the public welfare.
In democratic communities, there is always a tendency
on the part of what may be called superfine persons
to hold aloof from public, and especially municipal,
life. If this sentiment of fastidiousness or
indifference were to spread widely, and a fashion which
begins in one social stratum quickly permeates to
those immediately below it, there would be great danger,
as there seems to be in America, of the public administration
becoming seriously and permanently deteriorated.
To prevent this evil, it is desirable to create, in
every community, a strong sentiment against the practice
of persons, who have the requisite means, leisure,
and ability, withholding themselves from public life,
when invited by their fellow-citizens to take their
part in it. There may, of course, be paramount
claims of another kind, such as those of science,
or art, or literature, or education, but the superior
importance of these claims on the individuals themselves,
where they obviously exist, and where the claims of
the public service are not urgent, would readily be
allowed.
It seems to be a rapid transition
from cases of this kind to suicide, but, amongst the
many reasons, moral and religious, which may be urged
against suicide, there is one which connects itself
closely with the considerations which have just been
under our notice. As pointed out long ago by
Aristotle, the suicide wrongs the state rather than
himself. Where a man is still able to do any
service to the state, in either a private or a public
capacity, he is under a social, and, therefore, a
moral obligation to perform that service, and, consequently,
to withdraw from it by a voluntary death is to desert
the post of duty. This consideration, of course,
holds only where a man’s life is still of value
to society, but it should be pointed out that, where
this ceases to be the case, many other considerations
often, and some always do, intervene. There are
few men who have not relatives, friends, or neighbours,
who will be pained, even if they are not injured materially,
by an act of suicide, and, wherever the injury is a
material one, as in the case of leaving helpless relatives
unprovided for, it becomes an act of cruelty.
Then, under all circumstances, there remain the evil
example of cowardice and, to those who acknowledge
the obligations of religion, the sin of cutting short
the period of probation which God has assigned us.
Amongst duties to society, which are
seldom fully realised in their social aspect, is the
duty of bringing up children in such a manner as to
render them useful to the state, instead of a burden
upon it. Under this head, there are two distinct
cases, that of the rich and that of the poor, or,
more precisely, that of those who are in sufficiently
good circumstances to educate their children without
the assistance of the state or of their neighbours,
and that of those who require such assistance.
In the latter case, it is the duty of society to co-operate
with the parent in giving the child an education which
shall fit it for the industrial occupations of life,
and hence the moral obligation on the richer members
of a community to provide elementary schools, aided
by the state or by some smaller political aggregate,
or else by voluntary efforts. The object of this
assistance is not so much charity to the parent or
the individual children, as the prevention of crime
and pauperism, and the supply of an orderly and competent
industrial class. In rendering the assistance,
whether it come from public or private funds, great
care ought to be taken not to weaken, but, rather to
stimulate, the interest of the parent in the child’s
progress, both by assigning to him a share of the
responsibility of supervision, and, if possible, by
compelling him to contribute an equitable proportion
of the cost. So largely, if not so fully, are
the duties of the state and of individuals of the
wealthier classes, in the matter of educating the
children of the poor, now recognised, that the dangers
arising from a defective or injudicious education
seem, in the immediate future, to threaten the richer
rather than the poorer classes. Over-indulgence
and the encouragement of luxurious habits during childhood;
the weakened sense of responsibility, on the part
of the parent, which is often caused by the transference
to others of authority and supervision during boyhood
or girlhood; the undue stimulation of the love of amusement,
or of the craving for material comforts, during the
opening years of manhood or womanhood; the failure
to create serious interests or teach adequately the
social responsibilities which wealth and position bring
with them, all these mistakes or defects
in the education of the children of the upper classes
constitute a grave peril to society, unless they are
remedied in time. It seems, so far as we can forecast
the future, that it is only by all classes taking pains
to ascertain their respective duties and functions
in sustaining and promoting the well-being of the
community, and making serious efforts to perform them,
that the society of the next few generations can be
saved from constant convulsions. As intelligence
expands, and a sense of the importance of social co-operation
becomes diffused, it is almost certain that the existence
of a merely idle and self-indulgent class will no longer
be tolerated. Hence, it is as much to the interests
of the wealthier classes themselves as of society
at large, that their children should be educated with
a full sense of their social responsibilities, and
equipped with all the moral and intellectual aptitudes
which are requisite to enable them to take a lead
in the development of the community of which they
are members.
And here, perhaps, I may take occasion
to draw attention to the importance of the acquisition
of political knowledge by all citizens of the state,
and especially by those who belong to the leisured
classes. It is a plain duty to society, that
men should not exercise political power, unless they
have some knowledge of the questions at issue.
The amount of this knowledge may vary almost infinitely,
from that of the veteran statesman to that of the
newly enfranchised elector, but it is within the power
of every one, who can observe and reason, to acquire
some knowledge of at least the questions which affect
his own employment and the welfare of his own family
and neighbourhood, and, unless he will take thus much
pains, he might surely have the modesty to forego his
vote. To record a vote simply to please some one
else is only one degree baser than to barter it for
money or money’s worth, and indeed it is often
only an indirect mode of doing the same thing.
There is a large class of cases, primarily
affecting individuals rather than society at large,
which, if we look a little below the surface and trace
their results, are of a much more pernicious character
than is usually recognised, and, as ethical knowledge
increases, ought to incur far more severe reprobation
than they now do. Foremost amongst these is what
I may call the current morality of debts. A man
incurs a debt with a tradesman which he has no intention
or no reasonable prospect of paying, knowing that
the tradesman has no grounds for suspecting his inability
to pay. The tradesman parts with the goods, supposing
that he will receive the equivalent; the customer
carries them off, knowing that this equivalent is
not, and is not likely to be, forthcoming. I confess
that I am entirely unable to distinguish this case
from that of ordinary theft. And still there
is many a man, well received in society, who habitually
acts in this manner, and whose practice must be more
than suspected by his friends and associates.
He and his friends would be much astonished if he
were accosted as a thief, and still I cannot see how
he could reasonably repudiate this title. Short
of this extreme case, which, however, is by no means
uncommon, there are many degrees of what may be called
criminal negligence or imprudence in contracting debts,
as where a man runs up a large bill with only a slender
probability of meeting it, or a larger bill than he
can probably meet in full, or one of which he must
defer the payment beyond a reasonable time. In
all these cases, which are much aggravated, if the
goods obtained are luxuries and not necessaries (for
it is one of the plainest duties of every man, who
is removed from absolute want, to live within his
means), there is either actual dishonesty or a dangerous
approximation to it, and it would be a great advance
in every-day morality if society were to recognise
this fact distinctly, and apportion its censures accordingly.
Where the tradesman knows that he is running a risk,
the customer being also aware that he knows it, and
adapts his charges to the fact, it is a case of ‘Greek
meet Greek,’ and, even if the customer deserves
reprobation, the tradesman certainly deserves no compassion.
But this is a case outside the range of honest dealing
altogether, and must be regulated by other sentiments
and other laws than those which prevail in ordinary
commerce. There is another well-known, and to
many men only too familiar, exception to the ordinary
relation of debtor and creditor. A friend ‘borrows’
money of you, though it is understood on both sides
that he will have no opportunity of repaying it, and
that it is virtually a gift. Here, as the creditor
does not expect any repayment, and the debtor knows
that he does not, there is no act of dishonesty, but
the debtor, by asking for a loan and not a gift, evades
the obligation of gratitude and reciprocal service
which would attach to the latter, and thus takes a
certain advantage of his benefactor. In this
case it would be far more straightforward, even if
it involved some humiliation, to use plain words, and
to accept at once the true position of a recipient,
and not affect the seeming one of a borrower.
Connected with the subject of debtor and creditor is
the ungrounded notion, to which I have already adverted,
that the payment of what are called debts of honour
ought to take precedence of all other pecuniary obligations.
As these ‘debts of honour’ generally arise
from bets or play or loans contracted with friends,
the position assumed is simply that debts incurred
to members of our own class or persons whom we know
place us under a greater obligation than debts incurred
to strangers or persons belonging to a lower grade
in society. As thus stated, the maxim is evidently
preposterous and indefensible, and affords a good
instance, as I have noticed in a previous chapter,
of the subordination of the laws of general morality
to the convenience and prejudices of particular cliques
and classes. If there is any competition at all
admissible between just debts, surely those which
have been incurred in return for commodities supplied
have a stronger claim than those, arising from play
or bets, which represent no sacrifice on the part
of the creditor.
Another instance of the class of cases
which I am now considering is to be found in reckless
gambling. Men who indulge in this practice are
usually condemned as being simply hare-brained or foolish;
but, if we look a little below the surface, we shall
find that their conduct is often highly criminal.
Many a time a man risks on play or a bet or a horse-race
or a transaction on the stock exchange the permanent
welfare, sometimes even the very subsistence, of his
wife and children or others depending on him; or,
if he loses, he cuts short a career of future usefulness,
or he renders himself unable to develope, or perhaps
even to retain, his business or his estates, and so
involves his tenants, or clerks, or workmen in his
ruin, or, perhaps, he becomes bankrupt and is thus
the cause of wide-spread misery amongst his creditors.
And, even if these extreme results do not follow,
his rash conduct may be the cause of much minor suffering
amongst his relatives or tradesmen or dependents,
who may have to forego many legitimate enjoyments in
consequence of his one act of greed or thoughtlessness,
while, in all cases, he is encouraging by his example
a practice which, if not his own ruin, is certain
to be the ruin of others. The light-heartedness
with which many a man risks his whole fortune, and
the welfare of all who are dependent on him, for what
would, if gained, be no great addition to his happiness,
is a striking example of the frequent blindness of
men to all results except those which are removed
but one step from their actions. A gamester,
however sanguine, sees that he may lose his money,
but he does not see all the ill consequences to himself
and others which the loss of his money will involve.
Hence an act, which, if we look to the intention,
is often only thoughtless, becomes, in result, criminal,
and it is of the utmost importance that society, by
its reprobation, should make men realise what the
true nature of such actions is.
I pass now to a case of a different
character, which has only, within recent years, begun
to attract the attention of the moralist and politician
at all the peril to life and health ensuing
on the neglect of sanitary precautions. A man
carelessly neglects his drains, or allows a mass of
filth to accumulate in his yard, or uses well-water
without testing its qualities or ascertaining its
surroundings. After a time a fever breaks out
in his household, and, perhaps, communicates itself
to his neighbours, the result being several deaths
and much sickness and suffering. These deaths
and this suffering are the direct result of his negligence,
and, though it would, doubtless, be hard and unjust
to call him a murderer, he is this in effect.
Of course, if, notwithstanding warning or reflexion,
he persists in his negligence, with a full consciousness
of the results which may possibly ensue from it, he
incurs a grave moral responsibility, and it is difficult
to conceive a case more fit for censure, or even punishment.
Nor are the members of a corporation or a board, in
the administration of an area of which they have undertaken
the charge, less guilty, under these circumstances,
than is a private individual in the management of
his own premises. If men were properly instructed
in the results of their actions or pretermissions,
in matters of this nature, and made fully conscious
of the responsibility which those results entail upon
them, there would soon be a marked decrease in physical
suffering, disease, and premature deaths. The
average duration of life, in civilized countries, has
probably already been lengthened by the increased knowledge
and the increased sense of responsibility which have
even now been attained.
Closely connected with these considerations
on the diminution of death, disease, and suffering
by improved sanitary arrangements, is the delicate
subject of the propagation of hereditary disease.
It is a commonplace that the most important of all
the acts of life, is that on which men and women venture
most thoughtlessly. But experience shews, unmistakably,
that there are many forms of disease, both mental and
bodily, which are transmitted from the parents to the
children, and that, consequently, the marriage of
a diseased parent, or of a parent with a tendency
to disease, will probably be followed by the existence
of diseased children. In a matter of this kind,
everything, of course, depends on the amount of the
risk incurred, that is to say, on the extent of the
evil and the probability of its transmission.
The former of these data is supplied by common observation,
the latter by the researches of the pathologist.
It is for the moralist simply to draw attention to
the subject, and to insist on the responsibility attaching
to a knowledge of it. The marriages of persons
who are very poor, and have no reasonable prospect
of bringing up children in health, decency, and comfort,
are open to similar considerations but, as in the last
case, I must content myself with simply adverting to
the responsibility attaching to them, and noting the
extent to which that responsibility is usually ignored.
In connexion with this question, it may be added that
many of the attempts made by well-meaning people to
alleviate poverty and distress have, unfortunately,
too often the effect of ultimately aggravating those
evils by diverting attention from their real causes.
A not unnatural reluctance to discuss or reflect on
matters of this delicate character, combined with
the survival of maxims and sentiments derived from
an entirely different condition of society, are, doubtless,
to a great extent, the reasons of the backward condition
of morality on this subject.
The importance, from a social point
of view, of the careful education of children with
reference to their future position in life has already
been considered, but, in connexion with the class of
duties I am now treating, I may draw attention to
the obligation under which parents lie, in this respect,
to their children themselves. The ancient morality,
which was the product of the patriarchal form of society,
when the patria potestas was still in vigour,
laid peculiar stress on the duties of children to
parents, while it almost ignored the reciprocal duties
of parents to children. When the members of a
family were seldom separated, and the pressure of
population had not yet begun to be felt, this was
the natural order of ideas with respect to the parental
relation. But now that the common labour of the
household is replaced by competition amongst individuals,
and most young men and women have, at an early age,
to leave their families and set about earning their
own living, or carving out their own career, it is
obvious, on reflexion, that parents are guilty of
a gross breach of duty, if they do not use their utmost
endeavours to facilitate the introduction of their
children to the active work of life, and to fit them
for the circumstances in which they are likely to
be placed. To bring up a son or daughter in idleness
or ignorance ought to be as great a reproach to a parent
as it is to a child to dishonour its father or mother.
And yet, in the upper and middle classes at all events,
there are many parents who, without incurring much
reprobation from their friends, prefer to treat their
children like playthings or pet animals rather than
to take the pains to train them with a view to their
future trials and duties. It ought to be thoroughly
realised, and, as the moral consciousness becomes better
adapted to the existing circumstances of society, it
is to be trusted that it will be realised, that parents
have no moral right to do what they choose with their
children, but that they are under a strict obligation
both to society and to their children themselves so
to mould their dispositions and develope their faculties
and inform their minds and train their bodies as to
render them good and useful citizens, and honest and
skilful men. It is to be hoped that, some day,
people will regard with as much surprise the notion
that parents have a right to neglect the education
of their children as we now regard with wonder, when
we first hear of it; the maxim of archaic law, that
a parent had a right to put his child to death.
Much of the trouble, vexation, and
misery of which men are the cause to themselves is
due to cowardice, or the false shame which results
from attaching undue importance to custom, fashion,
or the opinion of others, even when that opinion is
not confirmed by their own reflexion. Shame is
an invaluable protection to men, as a restraining feeling.
But the objects to which it properly attaches are
wrong-doing, unkindness, discourtesy, to others, and,
as regards ourselves, ignorance, imprudence, intemperance,
impurity, and avoidable defects or misfortunes.
While it confines itself to objects such as these,
it is one of the sternest and, at the same time, most
effective guardians of virtue and self-respect.
But, as soon as a man begins to care about what others
will say of circumstances not under his own control,
such as his race, his origin, his appearance, his
physical defects, or his lack of wealth or natural
talents, he may be laying up for himself a store of
incalculable misery, and is certainly enfeebling his
character and impairing his chances of future usefulness.
It is under the influence of this motive, for instance,
that many a man lives above his income, not for the
purpose of gratifying any real wants either of himself
or his family, but for the sake of ‘keeping
up appearances,’ though he is exposing his creditors
to considerable losses, his family to many probable
disadvantages, and himself to almost certain disgrace
in the future. It is under the influence of this
motive, too, that many men, in the upper and middle
classes, rather than marry on a modest income, and
drop out of the society of their fashionable acquaintance,
form irregular sexual connexions, which are a source
of injury to themselves and ruin to their victims.
A circumstance which has probably
contributed largely, in recent times, to aggravate
the feeling of false shame is the new departure which,
in commercial communities, has been taken by class-distinctions.
The old line, which formed a sharp separation between
the nobility and all other classes, has been almost
effaced, and in its place have been substituted many
shades of difference between different grades of society,
together with a broad line of demarcation between
what may be called the genteel and the ungenteel classes.
It was a certain advantage of the old line that it
could not be passed, and, hence, though there might
be some jealousy felt towards the nobility as a class,
there were none of the heart-burnings which attach
to an uncertain position or a futile effort to rise.
In modern society, on the other hand, there is hardly
any one whose position is so fixed, that he may not
easily rise above or fall below it, and hence there
is constant room for social ambition, social disappointment,
and social jealousy. Again, the broad line of
gentility, which now corresponds most closely with
the old distinction of nobility, is determined by
such a number of considerations, birth,
connexions, means, manners, education, with the arbitrary,
though almost essential, condition of not being engaged
in retail trade, that those who are just
excluded by it are apt to feel their position somewhat
unintelligible, and, therefore, all the more galling
to their pride and self-respect It would be curious
to ascertain what proportion of the minor inconveniences
and vexations of modern life is due to the perplexity,
on the one side, and the soreness, on the other, created
by the exclusiveness of class-distinctions. That
these distinctions are an evil, in themselves, there
can, I think, be no doubt. Men cannot, of course,
all know one another, much less be on terms of intimacy
with one another, and the degree of their acquaintance
or intimacy will always be largely dependent on community
of tastes, interests, occupations, and early associations.
But these facts afford no reason why one set of men
should look down with superciliousness and disdain
on another set of men who have not enjoyed the same
early advantages or are not at present endowed with
the same gifts or accomplishments as themselves, or
why they should hold aloof from them when there is
any opportunity of common action or social intercourse.
The pride of class is eminently unreasonable, and,
in those who profess to believe in Christianity, pre-eminently
inconsistent. It will always, probably, continue
to exist, but we may hope that it will be progressively
modified by the advance of education, by the spread
of social sympathy, and by a growing habit of reflexion.
The ideal social condition would be one in which, though
men continued to form themselves into groups, no one
thought the worse or the more lightly of another,
because he belonged to a different group from himself.
Connected with exaggerated class-feeling
are abuses of-esprit de corps_. Unlike class-feeling,
esprit de corps is, in itself, a good.
It binds men together, as in a vessel or a regiment,
a school or a college, an institution or a municipality,
and leads them to sacrifice their ease or their selfish
aims, and to act loyally and cordially with one another
in view of the common interest. It is only when
it sacrifices to the interests of its own body wider
interests still, and subordinates patriotism or morality
to the narrower sentiment attaching to a special law
of honour, that it incurs the reprobation of the moralist.
But that it does sometimes deservedly incur this reprobation,
admits of no question. A man, to save the honour
of his regiment, may impair the efficiency of an army,
or, to promote the interests of his college or school,
may inflict a lasting injury on education, or, to
protect his associates, may withhold or pervert evidence,
or, to aggrandize his trade, may ruin his country.
It is the special province of the moralist, in these
cases, to intervene, and point out how the more general
is being sacrificed to the more special interest, the
wider to the narrower sentiment, morality itself to
a point of honour or etiquette. But, at the same
time, he must recollect that the esprit de corps
of any small aggregate of men is, as such, always an
ennobling and inspiriting sentiment, and that, unless
it plainly detach them from the rest of the community,
and is attended with pernicious consequences to society
at large, it is unwise, if not reckless, to seek to
impair it.
To descend to a subject of less, though
still of considerable, importance, I may notice that
cowardice and fear of ’what people will say’
lies at the bottom of much ill-considered charity and
of that facility with which men, often to the injury
of themselves or their families, if not of the very
objects pleaded for, listen to the solicitations of
the inconsiderate or interested subscription-monger.
It has now become a truism that enormous mischief
is done by the indiscriminate distribution of alms
to beggars or paupers. It is no less true, though
not so obvious, that much unintentional harm is often
done by subscriptions for what are called public objects.
People ought to have sufficient mental independence
to ask themselves what will be the ultimate effects
of subscribing their money, and, if they honestly
believe that those effects will be pernicious or of
doubtful utility, they ought to have the courage to
refuse it. There is no good reason, simply because
a man asks me and I find that others are yielding to
him, why I should subscribe a guinea towards disfiguring
a church, or erecting an ugly and useless building,
or extending pauperism, or encouraging the growth
of luxurious habits, or spreading opinions which I
do not believe. And I may be the more emboldened
in my refusal, when I consider how mixed, or how selfish,
are often the motives of those who solicit me, and
that the love of notoriety, or the gratification of
a feeling of self-importance, or a fussy restlessness,
or the craving for preferment is frequently quite
as powerful an incentive of their activity as a desire
to promote the objects explicitly avowed. There
is, moreover, an important consideration, connected
with this subject, which often escapes notice, namely,
the extent to which new and multiplied appeals to
charity often interfere with older, nearer, and more
pressing claims. Thus, the managers of the local
hospital or dispensary or charity organisation have
often too good cause to regret the enthusiastic philanthropy,
which is sending help, of questionable utility, to
distant parts of the world. People cannot subscribe
to everything, and they are too apt to fall in with
the most recent and most fashionable movement.
In venturing on these remarks, I trust it is needless
to say that I am far from deprecating the general practice
of subscribing to charities and public objects, a
form of co-operation which has been rendered indispensable
by the habits and circumstances of modern life.
I am simply insisting on the importance and responsibility
of ascertaining whether the aims proposed are likely
to be productive of good or evil, and deprecating
the cowardice or listlessness which yields to a solicitation,
irrespectively of the merits of the proposal.
These solicitations often take the
offensive form, which is intentionally embarrassing
to the person solicited, of an appeal to relieve the
purveyor of the subscription-list himself from the
obligation incurred by a ‘guarantee.’
The issue is thus ingeniously and unfairly transferred
from the claims of the object, which it is designed
to promote, to the question of relieving a friend or
a neighbour from a heavy pecuniary obligation.
’Surely you will never allow me to pay all this
money myself.’ But why not, unless I approve
of the object, and, even if I do, why should I increase
my subscription, on account of an obligation voluntarily
incurred by you, without any encouragement from me?
In a case of this kind, the ‘guarantee’
ought to be regarded as simply irrelevant, and the
question decided solely on the merits of the result
to be attained. Of course, I must be understood
to be speaking here only of those cases in which the
‘guarantee’ is used as an additional argument
for eliciting subscriptions, not of those cases in
which, for convenience sake, or in order to secure
celerity of execution, a few wealthy persons generously
advance the whole sum required for a project, being
quite willing to pay it themselves, unless they meet
with ready and cheerful co-operation.
In the department of social intercourse,
there are several applications of existing moral principles,
and specially of the softer virtues of kindness, courtesy,
and consideration for others, the observance of which
would sensibly sweeten our relations to our fellow-men
and, to persons of a sensitive temperament, render
life far more agreeable and better worth living than
it actually is. A few of these applications I
shall attempt to point out. Amongst savage races,
and in the less polished ranks of civilized life,
men who disagree, or have any grudge against one another,
resort to physical blows or coarse invective.
In polite and educated circles, these weapons are
replaced by sarcasm and innuendo. There are,
of course, many advantages gained by the substitution
of this more refined mode of warfare, but the mere
fact that the intellectual skill which it displays
gives pleasure to the bystanders, and wins social
applause, renders its employment far more frequent
than, on cool reflexion, could be justified by the
occasions for it. There can be no doubt that
it gives pain, often intense pain, especially where
the victim is not ready enough to retaliate effectively
in kind. And there can be no more justification
for inflicting this peculiar kind of pain than any
other, unless the circumstances are such as to demand
it. Any one, who will take the trouble to analyse
his acts and motives, will generally find, when he
employs these weapons, that he is actuated not so
much by any desire to reform the object of his attack
or to deter, by these means, him or others from wrong-doing,
as by a desire to show off his own cleverness and
to leave behind him a mark of his power in the smart
which he inflicts. These unamiable motives are
least justifiable, when the victim is a social inferior,
or a person who, by his age or position, is unable
to retaliate on equal terms. To vanity and cruelty
are then added cowardice, and, though all these vices
may only be displayed on a very small scale, they are
none the less really present. It may be laid
down, however difficult, with our present social habits,
it may be to keep the rule, that sarcasm should never
be employed, except deliberately, and as a punishment,
and that for innuendo, if justifiable by facts, men
should always have the courage to substitute direct
assertion.
Of the minor social vices, one of
the commonest is a disregard, in conversation, of
other persons’ feelings. Men who lay claim
to the character of gentlemen are specially bound
to shew their tact and delicacy of feeling by avoiding
all subjects which have a disagreeable personal reference
or are likely to revive unpleasant associations in
the minds of any of those who are present. And
yet these are qualities which are often strangely
conspicuous by their absence even in educated and
cultivated society. One of the most repulsive
and least excusable forms which this indifference
to other persons’ feelings takes is in impertinent
curiosity. There are some people who, for the
sake of satisfying a purposeless curiosity, will ask
questions which they know it cannot be agreeable to
answer. In all cases, curiosity of this kind
is evidence of want of real refinement, and is a breach
of the finer rules of social morality; but, when the
questions asked are intended to extract, directly
or indirectly, unwilling information on a man’s
private life or circumstances, they assume the character
of sheer vulgarity. A man’s private affairs,
providing his conduct of them does not injuriously
affect society, are no one’s business but his
own, and much pain and vexation of the smaller kind
would be saved, if this very plain fact were duly
recognised in social intercourse.
It may be noticed in passing, that
there still lingers on in society a minor form of
persecution, a sort of inquisition on a small scale,
which consists in attempting to extract from a man
a frank statement of his religious, social, or political
opinions, though it is known or suspected all the
time, that, if he responds to the invitation, it will
be to his social or material disadvantage. In
cases of this kind, it becomes a casuistical question
how far a man is called on to disclose his real sentiments
at the bidding of any impertinent questioner.
That the free expression of opinion should be attended
with this danger is, of course, a proof how far removed
we still are from perfect intellectual toleration.
Impertinent curiosity is offensive,
not only because it shews an indifference to the feelings
of the person questioned, but because it savours of
gratuitous interference in his affairs. This quality
it shares with another of the minor social vices,
the tendering of unasked for advice, or, in brief,
impertinent advice. There are certain circumstances
and relations in which men have the right, even if
they are not under the obligation, to give unsolicited
advice, as where a man is incurring an unknown danger
or foregoing some unsuspected advantage, or to their
servants, or children, or wards, or pupils; but, in
all these cases, either the special circumstance or
the special relation implies superiority of knowledge
or superiority of position on the part of the person
tendering the advice, and to assume this superiority,
where it does not plainly exist, is an act of impertinence.
Just as the assumption of superiority wounds a man’s
self-respect, so does the disposition to meddle in
his affairs, which is generally founded on that assumption,
affect his sense of independence, and, hence, an act
which includes both grounds of offence seems to be
a peculiarly legitimate object of resentment.
The lesson of letting other people alone is one which
men are slow to learn, though there are few who, in
their own case, do not resent any attack on their
liberty of judgment or action. This is emphatically
one of the cases in which we should try to put ourselves
in the place of others, and act to them as we would
that they should act towards us.
Excessive, and often ill-natured,
criticism of others is one of the minor vices which
seem to grow up with advancing civilisation and intelligence
rather than to retreat before them. It seems,
as a rule, to prevail much more in educated than in
uneducated society. The reason is not difficult
to find. Education naturally makes men more fastidious
and more keenly alive to the defects of those with
whom they associate. And then, when educated
men converse together, they are apt, merely from the
facility with which they deal with language, to express
in an exaggerated form the unfavourable estimate which
they have formed of others, especially if this exaggerated
form can be compressed into an epigram. But it
requires little reflexion to see that this keen and
exaggerated habit of criticism must be productive of
much discomfort in a society in which it is general,
and that, when applied to literary work, even though
it may be a protection against inaccuracy and breaches
of taste, it must be a great discouragement to the
young and repressive of much honest and valuable effort.
To restrain the critical spirit, whether applied to
mind or conduct, with proper limits, it is necessary,
keeping these considerations in view, to ask how much
we can reasonably or profitably require of men, and,
above all, never to lose that sympathetic touch with
others which renders us as keenly alive to their difficulties
as their errors, to their aspirations as their failure
to fulfil them.
I shall say nothing here of detraction,
backbiting, or malicious representation, because these
are social vices which are too obvious and too generally
acknowledged to be of any service as illustrations
of those extensions or new applications of morality
which I have in view in the present chapter.
I may, however, notice in passing, that the invention
or exaggeration of stories, which have a tendency to
bring men into ridicule or contempt, is a practice
which, from the entertainment it affords, is too easily
tolerated by society, and usually fails to meet with
the reprobation it deserves.
I shall advert to only one other topic,
namely, the treatment of the lower animals. With
rare exceptions, it is only of late that this subject
has been regarded as falling within the sphere of ethics,
and it is greatly to the credit of Bentham that he
was amongst the first to recognise its importance
and to commend it to the consideration of the legislator.
That the lower animals, as sentient beings, have a
claim on our sympathies, and that, consequently, we
have duties in respect of them, I can no more doubt
than that we have duties in respect to the inferior
members of our own race. But, at the same time,
considering their place in the economy of nature,
I cannot doubt that man has a right, within certain
limits, to use them, and even to kill them, for his
own advantage. What these limits are is a question
by no means devoid of difficulty. There are those
who maintain that we have no right to kill animals
for food, while there are those who, without maintaining
this extreme position, hold that we have no right to
cause them pain for the purposes of our own amusement,
or even for the alleviation of human suffering by
means of the advancement of physiological and medical
science. It will be seen that the three questions
here raised are the legitimacy of the use of animal
food, of field sports, and of vivisection. As
respects the first, I do not doubt that, considering
their relative places in the scale of being, man is
morally justified in sacrificing the lives of the
lower animals to the maintenance of his own health
and vigour, let alone the probability that, if he did
not, they would multiply to such an extent as to endanger
his existence, and would themselves, in the aggregate,
experience more suffering from the privation caused
by the struggle for life than they now do by incurring
violent deaths. At the same time, though man may
kill the lower animals for his own convenience, he
is bound not to inflict needless suffering on them.
The torture of an animal, for no adequate purpose,
is absolutely indefensible. Cock-fights, bull-fights,
and the like seem to me to admit of no more justification
than the gladiatorial shows. Are field-sports,
then, in the same category? The answer, I think,
depends on three considerations: (1) would the
animal be killed any way, either for food, or as a
beast of prey; (2) what is the amount of suffering
inflicted on it, in addition to that which would be
inflicted by killing it instantaneously; (3) for what
purpose is this additional suffering inflicted.
I shall not attempt to apply these considerations in
detail, but I shall simply state as my opinion that,
amongst the results of a legitimate application of
them, would be the conclusions that worrying a dog
or a cat is altogether unjustifiable; that fox-hunting
might be justified on the ground that the additional
suffering caused to the fox is far more than counterbalanced
by the beneficial effects, in health and enjoyment,
to the hunter; that shooting, if the sportsman be
skilful, is one of the most painless ways of putting
a bird or a stag to death, and, therefore, requires
no justification, whereas, if the sportsman be unskilful,
the sufferings which he is liable to cause, through
a lingering and painful death, ought to deter him from
practising his art. With regard to the much-debated
question of vivisection, it seems to me utterly untenable,
and eminently inconsistent on the part of those who
eat animal food or indulge in field-sports, to maintain
that, under no circumstances, is it morally justifiable
to inflict pain on the lower animals for the purpose
of ascertaining the causes or remedies of disease.
But, having once made this admission, I should insist
on the necessity of guarding it by confining the power
of operating on the living animal to persons duly
authorised, and by limiting it to cases of research
as distinct from demonstration. Those, moreover,
who are invested with this serious responsibility,
ought to feel morally bound to inflict no superfluous
suffering, and ought, consequently, to employ anaesthetics,
wherever they would not unduly interfere with the
conduct of the experiment; to resort, as far as possible,
to the lower rather than the higher organisms, as
being less susceptible of pain; and to limit their
experiments, both in number and duration, as far as
is consistent with the objects for which they are
permitted to perform them. This whole question,
however, of our relation to the lower animals is one
which is fraught with much difficulty, and supplies
a good instance of the range of subjects within which
the moral sentiment is probably in the course of development.
Recent researches, and, still more, recent speculations,
have tended to impress us with the nearness of our
kinship to other animals, and, hence, our sympathies
with them and our interest in their welfare have been
sensibly quickened. The word philanthropy no longer
expresses the most general of the sympathetic feelings,
and we seem to require some new term which shall denote
our fellow-feeling with the whole sentient creation.
Such is a sample, and I must repeat
that it is intended only as a sample, of the class
of questions to which, as it seems to me, the moral
test still admits of further application. Morality,
or the science and art of conduct, had its small beginnings,
I conceive, in the primeval household and has only
attained its present grand proportions by gradual
increments, derived partly from the semi-conscious
operations of the human intelligence adapting itself
to the circumstances in which it is placed, partly
from the conscious meditations of reflective men.
That it is likely to advance in the future, as it
has done in the past, notwithstanding the many hindrances
to its progress which confessedly exist, is, I think,
an obvious inference from experience. We may not
unreasonably hope that there will be a stricter sense
of justice, a more complete realisation of duty, more
delicacy of feeling, a greater refinement of manners,
more kindliness, quicker and wider sympathies in the
coming generations than there are amongst ourselves.
I have attempted, in this Essay, briefly to delineate
the nature of the feelings on which this progress
depends, and of the considerations by which it is
guided, as well as to indicate some few out of the
many directions which it is likely to take in the
future. In the former part of my task, I am aware
that I have run counter to many prejudices of long
standing, and that the theories which I consider to
be alone consistent with the fact of the progress
of morality, may by some be thought to impair its
authority. But if morality has its foundations
in the constitution of human nature, which itself
proceeds from the Divine Source of all things, I conceive
that its credentials are sufficiently assured.
In the present chapter, I have, in attempting to illustrate
the possibility of future improvements in the art
and theory of conduct, been necessarily led to note
some deficiencies in the existing moral sentiment.
This is always an unwelcome and invidious task.
Men do not like to be reminded of their moral failings,
and there is hardly any man, however critical he may
be of others, who, in the actual conduct of life,
does not appear to delude himself with the idea that
his own moral practice is perfect. I appeal,
however, from the unconscious assumptions of men to
their powers of reflexion, and I ask each man who reads
this book to consider carefully within himself whether,
on the principles here set out, much of the conduct
and many of the ethical maxims which are now generally
accepted do not admit of refinement and improvement.
In the sphere of morals, as in all other departments
of human activity, we are bound to do for our successors
what our predecessors were bound to do, and mostly
did, for us transmit the heritage we have
received with all the additions and adaptations which
the new experiences and changing conditions of life
have rendered necessary or desirable.