Amiel’s Journal. The Journal
Intime of Henri-Frederic Amiel. Translated,
with an Introduction and Notes, by Mrs. Humphry Ward.
Two vols. Macmillans.
Henri-Frederic Amiel was born at Geneva
in 1821. Orphaned of both his parents at the
age of twelve, his youth was necessarily “a little
bare and forlorn,” and a deep interest in religion
became fixed in him early. His student days
coming to an end, the years which followed, from 1842
to 1848 — Wanderjahre, in which he visited
Holland, Italy, Sicily, and the principal towns of
Germany — seem to have been the happiest
of his life. In 1849 he became a Professor at
Geneva, and there is little more to tell of him in
the way of outward events. He published
some volumes of verse; to the last apparently still
only feeling after his true literary metier.
Those last seven years were a long struggle against
the disease which ended his life, consumption, at
the age of fifty-three. The first entry in his
Journal is in 1848. From that date to his death,
a period of over twenty-five years, this Journal was
the real object of all the energies of his richly-endowed
nature: and from its voluminous sheets his literary
executors have selected the deeply interesting volumes
now presented in English.
With all its gifts and opportunities
it was a melancholy life — melancholy with
something not altogether explained by the somewhat
pessimistic philosophy exposed in the Journal, nor
by the consumptive tendency of Amiel’s physical
constitution, causing him from a very early date to
be much preoccupied with the effort to reconcile himself
with the prospect of death, and reinforcing the far
from sanguine temperament of one intellectually also
a poitrinaire.
You might think him at first sight
only an admirable specimen of a thoroughly well-educated
man, full, of course, of the modern spirit; stimulated
and formed by the influences of the varied intellectual
world around him; and competing, in his turn, with
many very various types of contemporary ability.
The use of his book to cultivated people might lie
in its affording a kind of standard by which they
might take measure of the maturity and producible quality
of their own thoughts on a hundred important subjects.
He will write a page or two, giving evidence of that
accumulated power and attainment which, with a more
strenuous temperament, might have sufficed for an
effective volume. Continually, in the Journal,
we pause over things that would rank for beauties
among widely differing models of the best French prose.
He has said some things in Pascal’s vein not
unworthy of Pascal. He had a right to compose
“Thoughts”: they have the force in
them which makes up for their unavoidable want of continuity.
But if, as Amiel himself challenges
us to do, we look below the surface of a very equable
and even smoothly accomplished literary manner, we
discover, in high degree of development, that perplexity
or complexity of soul, the expression of which,
so it be with an adequate literary gift, has its legitimate,
because inevitable, interest for the modern reader.
Senancour and Maurice de Guerin in one, seem to have
been supplemented here by a larger experience, a far
greater education, than either of them had attained
to. So multiplex is the result that minds of
quite opposite type might well discover in these pages
their own special thought or humour, happily expressed
at last (they might think) in precisely that just
shade of language themselves had searched for in vain.
And with a writer so vivid and impressive as Amiel,
those varieties of tendency are apt to present themselves
as so many contending persons. The perplexed
experience gets the apparent clearness, as it gets
also the animation, of a long dialogue; only, the
disputants never part company, and there is no real
conclusion. “This nature,” he observes,
of one of the many phases of character he has discovered
in himself, “is, as it were, only one of the
men which exist in me. It is one of my departments.
It is not the whole of my territory, the whole of
my inner kingdom”; and again, “there are
ten men in me, according to time, place, surrounding,
and occasion; and, in my restless diversity,
I am for ever escaping myself.”
Yet, in truth, there are but two men
in Amiel — two sufficiently opposed personalities,
which the attentive reader may define for himself;
compare with, and try by each other — as we
think, correct also by each other. There is
the man, in him and in these pages, who would be “the
man of disillusion,” only that he has never really
been “the man of desires”; and who seems,
therefore, to have a double weariness about him.
He is akin, of course, to Obermann, to René, even
to Werther, and, on our first introduction to him,
we might think that we had to do only with one more
of the vague “renunciants,” who in real
life followed those creations of fiction, and who,
however delicate, interesting as a study, and as it
were picturesque on the stage of life, are themselves,
after all, essentially passive, uncreative, and therefore
necessarily not of first-rate importance in literature.
Taken for what it is worth, the expression of this
mood — the culture of ennui for its own sake — is
certainly carried to its ideal of negation by Amiel.
But the completer, the positive, soul, which will
merely take that mood into its service (its proper
service, as we hold, is in counteraction to the vulgarity
of purely positive natures) is also certainly in evidence
in Amiel’s “Thoughts” — that
other, and far stronger person, in the long dialogue;
the man, in short, possessed of gifts, not for the
renunciation, but for the reception and use, of all
that is puissant, goodly, and effective in life, and
for the varied and adequate literary reproduction
of it; who, under favourable circumstances, or even
without them, will become critic, or poet, and in
either case a creative force; and if he be religious
(as Amiel was deeply religious) will make the most
of “evidence,” and almost certainly find
a Church.
The sort of purely poetic tendency
in his mind, which made Amiel known in his own lifetime
chiefly as a writer of verse, seems to be represented
in these volumes by certain passages of natural description,
always sincere, and sometimes rising to real distinction.
In Switzerland it is easy to be pleased with scenery.
But the record of such pleasure becomes really worth
while when, as happens with Amiel, we feel that there
has been, and with success, an intellectual effort
to get at the secret, the precise motive, of the pleasure;
to define feeling, in this matter. Here is a
good description of an effect of fog, which we commend
to foreigners resident in London:
“Fog has certainly a poetry
of its own — a grace, a dreamy charm.
It does for the daylight what a lamp does for us
at night; it turns the mind towards meditation; it
throws the soul back on itself. The sun, as
it were, sheds us abroad in nature, scatters and disperses
us; mist draws us together and concentrates us — it
is cordial, homely, charged with feeling. The
poetry of the sun has something of the epic in it;
that of fog and mist is elegiac and religious.
Pantheism is the child of light; mist engenders faith
in near protectors. When the great world is
shut off from us, the house becomes itself a small
universe. Shrouded in perpetual mist, men love
each other better; for the only reality then is the
family, and, within the family, the heart; and the
greatest thoughts come from the heart — so
says the moralist.”
It is of Swiss fog, however, that
he is speaking, as, in what follows, of Swiss frost:
“The weather is rainy, the whole
atmosphere grey; it is a time favourable to thought
and meditation. I have a liking for such days
as these; they revive one’s converse with oneself
and make it possible to live the inner life:
they are quiet and peaceful, like a song in a minor
key. We are nothing but thought, but we feel
our life to its very centre. Our very sensations
turn to reverie. It is a strange state of mind;
it is like those silences in worship which are not
the empty moments of devotion, but the full moments,
and which are so because at such times the soul, instead
of being polarized, dispersed, localized, in a single
impression or thought, feels her own totality and
is conscious of herself.”
And if we take Amiel at his own word,
we must suppose that but for causes, the chief of
which were bad health and a not long life, he too
would have produced monumental work, whose scope and
character he would wish us to conjecture from his
“Thoughts.” Such indications there
certainly are in them. He was meant — we
see it in the variety, the high level both of matter
and style, the animation, the gravity, of one after
another of these thoughts — on religion, on
poetry, on politics in the highest sense; on their
most abstract principles, and on the authors who have
given them a personal colour; on the genius of those
authors, as well as on their concrete works; on outlying
isolated subjects, such as music, and special musical
composers — he was meant, if people ever
are meant for special lines of activity, for the best
sort of criticism, the imaginative criticism; that
criticism which is itself a kind of construction,
or creation, as it penetrates, through the given literary
or artistic product, into the mental and inner constitution
of the producer, shaping his work. Of such critical
skill, cultivated with all the resources of Geneva
in the nineteenth century, he has given in this Journal
abundant proofs. Corneille, Cherbuliez; Rousseau,
Sismondi; Victor Hugo, and Joubert; Mozart and Wagner — all
who are interested in these men will find a value in
what Amiel has to say of them. Often, as for
instance in his excellent criticism of Quinet, he
has to make large exceptions ; limitations, skilfully
effected by the way, in the course of a really appreciative
estimate. Still, through all, what we feel is
that we have to do with one who criticises in this
fearlessly equitable manner only because he is convinced
that his subject is of a real literary importance.
A powerful, intellectual analysis of some well-marked
subject, in such form as makes literature enduring,
is indeed what the world might have looked for from
him: those institutes of aesthetics, for instance,
which might exist, after Lessing and Hegel, but which
certainly do not exist yet. “Construction,”
he says — artistic or literary construction — “rests
upon feeling, instinct, and,” alas! also, “upon
will.” The instinct, at all events, was
certainly his. And over and above that he had
possessed himself of the art of expressing, in quite
natural language, very difficult thoughts; those abstract
and metaphysical conceptions especially, in which
German mind has been rich, which are bad masters,
but very useful ministers towards the understanding,
towards an analytical survey, of all that the intellect
has produced.
But something held him back:
not so much a reluctancy of temperament, or of
physical constitution (common enough cause why men
of undeniable gifts fail of commensurate production)
but a cause purely intellectual — the presence
in him, namely, of a certain vein of opinion; that
other, constituent but contending, person, in his complex
nature. “The relation of thought to action,”
he writes, “filled my mind on waking, and I
found myself carried towards a bizarre formula, which
seems to have something of the night still clinging
about it. Action is but coarsened thought.”
That is but an ingenious metaphysical point, as he
goes on to show. But, including in “action”
that literary production in which the line of his own
proper activity lay, he followed — followed
often — that fastidious utterance to a cynical
and pessimistic conclusion.
Maia, as he calls it, the empty “Absolute”
of the Buddhist, the “Infinite,” the “All,”
of which those German metaphysicians he loved only
too well have had so much to say: this was for
ever to give the go-by to all positive, finite, limited
interests whatever. The vague pretensions of
an abstract expression acted on him with all the force
of a prejudice. “The ideal,” he admits,
“poisons for me all imperfect possession”;
and again, “The Buddhist tendency in me blunts
the faculty of free self-government, and weakens the
power of action. I feel a terror of action and
am only at ease in the impersonal, disinterested,
and objective line of thought.” But then,
again, with him “action” meant chiefly
literary production. He quotes with approval
those admirable words from Goethe, “In der
Beschränkung zeigt sich erst der
Meister”; yet still always finds himself
wavering between “frittering myself away on
the infinitely little, and longing after what is unknown
and distant.” There is, doubtless, over
and above the physical consumptive tendency, an instinctive
turn of sentiment in this touching confession.
Still, what strengthened both tendencies was that
metaphysical prejudice for the “Absolute,”
the false intellectual conscience. “I
have always avoided what attracted me, and turned my
back upon the point where secretly I desired to be”;
and, of course, that is not the way to a free and
generous productivity, in literature, or in anything
else; though in literature, with Amiel at all events,
it meant the fastidiousness which is incompatible
with any but the very best sort of production.
And as that abstract condition of
Maia, to the kind and quantity of concrete literary
production we hold to have been originally possible
for him; so was the religion he actually attained,
to what might have been the development of his profoundly
religious spirit, had he been able to see that the
old-fashioned Christianity is itself but the proper
historic development of the true “essence”
of the New Testament. There, again, is the constitutional
shrinking, through a kind of metaphysical prejudice,
from the concrete — that fear of the actual — in
this case, of the Church of history; to which the admissions,
which form so large a part of these volumes, naturally
lead. Assenting, on probable evidence, to so
many of the judgments of the religious sense, he failed
to see the equally probable evidence there is for the
beliefs, the peculiar direction of men’s hopes,
which complete those judgments harmoniously, and bring
them into connection with the facts, the venerable
institutions of the past — with the lives
of the saints. By failure, as we think, of that
historic sense, of which he could speak so well,
he got no further in this direction than the glacial
condition of rationalistic Geneva. “Philosophy,”
he says, “can never replace religion.”
Only, one cannot see why it might not replace a religion
such as his: a religion, after all, much like
Seneca’s.
“I miss something,” he
himself confesses, “common worship, a positive
religion, shared with other people. Ah! when
will the Church to which I belong in heart rise into
being?” To many at least of those who can detect
the ideal through the disturbing circumstances which
belong to all actual institutions in the world, it
was already there. Pascal, from considerations
to which Amiel was no stranger, came to the large
hopes of the Catholic Church; Amiel stopped short at
a faith almost hopeless; and by stopping short just
there he really failed, as we think, of intellectual
consistency, and missed that appeasing influence which
his nature demanded as the condition of its full activity,
as a force, an intellectual force, in the world — in
the special business of his life. “Welcome
the unforeseen,” he says again, by way of a counsel
of perfection in the matter of culture, “but
give to your life unity, and bring the unforeseen
within the lines of your plan.” Bring,
we should add, the Great Possibility at least within
the lines of your plan — your plan of action
or production; of morality; especially of your conceptions
of religion. And still, Amiel too, be it remembered
(we are not afraid to repeat it), has said some things
in Pascal’s vein not unworthy of Pascal.
And so we get only the Journal.
Watching in it, in the way we have suggested, the
contention of those two men, those two minds in him,
and observing how the one might have ascertained and
corrected the shortcomings of the other, we certainly
understand, and can sympathize with Amiel’s
despondency in the retrospect of a life which seemed
to have been but imperfectly occupied. But,
then, how excellent a literary product, after all,
the Journal is. And already we have found that
it improves also on second reading. A book of
“thoughts” should be a book that may be
fairly dipped into, and yield good quotable sayings.
Here are some of its random offerings:
“Look twice, if what you want
is a just conception; look once, if what you
want is a sense of beauty.”
“It is not history which teaches
conscience to be honest; it is the conscience which
educates history. Fact is corrupting — it
is we who correct it by the persistence of our ideal.”
“To do easily what is difficult
for others is the mark of talent. To do what
is impossible for talent is the mark of genius.”
“Duty has the virtue of making
us feel the reality of a positive world, while at
the same time detaching us from it.”
“As it is impossible to be outside
God, the best is consciously to dwell in Him.”
“He also (the Son of Man), He
above all, is the great Misunderstood, the least comprehended.”
“The pensee writer is to the
philosopher what the dilettante is to the artist.”
There are some, we know, who hold
that genius cannot, in the nature of things, be “sterile”;
that there are no “mute” Miltons, or the
like. Well! genius, or only a very distinguished
talent, the gift which Amiel nursed so jealously did
come into evidence. And the reader, we
hope, sees also already how well his English translator
has done her work. She may justly feel, as part
at least of the reward of a labour which must have
occupied much time, so many of the freshest hours of
mind and spirit, that she has done something to help
her author in the achievement of his, however discouraged
still irrepressible, desire, by giving additional
currency to a book which the best sort of readers
will recognize as an excellent and certainly very versatile
companion, not to be forgotten.
17th March 1886