That the outer man is a picture of
the inner, and the face an expression and revelation
of the whole character, is a presumption likely enough
in itself, and therefore a safe one to go by; evidenced
as it is by the fact that people are always anxious
to see anyone who has made himself famous by good
or evil, or as the author of some extraordinary work;
or if they cannot get a sight of him, to hear at any
rate from others what he looks like. So people
go to places where they may expect to see the person
who interests them; the press, especially in England,
endeavors to give a minute and striking description
of his appearance; painters and engravers lose no
time in putting him visibly before us; and finally
photography, on that very account of such high value,
affords the most complete satisfaction of our curiosity.
It is also a fact that in private life everyone criticises
the physiognomy of those he comes across, first of
all secretly trying to discern their intellectual and
moral character from their features. This would
be a useless proceeding if, as some foolish people
fancy, the exterior of a man is a matter of no account;
if, as they think, the soul is one thing and the body
another, and the body related to the soul merely as
the coat to the man himself.
On the contrary, every human face
is a hieroglyphic, and a hieroglyphic, too, which
admits of being deciphered, the alphabet of which we
carry about with us already perfected. As a matter
of fact, the face of a man gives us a fuller and more
interesting information than his tongue; for his face
is the compendium of all he will ever say, as it is
the one record of all his thoughts and endeavors.
And, moreover, the tongue tells the thought of one
man only, whereas the face expresses a thought of
nature itself: so that everyone is worth attentive
observation, even though everyone may not be worth
talking to. And if every individual is worth
observation as a single thought of nature, how much
more so is beauty, since it is a higher and more general
conception of nature, is, in fact, her thought of
a species. This is why beauty is so captivating:
it is a fundamental thought of nature: whereas
the individual is only a by-thought, a corollary.
In private, people always proceed
upon the principle that a man is what he looks; and
the principle is a right one, only the difficulty lies
in its application. For though the art of applying
the principle is partly innate and may be partly gained
by experience, no one is a master of it, and even
the most experienced is not infallible. But for
all that, whatever Figaro may say, it is not the face
which deceives; it is we who deceive ourselves in
reading in it what is not there.
The deciphering of a face is certainly
a great and difficult art, and the principles of it
can never be learnt in the abstract. The first
condition of success is to maintain a purely objective
point of view, which is no easy matter. For,
as soon as the faintest trace of anything subjective
is present, whether dislike or favor, or fear or hope,
or even the thought of the impression we ourselves
are making upon the object of our attention the characters
we are trying to decipher become confused and corrupt.
The sound of a language is really appreciated only
by one who does not understand it, and that because,
in thinking of the signification of a word, we pay
no regard to the sign itself. So, in the same
way, a physiognomy is correctly gauged only by one
to whom it is still strange, who has not grown accustomed
to the face by constantly meeting and conversing with
the man himself. It is, therefore, strictly speaking,
only the first sight of a man which affords that purely
objective view which is necessary for deciphering his
features. An odor affects us only when we first
come in contact with it, and the first glass of wine
is the one which gives us its true taste: in the
same way, it is only at the first encounter that a
face makes its full impression upon us. Consequently
the first impression should be carefully attended
to and noted, even written down if the subject of it
is of personal importance, provided, of course, that
one can trust one’s own sense of physiognomy.
Subsequent acquaintance and intercourse will obliterate
the impression, but time will one day prove whether
it is true.
Let us, however, not conceal from
ourselves the fact that this first impression is for
the most part extremely unedifying. How poor most
faces are! With the exception of those that are
beautiful, good-natured, or intellectual, that is
to say, the very few and far between, I believe a
person of any fine feeling scarcely ever sees a new
face without a sensation akin to a shock, for the
reason that it presents a new and surprising combination
of unedifying elements. To tell the truth, it
is, as a rule, a sorry sight. There are some
people whose faces bear the stamp of such artless
vulgarity and baseness of character, such an animal
limitation of intelligence, that one wonders how they
can appear in public with such a countenance, instead
of wearing a mask. There are faces, indeed, the
very sight of which produces a feeling of pollution.
One cannot, therefore, take it amiss of people, whose
privileged position admits of it, if they manage to
live in retirement and completely free from the painful
sensation of “seeing new faces.” The
metaphysical explanation of this circumstance rests
upon the consideration that the individuality of a
man is precisely that by the very existence of which
he should be reclaimed and corrected. If, on the
other hand, a psychological explanation is satisfactory,
let any one ask himself what kind of physiognomy he
may expect in those who have all their life long,
except on the rarest occasions, harbored nothing but
petty, base and miserable thoughts, and vulgar, selfish,
envious, wicked and malicious desires. Every
one of these thoughts and desires has set its mark
upon the face during the time it lasted, and by constant
repetition, all these marks have in course of time
become furrows and blotches, so to speak. Consequently,
most people’s appearance is such as to produce
a shock at first sight; and it is only gradually that
one gets accustomed to it, that is to say, becomes
so deadened to the impression that it has no more
effect on one.
And that the prevailing facial expression
is the result of a long process of innumerable, fleeting
and characteristic contractions of the features is
just the reason why intellectual countenances are of
gradual formation. It is, indeed, only in old
age that intellectual men attain their sublime expression,
whilst portraits of them in their youth show only
the first traces of it. But on the other hand,
what I have just said about the shock which the first
sight of a face generally produces, is in keeping
with the remark that it is only at that first sight
that it makes its true and full impression. For
to get a purely objective and uncorrupted impression
of it, we must stand in no kind of relation to the
person; if possible, we must not yet have spoken with
him. For every conversation places us to some
extent upon a friendly footing, establishes a certain
rapport, a mutual subjective relation, which
is at once unfavorable to an objective point of view.
And as everyone’s endeavor is to win esteem
or friendship for himself, the man who is under observation
will at once employ all those arts of dissimulation
in which he is already versed, and corrupt us with
his airs, hypocrisies and flatteries; so that
what the first look clearly showed will soon be seen
by us no more.
This fact is at the bottom of the
saying that “most people gain by further acquaintance”;
it ought, however, to run, “delude us by it.”
It is only when, later on, the bad qualities manifest
themselves, that our first judgment as a rule receives
its justification and makes good its scornful verdict.
It may be that “a further acquaintance”
is an unfriendly one, and if that is so, we do not
find in this case either that people gain by it.
Another reason why people apparently gain on a nearer
acquaintance is that the man whose first aspect warns
us from him, as soon as we converse with him, no longer
shows his own being and character, but also his education;
that is, not only what he really is by nature, but
also what he has appropriated to himself out of the
common wealth of mankind. Three-fourths of what
he says belongs not to him, but to the sources from
which he obtained it; so that we are often surprised
to hear a minotaur speak so humanly. If we make
a still closer acquaintance, the animal nature, of
which his face gave promise, will manifest itself
“in all its splendor.” If one is gifted
with an acute sense for physiognomy, one should take
special note of those verdicts which preceded a closer
acquaintance and were therefore genuine. For the
face of a man is the exact impression of what he is;
and if he deceives us, that is our fault, not his.
What a man says, on the other hand, is what he thinks,
more often what he has learned, or it may be even,
what he pretends to think. And besides this,
when we talk to him, or even hear him talking to others,
we pay no attention to his physiognomy proper.
It is the underlying substance, the fundamental datum,
and we disregard it; what interests us is its pathognomy,
its play of feature during conversation. This,
however, is so arranged as to turn the good side upwards.
When Socrates said to a young man
who was introduced to him to have his capabilities
tested, “Talk in order that I may see you,”
if indeed by “seeing” he did not simply
mean “hearing,” he was right, so far as
it is only in conversation that the features and especially
the eyes become animated, and the intellectual resources
and capacities set their mark upon the countenance.
This puts us in a position to form a provisional notion
of the degree and capacity of intelligence; which was
in that case Socrates’ aim. But in this
connection it is to be observed, firstly, that the
rule does not apply to moral qualities, which lie
deeper, and in the second place, that what from an
objective point of view we gain by the clearer development
of the countenance in conversation, we lose from a
subjective standpoint on account of the personal relation
into which the speaker at once enters in regard to
us, and which produces a slight fascination, so that,
as explained above, we are not left impartial observers.
Consequently from the last point of view we might
say with greater accuracy, “Do not speak in order
that I may see you.”
For to get a pure and fundamental
conception of a man’s physiognomy, we must observe
him when he is alone and left to himself. Society
of any kind and conversation throw a reflection upon
him which is not his own, generally to his advantage;
as he is thereby placed in a state of action and reaction
which sets him off. But alone and left to himself,
plunged in the depths of his own thoughts and sensations,
he is wholly himself, and a penetrating eye for physiognomy
can at one glance take a general view of his entire
character. For his face, looked at by and in itself,
expresses the keynote of all his thoughts and endeavors,
the arrêt irrevocable, the irrevocable decree
of his destiny, the consciousness of which only comes
to him when he is alone.
The study of physiognomy is one of
the chief means of a knowledge of mankind, because
the cast of a man’s face is the only sphere in
which his arts of dissimulation are of no avail, since
these arts extended only to that play of feature which
is akin to mimicry. And that is why I recommend
such a study to be undertaken when the subject of it
is alone and given up to his own thoughts, and before
he is spoken to: and this partly for the reason
that it is only in such a condition that inspection
of the physiognomy pure and simple is possible, because
conversation at once lets in a pathognomical element,
in which a man can apply the arts of dissimulation
which he has learned: partly again because personal
contact, even of the very slightest kind, gives a
certain bias and so corrupts the judgment of the observer.
And in regard to the study of physiognomy
in general, it is further to be observed that intellectual
capacity is much easier of discernment than moral
character. The former naturally takes a much more
outward direction, and expresses itself not only in
the face and the play of feature, but also in the
gait, down even to the very slightest movement.
One could perhaps discriminate from behind between
a blockhead, a fool and a man of genius. The
blockhead would be discerned by the torpidity and
sluggishness of all his movements: folly sets
its mark upon every gesture, and so does intellect
and a studious nature. Hence that remark of La
Bruyere that there is nothing so slight, so simple
or imperceptible but that our way of doing it enters
in and betrays us: a fool neither comes nor goes,
nor sits down, nor gets up, nor holds his tongue,
nor moves about in the same way as an intelligent man.
(And this is, be it observed by way of parenthesis,
the explanation of that sure and certain instinct
which, according to Helvetius, ordinary folk
possess of discerning people of genius, and of getting
out of their way.)
The chief reason for this is that,
the larger and more developed the brain, and the thinner,
in relation to it, the spine and nerves, the greater
is the intellect; and not the intellect alone, but
at the same time the mobility and pliancy of all the
limbs; because the brain controls them more immediately
and resolutely; so that everything hangs more upon
a single thread, every movement of which gives a precise
expression to its purpose.
This is analogous to, nay, is immediately
connected with the fact that the higher an animal
stands in the scale of development, the easier it
becomes to kill it by wounding a single spot.
Take, for example, batrachia: they are slow,
cumbrous and sluggish in their movements; they are
unintelligent, and, at the same time, extremely tenacious
of life; the reason of which is that, with a very
small brain, their spine and nerves are very thick.
Now gait and movement of the arms are mainly functions
of the brain; our limbs receive their motion and every
little modification of it from the brain through the
medium of the spine.
This is why conscious movements fatigue
us: the sensation of fatigue, like that of pain,
has its seat in the brain, not, as people commonly
suppose, in the limbs themselves; hence motion induces
sleep.
On the other hand those motions which
are not excited by the brain, that is, the unconscious
movements of organic life, of the heart, of the lungs,
etc., go on in their course without producing
fatigue. And as thought, equally with motion,
is a function of the brain, the character of the brain’s
activity is expressed equally in both, according to
the constitution of the individual; stupid people
move like lay-figures, while every joint of an intelligent
man is eloquent.
But gesture and movement are not nearly
so good an index of intellectual qualities as the
face, the shape and size of the brain, the contraction
and movement of the features, and above all the eye, from
the small, dull, dead-looking eye of a pig up through
all gradations to the irradiating, flashing eyes of
a genius.
The look of good sense and prudence,
even of the best kind, differs from that of genius,
in that the former bears the stamp of subjection to
the will, while the latter is free from it.
And therefore one can well believe
the anecdote told by Squarzafichi in his life of Petrarch,
and taken from Joseph Brivius, a contemporary of the
poet, how once at the court of the Visconti, when Petrarch
and other noblemen and gentlemen were present, Galeazzo
Visconti told his son, who was then a mere boy (he
was afterwards first Duke of Milan), to pick out the
wisest of the company; how the boy looked at them all
for a little, and then took Petrarch by the hand and
led him up to his father, to the great admiration
of all present. For so clearly does nature set
the mark of her dignity on the privileged among mankind
that even a child can discern it.
Therefore, I should advise my sagacious
countrymen, if ever again they wish to trumpet about
for thirty years a very commonplace person as a great
genius, not to choose for the purpose such a beerhouse-keeper
physiognomy as was possessed by that philosopher, upon
whose face nature had written, in her clearest characters,
the familiar inscription, “commonplace person.”
But what applies to intellectual capacity
will not apply to moral qualities, to character.
It is more difficult to discern its physiognomy, because,
being of a metaphysical nature, it lies incomparably
deeper.
It is true that moral character is
also connected with the constitution, with the organism,
but not so immediately or in such direct connection
with definite parts of its system as is intellectual
capacity.
Hence while everyone makes a show
of his intelligence and endeavors to exhibit it at
every opportunity, as something with which he is in
general quite contented, few expose their moral qualities
freely, and most people intentionally cover them up;
and long practice makes the concealment perfect.
In the meantime, as I explained above, wicked thoughts
and worthless efforts gradually set their mask upon
the face, especially the eyes. So that, judging
by physiognomy, it is easy to warrant that a given
man will never produce an immortal work; but not that
he will never commit a great crime.